Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T15:14:30.877Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Substantive/Procedural Distinction: Law's Solution to the Problem of Jus Cogens in a World of Sovereign States

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

This Article uses social systems theory to examine the increased reliance on a distinction between substantive and procedural international law to resolve cases involving a conflict between jus cogens and state immunity. This presents the problem of an evolutionary relationship between international law and the complex differentiation of world society. International law is shown to be structurally related to the segmentary differentiation of states that underwrites modern society's functional differentiation. At the same time, it is shown to be structurally related to the increasing formulation of global norms that result from advanced functional differentiation. The Article then turns to examining the substantive/procedural law distinction as a solution to this dual functional reference problem. The distinction is shown to not only maintain the autopoiesis of law under these difficult conditions, but to also secure law's continued functional relevance in globalized society. This functionalist perspective is used to expose differences in the self-description and operation of international law, to point out how law has been blind to its own coding, and to highlight opportunities for programming law to respond in a more constructive manner to the challenges of globalization.

Type
International Law
Copyright
Copyright © 2018 by German Law Journal, Inc. 

References

1 Verdross published an article in 1937 introducing the option of a positive legal limitation on the freedom of contract which nation-states enjoy in making treaties, and could realize this concept further when he was elected a member of the International Law Commission in 1957. Alfred von Verdross, Forbidden Treaties in International Law, 31 Am. J. Int'l L. 4, 571–77 (1937). Once elected as Special Rapporteur in 1953, Lauterpacht submitted a draft provision suggesting that a treaty is void if its performance involves any violation of the overriding principles of international law, Special Rapporteur Hersch Latuerpacht, The Ordre Public International, Law of Treaties: Report by Special Rapporteur, 2 Yearbook of the International Law Commission, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/63.Google Scholar

2 See Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties arts. 53, 64, and 66(a), May 23, 1969.Google Scholar

3 This is not to overlook the fragmented and polycentric nature of global governance, whereby a multiplicity of non-state actors also contribute to achieving collective goals. See, e.g., Rosenau, James, Change, Complexity and Governance in a Globalizing Space, in Debating Governance 172 (Jon Pierre ed., 2000) (on such a broad definition of global governance). Nevertheless, the engagement of nation-states clearly remains essential to achieving lasting solutions to many global problems. Moreover, one must take account of the continued semantic value of the nation-state as a subject in the modern international legal system.Google Scholar

4 As per Lord Hoffmann of the British Supreme Court, the “same approach cannot be adopted in international law, which is based upon the common consent of nations,” in Jones v. The United Kingdom of Saudi Arabia, House of Lords, [2006] UKHL 26, para. 63., but cf. Hersch Lauterpacht, International Law, Vol. 1, 69 (1970). Lauterpacht's ever relevant, but unrealized, hope for the role of general principles in the development of international law beyond pure consensualism towards the will of states.Google Scholar

5 This is most notably expressed in the International Court of Justice's recent case, Jurisdictional Immunities of the State (Ger. v. Italy, Greece intervening), I.C.J. Rep. 2012 (hereinafter Jurisdictional Immunities).Google Scholar

6 See Talmon, Stefan, Jus Cogens after Germany v. Italy: Substantive and procedural Rules Distinguished, 25 Leiden J. of Int'l L. 986 (2012).Google Scholar

7 See Tomuschat, Christian, The Case of Germany v. Italy before the ICJ, in Immunities in the Age of Global Constitutionalism 88 (Anne Peters et al. eds., 2014).Google Scholar

8 See Ciaccio, Pietro Di, A Torturer's Manifesto? Impunity through Immunity in Jones v. The Kingdom of Saudi Arabia, 30 Sydney L. Rev. 557 (2008).Google Scholar

9 See Orakhelashvili, Alexander, Peremptory Norms as an Aspect of Constitutionalisation in the International Legal System, in The Dynamics of Constitutionalism in the Age of Globalisation 165 (Morley Frishman & Sam Muller eds., 2010).Google Scholar

10 See McGregor, Lorna, Torture and State Immunity: Deflecting Impunity, Distorting Sovereignty, 18 Eur. J. Int'l L. 911 (2007).Google Scholar

11 See Besner, Jennifer & Attaran, Amir, Civil Liability in Canada's Courts for Torture Committed Abroad: The Unsatisfactory Interpretation of the State Immunity Act 1985, 16 Tort L. Rev. 164 (2008).Google Scholar

12 See Report of the Study Group of the International Law Commission on the Fragmentation of International Law, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/L.628, April 13, 2006. Nevertheless, the token mention there of “functional differentiation,” and the hasty conclusion there that fragmentation was business as usual for a discipline which had always dealt with the institutional and political diversity of international society suggested a limited engagement with the sociological theory which had generated the original insight. Id., paras. 7, 17.Google Scholar

13 See Nobles, Richard & Schiff, David, A Sociology of Jurisprudence 47 (2006).Google Scholar

14 This development and its problems were eloquently expressed by the president of the International Court of Justice in his declaration in the Nuclear Weapons Opinion. See Declaration of President Bedjaoui, Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, 1996 I.C.J. Rep. 270–71.Google Scholar

15 See Oeter, Stefan, International Law and General Systems Theory, 44 German Yearbook Int'l L. 93 (2001).Google Scholar

16 See Fuller, Lon L., Positivism and Fidelity to Law—A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 631 (1958) (borrowing Fuller's phrase).Google Scholar

17 See Habermas, Jürgen, Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozialtechnologie? Eine Auseinandersetzung mit Niklas Luhmann, in Theorie Der Gessellschaft Oder Sozialtechnologie 157 (Jürgen Habermas & Niklas Luhmann eds., 1975).Google Scholar

18 See D'Amato, Anthony, International Law as an Autopoietic System, in Developments of International Law in Treaty Making 335 (Rudiger Wolfrum & Volker Röben eds., 2005); see also Oeter, supra note 15, at 84.Google Scholar

19 See Luhmann, Niklas, Social Systems 9 (1995). And, in turn, the operational closure achieved through the recursive linking of system specific communications serves as the “condition of possibility for openness.” Id. at 447.Google Scholar

20 On the role of this functional method which corresponds to systems theory, see id. at 53.Google Scholar

21 See, Durkheim, Emile, The Division of Labour in Society (1964); Shmuel Eisenstadt, Social Change, Differentiation and Evolution, 29 Am. Soc. Rev. (1964); Georg Simmel, The Sociology of Georg Simmel (Kurt Wolff ed., 1964); Max Weber, Economy and Society (1968).Google Scholar

22 See Luhmann, Niklas, Theory of Society, Vol. 2, 1013 (2013).Google Scholar

23 See id. Luhmann also includes differentiation in terms of a center and a periphery which allows for asymmetric relations between different social spheres. This differentiation form is not immediately relevant to the present study, except to note that it allows for the transcendence of the principle of segmentation; see, e.g., Wallerstein, Immanuel, The Modern World-System I: Capitalist Agriculture and the Origins of the European World-Economy in the Sixteenth Century (1974). Drawing upon Foucault, Kjaer also adds another differentiation form, namely “territorial differentiation,” to imply a “construction of a limited and coherent geographical space which is clearly demarcated from other geographical spaces within the framework of the modern nation-states,” see Kjaer, Poul, Constitutionalism in the Global Realm: A Sociological Approach 21 (2014). While that may seem relevant to the present study, it only obfuscates matters unnecessarily. What is most relevant for present purposes is the sovereign equality of nation-states, and that is most adequately represented by the segmentary principle of differentiation.Google Scholar

24 Id. at 13, 33.Google Scholar

26 See Luhmann, Niklas, The Differentiation of Society, 2 Can. J. Soc. 35 (1977).Google Scholar

27 See Luhmann, supra note 22, at 11.Google Scholar

28 See Albert, Mathias, Barry Buzan & Michael Zurn, Introduction: Differentiation Theory and International Relations, in Bringing Sociology to International Relations: World Politics as Differentiation Theory 3 (Mathias Albert et al. eds., 2013).Google Scholar

29 This was somewhat neglected by Luhmann. As Munch points out, Luhmann “deals too little” with the complex integration of functional and segmentary differentiation in world society. See Munch, Richard, Functional, Segmentary and Stratificatory Differentiation of World Society, in Bringing Sociology to International Relations: World Politics as Differentiation Theory 76 (Albert et al. eds., 2013).Google Scholar

30 See, e.g., Wengler, Wilhelm, Völkerrecht, Vol. 1, 107 (1964); Wolfgang Preiser, History of the Law of Nations: Ancient Times to 1648, in II Encyclopedia of Public International Law 722 (Rudolf Bernhardt ed., 1995).Google Scholar

31 See Grewe, Wilhelm, The Epochs of International Law 5160 (2000).Google Scholar

32 See, e.g., Gross, Leo, The Peace of Westphalia 1648-1948, 42 Am. J. of Int'l Law 28 (1948); Hans Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace 294 (1985); Helmut Steinberger, Sovereignty, in IV Encyclopedia of Public International Law (Rudolf Bernhardt ed., 1987).Google Scholar

33 See Osiander, Andreas, Sovereignty, International Relations, and the Westphalian Myth, 55 Int'l Org. 251, 287 (2001); Benno Teschke, The Myth of 1648: Class, Geopolitics and the Making of Modern International Relations (2003).Google Scholar

34 See Oppenheim, Lassa, International Law 44 (1905).Google Scholar

35 See Luhmann, supra note 26, at 45.Google Scholar

36 See, e.g., Trevor-Roper, Hugh, The Crisis of the Seventeenth Century: Religion, the Reformation & Social Change (1967) (Hugh Trevor-Roper's account of the crisis of hierarchical authority and the demise of cities).Google Scholar

37 Luhmann, supra note 26 at 45.Google Scholar

38 See Luhmann, Niklas, A Sociological Theory of Law 148 (2013).Google Scholar

39 See Luhmann, Niklas, The Representation of Society Within Society, in Political Theory in the Welfare State 1120 (1990).Google Scholar

40 Most notably with law, see Luhmann, Niklas, Law as a Social System 230273 (2004).Google Scholar

41 Luhmann's theory of the evolution of the modern state in this respect is complex and there is little space to explore it here. In short, Luhmann claimed that the development relied upon the evolution of the institutions of parliamentary democracy, not as the actualization of consensus, but rather upon the reflexive mechanisms which allowed the state to construct itself as a “formula of unity for the self-description of the political system,” and to construct its legitimacy as a “formula for contingency.” See Luhmann, Niklas, Die Politik Der Gesselschaft 125 (2000); Niklas Luhmann, State and Politics: Towards a Semantics of the Self-description of Political Systems, in Political Theory in the Welfare State 128 (1990).Google Scholar

42 For accounts of such segmentary differentiation, see, e.g., Luhmann, Niklas, Globalization or World Society?, 7 Int'l Rev. of Soc. 72 (1997); Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics 95 (1979); Mathias Albert & Barry Buzan, Differentiation: A Sociological Approach to International Relations Theory, 16 Eur. J. Int'l Relations 318 (2010); Munch, supra note 29, at 71.Google Scholar

43 See Viola, Lora Anne, Stratifactory Differentiation as a Constitutive Principle of the International System, in Bringing Sociology to International Relations: World Politics as Differentiation Theory 113 (Mathias Albert et al. eds., 2013).Google Scholar

44 See Luhmann, supra note 38, at 259.Google Scholar

45 See Kjaer, Poul, The Concept of the Political in the Concept of Transnational Constitutionalism: A Sociological Perspective, in After Globalization: New Patterns of Conflict and Their Sociological and Legal Reconstruction 4 (Christian Jorges & Tommi Ralli eds., 2011)Google Scholar

46 See Luhmann, supra note 26, at 41 (emphasis added).Google Scholar

47 See Scott, James Brown, The Spanish Origin of International Law: Francisco de Vitoria and His Law of Nations (1934); Grewe, supra note 31, at 25; J.A. Fernández-Santamaria, The State, War and Peace: Spanish Political Thought in the Renaissance 1516–1559, 61 (1977).Google Scholar

48 According to Parry's account of the Age of Reconnaissance, the two principle motives which impelled Europeans to venture overseas in the sixteenth century were “acquisitiveness and religious zeal.” See Parry, John, The Age of Reconnaissance: Discovery, Exploration and Settlement from 1450 to 1650, 19 (1963).Google Scholar

49 See de Vitoria, Francisco, De Indis Relectio Prior (John Pawley Bate trans., 1917); see also Grewe, supra note 31, at 145.Google Scholar

50 See also Anghie, Anthony, Imperialism, Sovereignty, and the Making of International Law 1328 (2004); cf. Luhmann, supra note 26, at 40 (“If every individual is acknowledged as choosing or not choosing a religious commitment; and if everybody can buy everything and pursue every occupation, given the necessary resources, then the whole system shifts in the direction of functional differentiation.”).Google Scholar

51 See Onuma, Yasauki, When was the Law of International Society Born? An Inquiry into the History of International Law from an Intercivilizational Perspective, 2 J. The Hist. Int'l L. 25 (2000); see also, Fernández-Santamaria, supra note 47, at 84–85.Google Scholar

52 See Fernández-Santamaria, supra note 47, at 62; Anghie, supra note 50, at 16, 24.Google Scholar

53 See Koskenniemi, Martti, Empire and International Law: The Real Spanish Contribution, 61 U. of Toronto L. J. 14 (2011).Google Scholar

54 See Borschberg, Peter, Hugo Grotius, The Portuguese, and Free Trade in the East Indies (2011).Google Scholar

55 See Grewe, supra note 31, at 149.Google Scholar

56 See id. at 119; Athena Efraim, Sovereign (In)equality in International Organizations 64 (1999).Google Scholar

57 See Bull, Hedley, The Importance of Grotius in International Relations, in Hugo Grotius and International Relations 75 (Hedley Bull et al. eds., 1992).Google Scholar

58 See Steinberger, supra note 32, at 504; Grewe, supra note 31, at 265.Google Scholar

59 See Thornhill, Chris, National Sovereignty and the Constitution of Transnational Law: A Sociological Approach to a Classical Antinomy, 3 Transnat'l Legal Theory 408 (2012).Google Scholar

60 See Grewe, supra note 31, at 13.Google Scholar

61 See Teubner, Gunter, A Constitutional Moment? The Logics of ‘Hit the Bottom’, in The Financial Crisis in Constitutional Perspective: The Dark Side of Functional Differentiation 14 (Poul Kjaer et al. eds., 2011).Google Scholar

62 See Luhmann, Niklas, Risk: A Sociological Theory (1993).Google Scholar

63 See Koskenniemi, Martti, What is International Law For?, in International Law 49 (Malcolm Evans ed., 2014).Google Scholar

64 See Pahuja, Sundhya, Decolonising International 40 (2011).Google Scholar

65 See Luhmann, supra note 40, at 469 (emphasis added).Google Scholar

66 See id. at 468.Google Scholar

67 See Luhmann, supra note 38.Google Scholar

68 See Koskenniemi, Martti, From Apology to Utopia (1989) (the most well-known example).Google Scholar

69 See Luhmann, Niklas, Ecological Communication 38 (1989).Google Scholar

70 See Luhmann, Niklas, Art as a Social System 186 (2000).Google Scholar

71 See Luhmann, Niklas, a Systems Theory of Religion 88 (2013).Google Scholar

72 Id. Though such a claim to universal validity is always precocious, as it is always open to functional equivalence.Google Scholar

73 See Luhmann, supra note 40, at 193.Google Scholar

74 See Trial of the Major War Criminals Before the International Military Tribunal, Vol. I 223 (Nüremberg, 1947) (https://www.loc.gov/rr/frd/Military_Law/pdf/NT_Vol-I.pdf).Google Scholar

75 See R. v. Bow Street Metropolitan Stipendiary Magistrate, ex parte Pinochet Ugarte (No. 3) (1999) 2 All E.R. 97. It is often overlooked that the House of Lord's decision to deny the former head of state immunity ratione materiae was based not on a violation of jus cogens, but rather on the authority of the 1984 Torture Convention which was incorporated into English law by the Criminal Justice Act 1988; see id. at 114 (as per Lord Browne-Wilkinson, “the Torture Convention did provide what was missing.”); see also Shelton, Dinah, Normative Hierarchy in International Law, 100 Am. J. Int'l L. 316 (2006).Google Scholar

76 See R. v. Bow Street Metropolitan Stipendiary Magistrate at 166 (Lord Hutton).Google Scholar

77 See R. v. Bow Street Metropolitan Stipendiary Magistrate at 178 (Lord Millett).Google Scholar

78 See Weatherall, Thomas, Jus Cogens and Sovereign Immunity: Reconciling Divergence in Contemporary Jurisprudence, 46 Geo. J. of Int'l L. 1175 (2015).Google Scholar

79 See Fox, Hazel & Webb, Philippa, The Law of State Immunity 26 (2015).Google Scholar

80 See Bouzari v. Islamic Republic of Iran, [2002] 124 ILR 427, aff'd, [2004] 243 DLR (4th) 406, para. 91 (Can. Ont. Sup. Ct.). Municipal courts have generally rejected civil claims for jus cogens violations on the basis that they come too close to “subjecting one state to the jurisdiction of another.” Nevertheless, under the normative rupture of globalized society, neither practice nor logic appear to support the distinction of criminal proceedings as relating only to prosecution of the individual and civil proceedings as encroaching upon the sovereign immunity of the state. Special Rapporteur Kolodkin, Roman A., Second Report on Immunity of State Officials from Foreign Criminal Jurisdiction, International Law Commission, ¶ 66 U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/631 (2010). Recently, a U.S. District Court denied the former Prime Minister of Somalia immunity in a civil suit for violations of jus cogens in Yousuf v. Samantar, 699 F.3d 763, 776 (4th Circ. 2012), ultimately leaving the law in this area in a “state of flux.” Jones and Others v. The United Kingdom, Eur. Ct. H.R., para. 213 (2014).Google Scholar

81 See Fox & Webb, supra note 79, at 38.Google Scholar

82 See The reference to the World Court is commonly used with little reflection. It appears, though, that the practice is based on a predominant statist concept of world society at the time of the Court's foundation. For example, according to Rosenne, the moniker is warranted by the recognition of the Court as the principal judicial organ of the United Nations, the fact that all members of the United Nations are ipso facto parties to the Statute of the Court, and the fact that non-members states can also be parties before the Court. Shabatai Rosenne, The World Court and How It Works 23 (Terry Gill ed., 2003). Nevertheless, the label is used differently here to highlight that, despite the statist foundations of the term, the Court must, in the absence of alternative legal structures, strive at an operational level to be a principal institution for expectations not only of sovereign states, but of a much broader world society.Google Scholar

83 See Al-Adsani v. United Kingdom, App. No. 35763/97, para. 61 (2002).Google Scholar

84 Id. at para. 48.Google Scholar

85 Rwanda contested the Court's jurisdiction based on its reservation to Article IX of the 1948 Genocide Convention. See Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo (Dem. Rep. Congo v. Rwanda), Jurisdiction and Admissibility, Judgment, I.C.J. Rep. 2006 (hereinafter Armed Activities).Google Scholar

86 Id. at para. 64.Google Scholar

88 See Jones v. Saudi Arabia [2006] UKHL 26, para. 24.Google Scholar

89 Id. at paras. 24, 44.Google Scholar

90 See Fox, Hazel, The Law of State Immunity 525 (2002).Google Scholar

91 See Jurisdictional Immunities, supra note 5.Google Scholar

92 Id. at para. 91.Google Scholar

93 Id. at para. 93.Google Scholar

94 See Jurisdictional Immunities, supra note 5.Google Scholar

96 Id. at para. 95.Google Scholar

97 Id. at para. 96.Google Scholar

98 “While jurisdictional immunity is procedural in nature, criminal responsibility is a question of substantive law. Jurisdictional immunity may well bar prosecution for a certain period or for certain offences; it cannot exonerate the person to whom it applies from all criminal responsibility.” See Arrest Warrant of April 11, 2000 (Dem. Rep. Congo v. Belgium), Judgment, I.C.J. Rep. para 60 2002.Google Scholar

99 See Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, Andreas, Niklas Luhmann: Law, Justice, Society 74 (2010).Google Scholar

100 See Luhmann, supra note 69, at 37.Google Scholar

101 See Weatherall, supra note 78, at 1152.Google Scholar

102 See Jones v. Saudi Arabia, supra note 88; Talmon, supra note 6, at 980.Google Scholar

103 Luhmann sees paradoxes as creative, because “one has to try so hard to avoid and to conceal it.” See Luhmann, supra note 40, at 177.Google Scholar

104 See Fox, supra note 90.Google Scholar

105 See Luhmann, supra note 40, at 186.Google Scholar

106 See, e.g., Orakhelashvili, Alexander, Peremptory Norms in International Law 359 (2006).Google Scholar

107 See Luhmann, supra note 40, at 207.Google Scholar

108 Id. Google Scholar

109 Id. at 206.Google Scholar

110 On the relationship between function and code in relation to law, see Luhmann, id. at 294, and on this relationship in general, see Luhmann, supra note 22, at 90.Google Scholar

111 See Peters, Anne, Let Not Triepel Triumph—How to Make the Best Out of Sentenza No. 238 of the Italian Constitutional Court for a Global Legal Order, EJIL: Talk! (2014), https://www.ejiltalk.org/let-not-triepel-triumph-how-to-make-the-best-out-of-sentenza-no-238-of-the-italian-constitutional-court-for-a-global-legal-order-part-i/.Google Scholar

112 See, e.g., Armed Activities, supra note 85, at para. 64. Nonetheless, the Court's wording in the Jurisdictional Immunities case could be a careless reversal of this trend in that it was only prepared to assume for the sake of rhetoric that “the rules of the law of armed conflict which prohibit the murder of civilians in occupied territory, the deportation of civilian inhabitants to slave labor and the deportation of prisoners of war to slave labor are rules of jus cogens.” See Jurisdictional Immunities, supra note 5, at para. 93.Google Scholar

113 On this account of the function of law, see Luhmann, supra note 38.Google Scholar

114 See Luhmann, supra note 40, at 286.Google Scholar

115 See Weatherall, supra note 78, at 1152.Google Scholar

116 See Abi-Saab, Georges, The Third World and the Future of the International Legal Order, 29 Revue Egyptienne de Droit International 53 (1973).Google Scholar

117 See Brownlie, Ian, Discussion, in Change and Stability in International Law-Making 108, 110 (Antonio Cassese & Weiler, Joseph H. eds., 1988).Google Scholar

118 See D'Amato, Anthony, It's a Bird, It's a Plane, It's Jus Cogens, 6 Conn. J. Int'l L. 1 (1990).Google Scholar

119 See comments of Professor Jean D'Aspremont, Jus Cogens: A Social Construct Without Pedigree, Mississippi College School of Law, May 8, 2015 (“You are not really an international lawyer if you do not understand, and cannot deploy and make use of the doctrine of jus cogens.”), https://youtu.be/Np61Xq-JRRM.Google Scholar

120 See What Aristotle deemed the truly political, The Politics 1252a5-6 (Trevor Saunders ed., 1981).Google Scholar

121 See Nollkaemper, André, International Adjudication of Global Public Goods: The Intersection of Substance and Procedure, 23 Eur. J. Int'l L. 771 (2012).Google Scholar

122 See, e.g., Peters, Anne, Immune against Constitutionalization?, Immunities in the Age of Global Constitutionalism 18 (Anne Peters et al. eds., 2014).Google Scholar

123 See Cotterrell, Roger, Why Must Legal Ideas be Interpreted Sociologically?, 25 J.L. & Soc. 2, 182 (1998).Google Scholar

124 See Koskenniemi, Martti, The Methodology of International Law, Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law (2007).Google Scholar