Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T18:51:17.178Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Socio-Theoretically Based Legal Science and Critical Legal Studies: Points of Contract and Divergencies

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Where do American and German critiques of their respective “mainstream” legal traditions converge, and where do they diverge? When can the convergences be interpreted as common learning experiences with modern law, as insights into the futility of critical efforts, as indications for their correction? Which divergences are due to differences between the legal cultures and philosophical traditions? Where are they reactions to more specific socio-political constellations and particular structurings of the respective academic systems? From which projects can the “other side” gain new insights, or perhaps entirely new perspectives? Such questions inevitably arise from a volume devoted to German and American critical and socio-theoretical contributions to the discussion of legal theoretical fundamentals. Yet they demand too much from an individual author (at least this one), and their enumeration is intended to make clear the sort of difficulties they occasion and suggest how they might be fruitfully dealt with.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2011 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 Frankenberg, Gunter, supra in this volume.Google Scholar

2 Even beyond the participants of the Bremen Symposium; see Joachim Perels, Die Rechtstheorie auf dem Weg zur neuen BELIEBIGKEIT?, 307 (1987).Google Scholar

3 It is no accident that in the course of the German protest movement of the Sixties, jurists spread out in all directions at once to ransack Marxism, Critical Theory, Systems Theory, Critical Rationalism, and Analytical Philosophy, nor that the contributions of the CLS-movement bristle with a complete arsenal of “famous dead Europeans (and some living ones)”: James Boyle, Critical Legal Studies: A Young Person's Guide, 19 (1985) (Typescript); or that one does not shy from simultaneously claiming inspiration from several intellectually disparate currents for the same contribution (see, infra, A II 2 at note 45). Secondary analyses which examine the references of individual authors to specific theoretical projects and philosophies typically come to the conclusion that the practice of legal-critical analysis does not stick closely to the views found in their theoretical sources; see Brosnan, Donald F., Serious But Not Critical, 60 Southern California Law Review (So. Cal. L. Rev.) 259 (1987); Stick, John, Can Nihilism Be Pragmatic?, 100 Harvard Law Review (Harv. L. Rev.) 313 (1986).Google Scholar

4 See Schlegel, Johann Elias, supra in this volume as well as on Free Law infra 3, note 23.Google Scholar

5 Ulrich K. Preuss, Legalität und Pluralismus. Beiträge zum Verfassungsrecht der Bundesrepublik Deutschland (1973).Google Scholar

6 Id., 42.Google Scholar

7 This starting point then determines not only the confrontation with the constitutional theory of the Weimar Republic (Id., 65, 84), but also the understanding of the West German Basic Law (id., 91, 102). The later development and revision of the approach is evident from Ulrich K. Preuss, supra in this volume. See also Karl-Heinz Ladeur, supra in this volume (at note 29).Google Scholar

8 Probleme einer Theorie des Wirtschaftsrechts, in Wirtschaftsrecht als Kritik des Privatrechts. Beiträge zur Privat-und Wirtschaftsrechtstheorie, 9 (Heinz-Dieter Assmann & Gert Brüggemeier & Dieter Hart & Christian Joerges, 1980).Google Scholar

9 Id., 32.Google Scholar

10 Negt, Oskor, 10 Thesen zur marxistischen Rechtstheorie, in: Probleme der marxistischen Rechtstheorie, 10, 35 (Rottleuthner, Hubert ed., 1975).Google Scholar

11 The difficulties of the Marxist legal theory only vaguely referred to here have been pursued with patience and thoroughness by Rottleuthner, Marxistische und analytische Rechtstheorie, supra, note 10, 159.Google Scholar

12 See Brüggemeier, Gert, Vorstudien zu einer Wettbewerbsrechtstheorie. Untersuchungen zu den theoretischen Grundlagen eines sozialen Ordnungskonzepts, Diss. jur. (1974).Google Scholar

13 See Wiethölter, Rudolph, Materialisierungen und Prozeduralisierungen von Recht, in: Workshop zu Konzepten des postinterventionistischen Rechts, (ZERP Materialien, Heft 4), 25, 26 (Brüggemeier, Gert & Joerges, Christian eds., 1984). [English version: Materialisation and Proceduralisation in Modern Law, in Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State, 221, 222 (Teubner, Gunther ed., 1985)].Google Scholar

14 Der Begriff der politischen Beteiligung (1958), reprinted in: Kultur und Kritik. Verstreute Aufsätze, 9, (Jürgen Habermas 1973); Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit. Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft, Neuwied-Berlin (1962); Theorie und Praxis. Sozialphilosophische Studien (1963) - Again, one must not understand the influence in the sense of a hierarchy between philosophy as superior science and the individual disciplines as applied sciences. The difficulties of a reflexive social theory which wishes to comprehend its own emergence and anticipate its own application has been noted by jurists too (see Rudolph Wiethölter, Rechtswissenschaft in Kritik und als Kritik, (1971) [Studium Generale der J. Gutenberg-Universität, 1973]).Google Scholar

15 Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriß der verstehenden Soziologie, 496, 503 (Winckelmann, Johannes ed., 1972).Google Scholar

16 See Wiethölter, Rudolph, Bürgerliches Recht, in: Handlexikon zur Rechtswissenschaft, 47, 50 (Görlitz, Axel ed. 1972); see Habermas, Jürgen, Wie ist Legitimität durch Legalität möglich, Kritische Justiz (KJ) 1, 7 (1987).Google Scholar

17 Habermas distanced himself early from “immanent critique”, a form so characteristic for the “classical” Critical Theory (see Der Begriff der politschen Beteiligung, supra, note 14, 53); this is treated sytematically by Axel Honneth, Von Adorno zu Habermas. Zum Gestaltwandel kritischer Gesellschaftstheorie, in Sozialforschung als Kritik. Zum sozialwissenschaftlichen Potential der Kritischen Theorie, 87 (Wolfgang Bonß & Honneth, Axel eds., 1982); Seyla Benhabib, Die Moderne und die Aporien der Kritischen Theorie, id., 127, 151.Google Scholar

18 Habermas, Jürgen, Überlegungen zum evolutionären Stellenwert des modernen Rechts, in Zur Rekonstruktion des historischen Materialismus, 260, 265 (Habermas, Jürgen ed., 1976); see Habermas, Jürgen, Wie ist Legitimität durch Legalität möglich?, supra, note 16, 8 - In Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns (Vol. 2: Zur Kritik der funktionalistischen Vernunft), 1981, 229, Habermas expanded on these statements: With its implicit moral contents, formal law corresponded to the replacement of religious and metaphysical world images by post-conventional structures of consciousness; this anchoring in the process of rationalization of the lifeworld not only belongs to the developmental conditions but also to the pre-conditions for the preservation of formal-legal attainments.Google Scholar

19 On the dualism of law as “medium” and “institution” see, infra, B I 3 at note 97 and C I 1 at note 146.Google Scholar

20 Habermas, Jürgen, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns (Vol. 2), supra, note 18, 527.Google Scholar

21 Habermas, Jürgen, Wie ist Legitimität durch Legalität möglich?, supra, note 16, 10.Google Scholar

22 Habermas, Jürgen, supra, note 19.Google Scholar

23 Gnaeus Flavius (alias Hermann Kantorowicz), Der Kampf um die Rechtswissenschaft, 7 (1906).Google Scholar

24 Regina Ogorek, Richterkönig oder Subsumtionsautomat? Zur Justiztheorie des 19. Jahrhunderts, (1986).Google Scholar

25 Id., 39-169.Google Scholar

26 Ogorek, supra, note 24, 170279.Google Scholar

27 Ogorek, supra, note 24, 280367.Google Scholar

28 Ogorek, supra, note 24, 273.Google Scholar

29 See Fraenkel, Ernst, Zur Soziologie der Klassenjustiz, 28 (1927). Google Scholar

30 See, supra, 1 at note 7.Google Scholar

31 Habermas, Jürgen, Überlegungen zum evolutionären Stellenwert des modernen Rechts (note 18), 267 and supra 2, note 17.Google Scholar

32 See the self-critical considerations in Günther Frankenberg & Ulrich Rödel, Von der Volkssouveränität zum Minderheitenschutz. Die Freiheit politischer Kommunikation im Verfassungsstaat (1981) 9 as well as Barbara Freitag, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns und genetische Psychologie. Ein Dialog zwischen Jürgen Habermas und Jean Piaget, 35 Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie (ZfSS) 555 (1983).Google Scholar

33 Unger, Roberto M., Law in Modern Society. Toward a Criticism of Social Theory, 204 (1976).Google Scholar

34 Horwitz, infra, note 44, 203.Google Scholar

35 Kennedy, Duncan, Legal Formality, 2 J. Legal Stud. 351 (1973).Google Scholar

36 Kennedy, Duncan, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976); The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries, 28 Buffalo Law Review 205 (1979); Toward an Historical Understanding of Legal Consciousness: The Case of Classical Legal Thought in America, 1850-1940, in 3 Research in Law and Sociology 3 (Spitzer, Steven ed., 1980).Google Scholar

37 Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, id., 1687-1690.Google Scholar

38 Legal Formality, supra, note 36, 359; Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1754.Google Scholar

39 Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 17451748.Google Scholar

40 Legal Formality, supra, note 36, 361363.Google Scholar

41 See the often-cited analysis of Roberto Unger, Knowledge and Politics, 29-144 (1975).Google Scholar

42 See the references in Robert W. Gordon, New Developments in Legal Theory, in: The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique, 281, 284-289 (Kairys, David ed., 1982); Boyle, James, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social Thought, 133 University of Pennsylvania Law Review (U. Pa. L. Rev.) 687, 721-735 (1985) as well as the compilation of (at least temporarily) Marxist inspired authors of the CLS-Movement by Alan Hunt, The Theory of Critical Legal Studies, 6 Oxford J. of Legal Studies 1, 10 (1986) note 26.Google Scholar

43 See the references in Kennedy, David, Critical Theory, Structuralism and Contemporary Legal Scholarship, 21 New England Law Review (New England L. Rev.) 209, 244- 248 (1985-86) - Naturally, one can find close similarities transcending individual or selective receptions, if one takes an abstract enough viewpoint. Thus Jeffrey A. Standen (Note, Critical Legal Studies as an Anti-Positivist Phenomenon, 27 Virginia Law Review 983 (1986)) focuses on the anti-positivism, the “anti- constructivism” and the utopian motives of the Frankfurt School, in order to support his thesis that the CLS movement imported German metaphysics (!) into the US (998). On the other hand, the advice of European authors to integrate refinements of the theorem of the “relative autonomy” of the law (See Hunt, id., 37) or to recall the concept of critique of the early Horkheimer (see Roger Cotterrell, Critique and Law: The Problematic Legacy of the Frankfurt School, Tidskrift foer Raettssociologi 3, 1 (1986)) hardly arouse interest.Google Scholar

44 Horwitz, Morton J., The Rise of Legal Formalism, 19 American Journal of Legal History (Am. J. Legal Hist.) 251 (1975); The Transformation of American Law, 1780-1860 (1977).Google Scholar

45 See the critique in Gordon, Robert W., Critical Legal Histories, 36 Stanford Law Review (Stan. L. Rev.) 57, 79, 9698, 100-102 (1984) as well as the more detailed review of David Sugarman, British Journal of Law and Society 297, 303-308 (1980).Google Scholar

46 See Kennedy, supra, note 35 - The explicit retraction of the positions described here doesn't change this influence, especially when the retraction contains no distancing from the history of its impact (See Peter Gabel & Duncan Kennedy, Roll Over Beethoven, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 1, 15, 17, 24, 43 (1984)) and Kennedy repeated the retracted statements a little later in modified form: Freedom and Constraint in Adjudication: A Critical Phenomenology, 36 Legal, J. Ed. 518, 551 (1986).Google Scholar

47 Kennedy, Duncan, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1712; see The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries, supra, note 36, 210.Google Scholar

48 One frequently encounters this reproach: Peter Goodrich, Law and Modernity, 49 The Modern Law Review (The Modern L. Rev.) 545, 548 (1986) (“superficial ecclecticism”); Hunt, supra, note 42, 3 (“jumbled, incoherent eclecticism”); Koen Raes, Van juridisch relisme tot kritische rechtstheorie. The Critical Legal Studies Movement in de verenigde staten, 777, 780 (1987) (“ongestoord ecclecticisme”). Nevertheless: the censure of Kennedy is really directed at theoretical traditions, which no analysis of modern law could simply “transpose”, and the confession that the confrontation with those traditions has left its traces behind says little about the qualities of the product that emerges from that confrontation.Google Scholar

49 Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1738.Google Scholar

50 Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1688.Google Scholar

51 Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 17281737.Google Scholar

52 Kennedy, Legal Formality, supra, note 35.Google Scholar

53 Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1712.Google Scholar

54 Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 17171722.Google Scholar

55 On the dating of this epoch, see Kennedy, Toward a Historical Understanding of Legal Consciousness, supra, note 36, 23.Google Scholar

56 Early attempts at greater specification read as follows: “Consciousness refers to the total Contents of a Mind, including images of the Self, of emotions, goals and values, and theories about the Self … Legal consciousness refers to the particular form of consciousness that characterizes the legal profession as a social group, at a particular moment” (Kennedy, Toward a Historical Understanding of Legal Consciousness, supra, note 36, 23). “… a defining characteristic of Classical legal thought was the assimilation of a great deal of law to a single subsystem dominated by the concept of power absolute within its judicially delineated sphere. A second defining characteristic of Classicism, in contrast to pre-Classical and modern thinking, was the claim that very abstract propositions were nonetheless operative” (Kennedy, Toward a Historical Understanding of Legal Consciousness, supra, note 36, 21).Google Scholar

57 Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1685; see The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries, supra, note 36, 212 and most recently Freedom and Constraint in Adjudication, supra, note 46, 548554.Google Scholar

58 Kennedy, The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries, supra, note 36, 210.Google Scholar

59 Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1717, see 1722.Google Scholar

60 See, infra, B II 2, note 114.Google Scholar

61 Unger's critique of legal formalism proceeds (as does Kennedy's) from the contradiction and thereby resulting infeasibility of liberal theories of justice, the separation of law and law application (Unger, Knowledge and Politics, supra, note 41, 67-100). But Unger's reconstruction of the connections of legal theory, political theory and the “psychology” of liberalism aims at a new social theory which overcomes the antinomies of “theory and fact”, “reason and desire”, and “rules and values” (see also the references infra, C II 1).Google Scholar

62 The prominence of Derrida is a phenomena in itself; see, e.g.: Frug, Gerald E., The Ideology of Bureaucracy in American Law, 97 Harv. L. Rev. 1276, 1286-1292 (1984); Dalton, Clare, An Essay in the Deconstruction of Contract Doctrine, 94 Yale Law Journal (Yale L. J.) 999, 1007-1009 (1985); Peller, Gary, The Metaphysics of American Law, 73 California Law Review (Cal. L. Rev.) 1151 (1985); Leubsdorf, John, Deconstructing the Constitution, 40 Stan. L. Rev. 181 (1987); Balkin, Jack M., Deconstructive Practice and Legal Theory, 96 Yale L. J. 743 (1987); more comprehensively: Heller, Thomas C., Structuralism and Critique, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 127, 155-172, 182-197 (1984); Kennedy, supra, note 43, 271289.Google Scholar

63 Balkin, Jack M., id., 744-755, 761.Google Scholar

64 E.g. Kennedy, David, The Turn to Interpretation, 58 So. Cal. L. Rev. 251 (1985).Google Scholar

65 E.g. Frug, supra, note 62; Dalton, supra, note 62.Google Scholar

66 Leubsdorf, supra, note 62.Google Scholar

67 Peller, supra, note 62; Balkin, supra, note 62.Google Scholar

68 Peller, supra, note 62, 1153-1158, 1181-1191.Google Scholar

69 Balkin, supra, note 62, 763.Google Scholar

70 Balkin, supra, 785.Google Scholar

71 See Rottleuthner, Hubert, Theories of Legal Evolution: Between Empiricism and Philosophy of History, Rechtstheorie (Beiheft 9), 217 (1986); Hubert Rottleuthner, Aspekte der Rechtsentwicklung in Deutschland, 206 (1985).Google Scholar

72 Winckelmann, supra, note 15, 504513.Google Scholar

73 See the analysis (widely read in its day) from Wolfgang Müller & Christel Neusüß, Die Sozialstaatsillusion, Sozialistische Politik, 4 (1970), as well as the overview in Heinz-Dieter Assmann, Wirtschaftsrecht in der Mixed Economy. Auf der Suche nach einem Sozialmodell für das Wirtschaftsrecht, 240 (1980).Google Scholar

74 See, e.g., Sinzheimer, Hugo, Formen und Bedeutung der Betriebsräte, (1919); Die Zukunft der Arbeiterräte, (1919), both works reprinted in: Hugo Sinzheimer, Arbeitsrecht und Rechtssoziologie. Gesammelte Aufsätze und Reden, Vol. 1, 321 and 351 (Kahn-Freund, Otto & Ramm, Thielo eds., 1976), as well as the documentation in Gert Brüggemeier, Entwicklung des Rechts im organisierten Kapitalismus. Materialien zum Wirtschaftsrecht, Vol. 1: Von der Gründerzeit bis zur Weimarer Republik, 295-319 (1977) and David Kettler, Legal Reconstitution of the Welfare State: Latent Social Democratic Legacy, 21 Law & Soc. Rev. 9, 29-34 (1987).Google Scholar

75 See, e.g. Neumann, Franz L., über die Voraussetzungen und den Begriff einer Wirtschaftsverfassung (1931), reprinted in: Franz L. Neumann, Wirtschaft, Staat, Demokratie. Aufsätze 1930-1954, 76 (Söllner, Alfons ed., 1978).Google Scholar

76 Heller, Hermann, Rechtsstaat oder Diktatur?, (1930). From the wealth of secondary literature, see Ingeborg Maus, Hermann Heller und die Staatsrechtslehre der Bundesrepublik, in: Ingeborg Maus, Rechtstheorie und politische Theorie im Industriekapitalismus, 173 (1986).Google Scholar

77 Abendroth, Wolfgang, Zum Begriff des demokratischen und sozialen Rechtsstaates im Grundgesetz der Bundesrepublik Deutschland (1954), reprinted in: Franz L. Neumann, Antagonistische Gesellschaft und politische Demokratie. Aufsätze zur politischen Soziologie, 109 (1967).Google Scholar

78 But by no means exclusively: Thus Udo Reifner, Alternatives Wirtschaftsrecht am Beispiel der Verbraucherverschuldung, (1979), has developed a materialist-social state theory of civil law which in a “social interpretation, is intended to exploit symptomatic breaks of post-formal legal development” and lead to a “market economy compensating” use of law (66, 91); see the detailed examination in Christian Joerges, Verbraucherschutz als Rechtsproblem. Eine Untersuchung zum Stand der Theorie und zu den Entwicklungsperspektiven des Verbraucherrechts, 24-30, 37-40, 46-49, 52-55 (1981).Google Scholar

79 See particularly: Claus Offe, Strukturprobleme des kapitalistischen Staates, (1972).Google Scholar

80 See, e.g., Claus Offe, Competitive Party Democracy and the Keynesian Welfare State: Factor of Stability and Desintegration, 15 Policy Sciences 225 (1983); Korporatismus als System nichtstaatlicher Makrosteuerung, Geschichte und Gesellschaft 10 (1984), 234 - On terminology see also the references in Ulrich K. Preuss, The Concept of Rights in the Welfare State, in: Dilemmas of Law and the Welfare State, 151, 152-154 (Teubner, Gunther ed., 1986).Google Scholar

81 Habermas, Jürgen, Legitimationsprobleme des Spätkapitalismus, (1973).Google Scholar

82 Habermas, Jürgen, Die Krise des Wohlfahrtsstaates und die Erschöpfung utopischer Energien, in: Jürgen Habermas, Die Neue Unübersichtlichkeit, 141 (1985).Google Scholar

83 For a compendious representation of the entire discussion encompassing legal science, political science, and economics see Heinz-Dieter Assmann, supra, note 73.Google Scholar

84 Nobert Reich, Markt und Recht, 64 (1977); Reich, Norbert, Zum Verhältnis von Markt und Recht als Gegenstand sozialökonomischer Theoriebildung, 63 Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie (ARSP) 485 (1977). For a critique see Dieter Hart & Christian Joerges, Verbraucherrecht und Marktökonomik. Eine Kritik ordnungstheoretischer Eingrenzungen der Verbraucherpolitik, supra, note 8, 83, 168-177; Assmann, supra, note 73, 185, 251 and implicitly Norbert Reich himself: Staatliche Regulierung zwischen Marktversagen und Politikversagen. Erfahrungen mit der amerikanischen FTC und ihre Bedeutung für die Entwicklung des Verbraucherschutzrechts, 133-139 (1984).Google Scholar

85 Entwicklung des Rechts im organisierten Kapitalismus, supra, note 74, 17-29; Privatrechtstheorie als Aufgabe, 64 ARSP 87 (1978); Probleme einer Theorie des Wirtschaftsrechts, supra, note 8. Rudolf Wiethölter did propose a similar program of a “material constitutional theory as social theory of society with a reconstruction of our legal development as social development”, but then did not carry it out in this form (see Thesen zum Wirtschaftsverfassungsrecht, in: Der Kampf um das Grundgesetz. über die politische Bedeutung der Verfassungsinterpretation, 158, 161 (Abendroth, Wolfgang et al., eds., 1977).Google Scholar

86 The momentarily final result are “components” for the model of an “organization constitution” which distingushes itself negatively from the liberal contract constitution but still does not let itself be aggregated into a positive model; see Gert Brüggemeier Wirtschaftsordnung und Staatsverfassung - Mischverfassung des demokratischen Interventionskapitalismus - Verfassungstheorie des Sozialstaates. Drei Modelle der Verflechtung von Staat und Wirtschaft? - Eine Problemskizze, in: Rechtsformen der Verflechtung von Staat und Wirtschaft, 60 (Gessner, Volker & Winter, Gerd eds., 1982).Google Scholar

87 See, supra, A I 1, note 12.Google Scholar

88 See the often-cited study by Franz Wieacker, Das Sozialmodell der klassischen Privatrechtsgesetzbücher und die Entwicklung der modernen Gesellschaft, (1953) (justified inquiry about Wieacker's terminus in Jürgen Schmidt, Vertragsfreiheit und Schuldrechtsreform. Überlegungen zur Rechtfertigung der inhaltlichen Gestaltungsfreiheit bei Schuldverträgen, 17 (1985)).Google Scholar

89 See, supra, A I 3, note 23.Google Scholar

90 See hubert rottleuthner, rechtswissenschaft als sozialwissenschaft, 187-208 (1973); hubert rottleuthner, richterliches handeln. zur kritik der juristischen dogmatik, 1-60 (1973).Google Scholar

91 Hart, Dieter, Allgemeine Geschäftsbedingungen und Justizsystem. Zum Verhältnis von Vertrags- und ökonomietheorie, 9 (1975).Google Scholar

92 This was demonstrated on many of the central materials of civil law such as contract law, tort law, and the law of unjust enrichment Otherwise reference should be made to economic law monographs which each have their own approaches: Claus Ott, Recht und Realität der Unternehmenskorporation. Ein Beitrag zur Theorie der juristischen Person, (1977); Walz, Wolfgang R., Steuergerechtigkeit und Rechtsanwendung. Grundlinien einer relativ autonomen Steuerrechtsdogmatik, (1980).Google Scholar

93 This is the leitmotif of the critique on the “ordoliberal” theory of the interdependence of (competitive) “economic constitution” and (democratic) “state constitution”; (see Rudolph Wiethölter, Privatrecht als Gesellschaftstheorie?, Festschrift für Ludwig Raiser, 645 (1974); Hart, Dieter, Zur Instrumentierung des Wirtschaftsrechts am Beispiel der Wirtschaftsverfassung, 140 Zeitschrift für das gesamte Handelsrecht und Wirtschaftsrecht (ZHR) 31 (1976); Gotthold, Jürgen, Neuere Entwicklungen der Wettbewerbsrechtstheorie, 145 ZHR 286 (1981). - The term “ordoliberal” is untranslatable, but for its legal conception there are several American equivalents: The ordoliberal theory can be characterized as an attempt to lay claim to the Basic Law for a legal defense of the liberal model against social state transformations, as a “freezing into the legal system (of) the whole structure of laissez-faire” as Kennedy ascertained for the US in the late classical period (Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1733-1756). - In Friedrich August von Hayek, Der Weg zur Knechtschaft (The Road to Serfdom, 1944), Erlenbach-Zürich 1952; Die Verfassung der Freiheit (The Constitution of Liberty, 1960), (1971), American neoliberals and German ordoliberals of the “second generation” have a common theoretical legacy.Google Scholar

94 Wiethölter, Rudolph, Wirtschaftsrecht, in: Görlitz, supra, note 16, 531, 532.Google Scholar

95 Hart, Dieter, Vom bürgerlichen Recht zur politischen Verwaltung, 274 (1974).Google Scholar

96 See: Schmidt, Eike, Von der Privat- zur Sozialautonomie, 153, 155-159 (1980); Teubner, Gunther, Verrechtlichung - Begriffe, Merkmale, Grenzen, Auswege in: Verrechtlichung von Wirtschaft, Arbeit und sozialer Solidarität. Vergleichende Analysen, 289, 313, (Kübler, Friedrich ed., 1984), (English version: Juridification - Concepts, Aspects, Limits, Solutions in: Juridification of Social Spheres. a Comparative Analysis in the Area of Labour, Corporate, Antitrust and Social Welfare Law, 3, 19, Kübler, Friedrich ed., 1987) and Dieter Hart himself: Zur konzeptionellen Entwicklung des Vertragsrechts, 66, 77 (1984).Google Scholar

97 See already Jürgen Habermas, Legitimationsprobleme im Spätkapitalismus, supra, note 81, 9, and then in Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, supra, note 18 (Vol. 1 Handlungsrationalität und gesellschaftliche Rationalisierung), 332, Vol. 2, 229 and above all 487.Google Scholar

98 Habermas, Jürgen, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, supra, note 18, Vol. 2, 536.Google Scholar

99 Habermas, Jürgen, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, supra, note 18, 571, 510.Google Scholar

100 Habermas, Jürgen, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, supra, note 18, 514 (emphasis in original).Google Scholar

101 Habermas, Jürgen, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, supra, note 18, 539 (emphasis in original).Google Scholar

102 See Wiethölter, supra, note 13, 30.Google Scholar

103 See, supra, 2 at note 93.Google Scholar

104 See, infra, C I 1.Google Scholar

105 See, supra, A II 1; Unger's liberalism critique belongs to the repertoire of the CLS-movement, but not, characteristically, his later examinations, such as the one drawn on here.Google Scholar

106 Unger, supra, note 33.Google Scholar

107 Unger, supra, note 33, 193.Google Scholar

108 Unger, supra, note 33, 193200.Google Scholar

109 Unger, supra, note 33, 153.Google Scholar

110 Unger, supra, note 33, 206.Google Scholar

111 Unger, supra, note 33, 214, 238-268; see, infra, C II 1.Google Scholar

112 Gesellschaft, Wirtschaft und, supra, note 15, 502; see Unger, Roberto M., The Critical Legal Studies Movement, 96 Harv. L. Rev. 561, 571 (1983).Google Scholar

113 Unger, supra, note 33, 246 (a “program of institutional reconstruction”, Unger, supra, note 112, 601).Google Scholar

114 Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 17331737.Google Scholar

115 Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1738.Google Scholar

116 The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries, supra, note 36, 220.Google Scholar

117 Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1732.Google Scholar

118 “The opposed rhetorical modes lawyers use, reflect a deeper level of contradiction. At this deeper level, we are divided, among ourselves and also within ourselves, between irreconcilable visions of humanity and society …” (Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1685). Even after his retraction of the “fundamental contradiction” (note 46), Kennedy repeated this thesis. Freedom and Constraint in Adjudication: A Critical Phenomenology (note 46), describes a judge who wants to bring his “progressive” attitudes into effect, and in so doing immerses himself in the messages of the legal texts, contemplates his entanglements in role constraints and networks of expectation and ultimately, no longer secure in his original intuitions, helplessly falls by the wayside.Google Scholar

119 See, e.g., Charles M. Yablon, The Indeterminacy of the Law: Critical Legal Studies and the Problem of Legal Explanation, 6 Cardozo Law Review 917 (1985); but see Singer, Joseph W., The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory, 94 Yale L. J. 1, 20 (1984).Google Scholar

120 See Solum, Lawrence B., On the Indeterminacy Crisis: Critiquing Critical Dogma, 54 University of Chicago Law Review 462 (1987); Hegland, Kennedy, Goodbye to Deconstruction, 58 So. CAL. L. REV. 1203 (1985).Google Scholar

121 Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1745.Google Scholar

122 Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, supra, note 36, 1776.Google Scholar

123 Kennedy, Duncan, Distributive and Paternalistic Motives in Contract and Tort Law, with Special Reference to Compulsory Terms and Unequal Bargaining Power, 41 Maryland Law Review 563, 638-649 (1982).Google Scholar

124 See the analyses of the “constructive” elements of Legal Realism in Peller, supra, note 62, 2019-2064, as well as Balkin, supra, note 62, 770772.Google Scholar

125 Frug, supra, note 62, 1276. - Frug's classificaltion of group law doctrines to particular “bureaucracy models” corresponds exactly to the type of German analyses discussed supra in I 2.Google Scholar

126 Even here there are agreements: the affinities between the formalist model of bureaucracy and the market mechanisms for the control of managers discovered by representatives of economic analysis would be expressed by German authors through the qualification of the Chicago School as a specific variant of the “materialization” of formal law.Google Scholar

127 Frug, supra, note 125, 1296, 1386.Google Scholar

128 Frug, supra, note 62, 1382.Google Scholar

129 Frug, supra, note 62, 1360.Google Scholar

130 Dalton, supra, note 62.Google Scholar

131 Brüggemeier, supra, note 12, 1006, 1007.Google Scholar

132 See, supra, I 2.Google Scholar

133 Dalton, supra, note 62, 1012.Google Scholar

134 Dalton, supra, note 62, 1029.Google Scholar

135 See, supra, I 2 and 3.Google Scholar

136 Dalton, supra, note 62, 1014.Google Scholar

137 Dalton, supra, note 62, 1000; on the perspectives of this argumentation see, infra, C II 3.Google Scholar

138 See Heller, Thomas C., A Brief Rejoinder to the Discussion of the CCLS, 1 Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie (ZfRSoz) 126 (1980); Schlegel, John H., Notes Toward an Intimate, Optionated, and Affectionate History of the Conference on Critical Legal Studies, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 391 (1984); Mark Kelman, A Guide to Critical Legal Studies, 1-14 (1987).Google Scholar

139 Windscheid, Bernhard, Die Aufgaben der Rechtswissenschaft (Leipziger Rektoratsrede of 31. October 1884), in Bernhard Windscheid, Gesammelte Reden und Abhandlungen, 100, 112 (Oertmann, Paul ed., 1904).Google Scholar

140 I.e.: the approaches which are discussed in this volume but which in their overall importance remain most likely marginal.Google Scholar

141 GÜNTHER, KLAUS, DER SINN FÜR ANGEMESSENHEIT. ANWENDUNGSDISKURSE IN RECHT UND MORAL (1988).Google Scholar

142 See particularly Habermas, Jürgen, Diskursethik - Notizen zu einem Begründungsprogramm, in JÜRGEN HABERMAS, MORALBEWUßTSEIN UND KOMMUNIKATIVES HANDELN, 53, 127 (1983).Google Scholar

143 HABERMAS, id., 75.Google Scholar

144 Günther, supra, note 141, 117; see on the following already Klaus Günther, Materialisierung als Rekontextualisierung des Formalrechts, Typescript (1984); Preliminary Considerations to a Theory of Procedural Application, in Workshop zu Konzepten des postinterventionistischen Rechts, 74 (Brüggemeier, Gert & Joerges, Christian eds., 1984); Günther, Klaus, The Core of Moral Universalism in Modern Law, Typescript (1984).Google Scholar

145 See on this Kennedy, supra, note 35, whose critique of liberal law application doctrines concentrates on the idea that the substantive content of rules could be brought to effect through their “application” in concrete conflicts.Google Scholar

146 See, supra, B I 3.Google Scholar

147 Günther, supra, note 144, 21.Google Scholar

148 Günther, supra, note 141, 473.Google Scholar

149 See Wiethölter, supra, note 13, 45 (German version), 235 (English version).Google Scholar

150 See Joerges, Christian, Quality Regulation in Consumer Goods Markets: Theoretical Concepts and Practical Examples, in Contract and Organisation. Legal Analysis in the Light of Economic and Social Theory, 142 (Daintith, Terence & Gunther. Teubner eds., 1986) - Anyone who considers such examples will probably estimate the chances of Dworkin's Hercules to bring the principles of relevant law into a coherent connection (Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire, 165, 176, 313 (1986)) more skeptically than Günther does (Günther, supra, note 141, 483). -Dworkin reacts to the radical skepticism of the CLS-movement's indeterminacy thesis (supra B II 2 and 3 as well as C II 2 and 3) with a sort of burden of proof rule: “The internal skeptic must show that the flawed and contradictory account is the only one available” (Dworkin, id., 274). This answer meets the assertion that there are absolutely no successful examples for the legal treatment of colliding interests and principles. On the other hand, recalling that Hercules failed on Earth, one may demand that legal theory must systematically consider the practical-political limits of its normative ideas.Google Scholar

151 See Habermas, Jürgen & Luhmann, Niklas, Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozialtechnologie - Was leistet die Systemforschung? (1971).Google Scholar

152 Just compare the programmatic Mitteilung der Herausgeber: Zum ersten Heft der Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie, ZfRSoz 1 (1980), with issues from the last few years of that journal.Google Scholar

153 See Klaus F. Röhl, Rechtssoziologie, 61, 62 (1987); Lautmann, Rüdiger & Meuser, Michael, Verwendungen der Soziologie in Handlungswissenschaften am Beispiel von Pädagogik und Jurisprudenz, ZfSS 685, 697 (1986).Google Scholar

154 This critique too has an almost twenty year tradition: see Jörg Münstermann, Zur Rechtstheorie Niklas Luhmanns, Kritische Justiz (KJ) 325 (1969), and for a recent example Niklaus Dimmel & Alfred J. Noll, Autopoiesis und Selbstreferentialität als “postmoderne Rechtstheorie” - Die neue reine Rechtsleere, Demokratie und Recht (DuR) 379 (1988).Google Scholar

155 Gunther Teubner protested against taking over this function and at the same time refused to give off the relevant signals; see Gunther Teubner, Social Order from Legislative Noise? Autopoietic Closure as a Problem for Legal Regulation, 5-6 (1985).Google Scholar

156 See Teubner, Gunther, And God Laughed… . Indeterminacy, Self-Reference and Paradox in Law, supra in this volume. From the writings of Niklas Luhmann, see above all: Die Rückgabe des zwölften Kamels. Zum Sinn einer soziologischen Analyse des Rechts, 22, Typescript (1984).Google Scholar

157 Teubner, supra, note 96; Wiethölter, supra, note 13, 91.Google Scholar

158 Episodenverknüpfung: Zur Steigerung von Selbstreferenz im Recht, in Theorie als Passion. Niklas Luhmann zum 60. Geburtstag, 423, 437 (Dirk Baecker et al. eds., 1987).Google Scholar

159 Episodenverknüpfung: Zur Steigerung von Selbstreferenz im Recht, id., 442.Google Scholar

160 See Luhmann, Niklas, Closure and Openness: On Reality in the World of Law, in Autopoietic Law: A New Approach to Law and Society, 335, 337 (Teubner, Gunter ed., 1988).Google Scholar

161 Teubner, Gunther, Introduction to Autopoietic Law, in Autopoietic Law: A New Approach to Law and Society, 1, 2 (Teubner, Gunter ed., 1988); Luhmann would say: the assumptions which go into the reality constructions of the theory of autopoietic systems (id., 343).Google Scholar

162 See Teubner, supra, note 156, 32.Google Scholar

163 Klaus Günther sees corresponding difficulties as they here are asserted for the relation of legal theory and legal doctrine in the relationship between the “code” of the legal system and the environmental adaptations mediated via its “programmings” (Der Sinn für Angemessenheit, supra, note 141, 327).Google Scholar

164 Ladeur, Karl-Heinz, Abwägung - Ein neues Paradigma des Verwaltungsrechts. Von der Einheit der Rechtsordnung zum Rechtspluralismus, 121-184 (1984); see Ladeur, Karl-Heinz, Von der Gesetzesvollziehung zur strategischen Rechtsfortbildung, in Leviathan 332 (1979).Google Scholar

165 Abwägung - Ein neues Paradigma des Verwaltungsrechts. Von der Einheit der Rechtsordnung zum Rechtspluralismus, supra, note 164, 135, 149, 208.Google Scholar

166 Abwägung - Ein neues Paradigma des Verwaltungsrechts. Von der Einheit der Rechtsordnung zum Rechtspluralismus, supra, note 164, 153; on the situation in Germany in the Twenties and the National Socialist reaction see Karl-Heinz Ladeur, Sprachformationen und Rechtsparadigma. Eine modelltheoretische Skizze des deutschen Verwaltungsrechts im 20. Jahrhundert, in Wissenschaft und Recht der Verwaltung seit dem Ancien Regime. Europäische Ansichten (Ius Commune. Sonderheft 21), 189, 200 (Heyen, Erk Volkmar ed., 1984).Google Scholar

167 Ladeur, supra, note 164, 172, 214; see already Ladeur, Karl-Heinz, in Friedhelm Hase & Karl-Heinz Ladeur, Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit und politisches System. Studien zum Rechtsstaatsproblem in Deutschland, 224 (1980).Google Scholar

168 E.g.: Jenseits von Regulierung und Ökonomisierung der Umwelt: Bearbeitung von Ungewissheit durch (selbst-)organisierte Lernfähigkeit - Eine Skizze, Zeitschrift für Umweltpolitik (ZfU) 1 (1987); Rundfunkverfassung für die “Informationsgesellschaft”? Selbstorganisation von “taste communities” als Alternative zum Markt und zur öffentlichrechtlichen Integration, in 31 Publizistik 147 (1986).Google Scholar

169 Ladeur, supra, note 164, 200, 221; see Ladeur, Karl-Heinz, Perspektiven einer post-modernen Rechtstheorie. Zur Auseinandersetzung mit Niklas Luhmanns Konzept der “Einheit des Rechtssystems”, in 16 Rechtstheorie 383, 422 (1985) (English version: Perspectives on a Post-Modern Theory of Law: A Critique of Niklas Luhmann, “The Unity of the Legal System”, in Autopoietic Law: A New Approach to Law and Society, 242, 272 (Teubner, Gunter ed., 1988)). Translated into more concrete contexts: Environmental law must orient itself towards the process-like transformations of its area of applicability (the environment subject to various burdens) and to take care of the coordination, subordination, and compatibilization of various actors and interests. Therefore environmental regulations (threshold values) should be determined in open commission procedures, in which all relevant disciplines and also the respective “founded” counter-positions can be articulated. The legal examination should then limit itself to the weighting of the factors, the establishment of a threshold value and the individual procedural steps, while the administration should be conceded a planning discretion (Karl-Heinz Ladeur, Zum planerischen Charakter der technischen Normen im Umweltrecht - Zugleich ein Beitrag zum Wyhl-Urteil des Bundesverwaltungsgerichts - Umwelt- und Planungsrecht (UPR) 253, 258 (1987)).Google Scholar

170 See the argumentation of Albrecht Wellmer, Zur Dialektik von Moderne und Postmoderne. Vernunftkritik nach Adorno, 106-107 (1985).Google Scholar

171 Gunther Teubner reacted to Ladeur's critique of reflexive law with “hearty greetings from chaos” (Anmerkungen zu Ladeurs Konzept des “strategischen Rechts”, in Workshop zu Konzepten des postinterventionistischen Rechts, 340, 346 (Brüggemeier, Gert & Joerges, Christian eds., 1984)).Google Scholar

A more friendly interpretation of the concrete regulation proposals offered by Ladeur can point out that implicitly the flexibilization of law is constantly limited by considerations in which Klaus Günther would recognize suitability argumentations and the attractiveness of the universalibility principle.Google Scholar

172 See, supra, A III and B III.Google Scholar

173 See, on the liberalism critique: supra A II; and his analysis of post-classical legal developments, supra B II 1.Google Scholar

174 See Unger, supra, note 41; Law in Modern Society, supra, note 33; Roberto M. Unger, Passion. An Essay on Personality (1984); the three-volume opus Roberto M. Unger, Politics. a Work in Constructive Social Theory (1987) is still unavailable to me (April 1988). - From the still sparse secondary literature see Drucilla Cornell, Toward a Modern/Postmodern Reconstruction of Ethics, 133 U. Pa. L. Rev. 291, 327-358 (1985); Goodrich, Peter, Law and Modernity, 49 Modern Law Review 545 (1986); Duxbury, Neil T., Look Back in Unger: A Retrospective Appraisal of Law in Modern Society, 49 Modern Law Review 658 (1986); Collins, Hugh, Roberto Unger and the Critical Legal Studies Movement, 14 Journal of Law and Society 387 (1987).Google Scholar

175 Unger, supra, note 112.Google Scholar

176 Unger, supra, note 112, 582.Google Scholar

177 Unger, supra, note 112, 583586.Google Scholar

178 Unger, supra, note 112, 586602.Google Scholar

179 Unger, supra, note 112, 616644. - Unger has picked up the habit of dispensing with footnotes. In light of the hypertrophy and the authoritarian gesture of this technique this may be a useful object lesson. But the consequence is that above all the argumentation with judicial developments (which for Unger have a particular significance) remain largely impenetrable even for interested foreign readers.Google Scholar

180 See, supra, A I 2 at note 91, and note 125.Google Scholar

181 See, supra, A I 1 at note 85.Google Scholar

182 See, supra, A II 2 at note 93 and A II 3.Google Scholar

183 See, supra, B II 1 at note 110.Google Scholar

184 Peteghem, Jan van, Critical legal studies: Deconstructie of romantisch kartesianisme?, 16 Rechtsfilosofie en Rechtstheorie 187, 189 (1987).Google Scholar

185 Kelman, Mark G., Trashing, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 293 (1984).Google Scholar

186 Kelman, id., 344.Google Scholar

187 Kelman, supra, note 185, 337.Google Scholar

188 Kelman, supra, note 185, 338-340; Here I can only make reference to the debate concerning empirical legal research connected with these reservations: see Munger, Frank & Seron, Carroll, Critical Legal Studies versus Critical Legal Theory: A Comment on Method, 6 Law & Policy 257 (1984); Whitford, William C., Lowered Horizons: Implementation Research in a Post-CLS World, Wisconsin Law Review (Wisc. L. Rev.) 755 (1986).Google Scholar

189 Kelman, supra, note 185, 323.Google Scholar

190 Kelman, supra, note 185, 321, 345.Google Scholar

191 Kelman, supra, note 185, 326.Google Scholar

192 Kelman, supra, note 185, 299; Kelman, supra, note 138, 5.Google Scholar

193 Kelman, supra, note 185, 321, note 68 refers above all to Alan D. Freeman, Truth and Mystification in Legal Scholarship, 90 Yale L. J. 1029, 1030 (1981): “The point of delegitimation is to expose possibilities more truly expressing reality, possibilities of fashioning a future that might at least partially realize a substantive notion of justice …”.Google Scholar

194 See, supra, A II 3 at note 58 and B II 3 at note 123; After the retraction of the “basic contradiction” (supra note 46) of course there still remain of these utopias only the authentic moments of spontaneous expressions of freedom (Gabel/Kennedy, supra, note 46, 43).Google Scholar

195 The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory, 94 Yale L. J. 1 (1984); see the critique of Stick, John, Can Nihilism be Pragmatic?, 100 Harv. L. Rev. 332 (1986).Google Scholar

196 See, supra, C II 3 at note 130.Google Scholar

197 Dalton, supra, note 62, 1010.Google Scholar

198 See, supra, B II 3 at note 135.Google Scholar

199 Dalton, supra, note 62, 1095.Google Scholar

200 See Klausa, Ekkehard & Klaus F. Röhl & Ralf Rogowski & Hubert Rottleuthner, Rezensionen eines Denkansatzes: Die Conference on Critical Legal Studies, 1 ZfRSoz 85 (1980), and the reply from Thomas C. Heller (Heller, supra, note 138).Google Scholar