Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-495rp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-05T14:31:57.111Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Persons and Things in International Law and “Law of Humanity”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Drawing from Roberto Esposito's recent work on persons and things, this Article studies recent attempts to rethink international legal personality. Esposito's work resurrects the claim that personhood operates like a mask, splitting the legal and philosophical world into persons and things. International law differs from domestic law in that international legal personality has traditionally been the prerogative of states, not of (rational) individuals. Yet, this has not completely dismantled the persons/things logic, because the exclusive legal personality of states has continuously threatened to reduce individuals into things in the eyes of international law. It is perhaps for this reason that international legal theorists have long sought to extend international legal personality to individuals and other non-state actors. This Article addresses the most recent attempt, namely an attempt to shift international law towards a law of humanity. Without taking a stance on whether this project is a good idea or not, this Article raises some doubts about whether the concept of international legal personality can help in fulfilling the project's aim, namely to help increase human freedom and wellbeing. This is especially relevant because, regardless of whether legal personality is attributed primarily to the state or the individual, we still remain—according to Esposito—within a theoretical framework in which the dispositif of person necessarily excludes some forms of life in protecting or empowering others.

Type
Special Issue Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood
Copyright
Copyright © 2017 by German Law Journal, Inc. 

References

1 Roberto Esposito, Persons and Things: From the Body's Point of View 2 (2015).Google Scholar

2 See id. at 16–17.Google Scholar

3 See id. at 81–85.Google Scholar

4 See Pottage, Alain & Mundy, Martha, Law, Anthropology, and the Constitution of the Social: Making Persons and Things 139 (2004).Google Scholar

5 See Klabbers, Jan, The Concept of Legal Personality, 11 Ius Gentium 3566 (2005).Google Scholar

6 See Parlett, Kate, The Individual in the International Legal System: Continuity and Change in International Law 11–14 (2d ed. 2013); see generally Emer de Vattel, The Law of Nations (2008).Google Scholar

7 See Nijman, Janne Elisabeth, The Concept of International Legal Personality: An Inquiry into the History and Theory of International Law 83 (2004).Google Scholar

8 See Barbara, Christopher, International Legal Personality: Panacea or Pandemonium? Theorizing About the Individual and the State in the Era of Globalization, 12 Austrian Rev. Int'l Eur. L. 17, 3335 (2007).Google Scholar

9 Crawford, James R., The Creation of States in International Law 28 (2d ed. 2007).Google Scholar

10 See Craven, Matthew, On Statehood, Self-determination, and Recognition, in International Law 201–47, 215 (Malcolm Evans ed., 4th ed. 2014).Google Scholar

11 Klabbers, supra note 5, at 37.Google Scholar

12 See Oppenheim, Lassa, 1 International Law: A Treatise (1905).Google Scholar

13 See Parlett, supra note 6, at 13–16.Google Scholar

14 See Peters, Anne, Beyond Human Rights: The Legal Status of the Individual in International Law, in The Concept of International Legal Personality: An Inquiry into the History and Theory of International Law 1819 (2004).Google Scholar

15 See Nijman, supra note 7, at 297–325; Peters, supra note 14, at 20–21.Google Scholar

16 See Portmann, Roland, Legal Personality in International Law 126–72 (2010).Google Scholar

17 Jurisdiction of the Courts of Danzig (Pecuniary Claims of Danzig Railway Officials who have Passed into the Polish Service, Against the Polish Railways Administration), P.C.I.J. (Ser. B) no. 15 (Mar. 3, 1928).Google Scholar

18 See id. at 17–18.Google Scholar

19 Parlett, supra note 6, at 25.Google Scholar

20 George Manner, The Object Theory of the Individual in International Law, 46 Am. J. Int'l L. 428–49 (1952).Google Scholar

21 Nijman, supra note 7, at 469.Google Scholar

22 Lassa Oppenheim, International Law 636, 639 (Lauterpacht 8th ed. 1955); see also Schwarzenberger, Georg, A Manual of International Law 35, 53–54 (1947).Google Scholar

23 See Parlett, supra note 6, at 353–54.Google Scholar

24 See Mikko Rajavuori's chapter in this volume, 18 German L.J. (2017).Google Scholar

25 See Akehurst, Michael, A Modern Introduction to International Law 70 (rev. ed. 1987).Google Scholar

26 For an overview, see Portmann, supra note 16, pt. II.Google Scholar

27 See Higgins, Rosalyn, Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It 50 (Clarendon Press ed. 1995).Google Scholar

28 See Mc, Myres S.Dougal, Lasswell, Harold D. & Lung-chu Chen, Human Rights and World Public Order: The Basic Policies of an International Law of Human Dignity (1977).Google Scholar

29 See Portmann, supra note 16, pt. III.Google Scholar

30 See Antonio Augusto Cancado Trindade, International Law for Humankind (2010); Theodor Meron, The Humanization of International Law (2006); Antonio Cassese, International Law 165–66 (2d ed. 2003).Google Scholar

31 See Peters, supra note 14, at 36–38.Google Scholar

32 Barbara, supra note 8, at 25.Google Scholar

33 See id. at 23.Google Scholar

34 Id. at 23–24.Google Scholar

35 Id. at 29.Google Scholar

36 See Peters, Anne, Humanity as the A and Ō of Sovereignty, 20 Eur. J. Int'l L. 513, 514 (2009).Google Scholar

37 Barbara, supra note 8, at 45.Google Scholar

38 See id. at 47.Google Scholar

39 See Alexy, Robert, a Theory of Constitutional Rights Chapter 44111 (2010).Google Scholar

40 See Domingo, Rafael, The New Global Law (reprinted ed. 2011).Google Scholar

41 See id. at xiv.Google Scholar

42 Id. at xxi.Google Scholar

43 Barbara, supra note 8, at 55.Google Scholar

44 Id. at 17–18.Google Scholar

45 Id. at 37.Google Scholar

46 Peters, supra note 36, at 514.Google Scholar

47 Id. at 551.Google Scholar

48 Id. at 552.Google Scholar

49 See Benvenisti, Eyal, Sovereigns as Trustees of Humanity: On the Accountability of States to Foreign Stakeholders, 107 Am. J. Int'L L. 295 (2013).Google Scholar

50 See Waldron, Jeremy, Are Sovereigns Entitled to the Benefit of the International Rule of Law?, 22 Eur. J. Int'l L. 315–43 (2011).Google Scholar

51 See Criddle, Evan J. & Evan Fox-Decent, Fiduciaries of Humanity: How International Law Constitutes Authority (2016). On the fiduciary turn in law, see Contract, Status, and Fiduciary Law, (Miller, Paul B. & Gold, Andrew S. eds., 2016); Leib, Ethan J. & Galoob, Stephen R., Fiduciary Political Theory: A Critique Essay, 125 Yale L.J. 1820–879 (2015); Philosophical Foundations of Fiduciary Law, (Gold, Andrew S. & Miller, Paul B. eds., 2014); D. Theodore Rave, Politicians as Fiduciaries, 126 Harv. L. Rev. 671–739 (2012).Google Scholar

52 Nijman, supra note 7, at 456–57.Google Scholar

53 See id. at 467.Google Scholar

54 Id. at 468.Google Scholar

55 Id. at 468.Google Scholar

56 Ruti Teitel, Humanity's Law 17 (2011).Google Scholar

57 Id. at x.Google Scholar

58 Id. at 19.Google Scholar

59 See Nijman, supra note 7, at 456–57.Google Scholar

60 See Barbara, supra note 8, at 18.Google Scholar

61 See Peters, supra note 36, at 40–41.Google Scholar

62 Id. at 553–54.Google Scholar

63 Id. at 58–59.Google Scholar

64 Roberto Esposito, Communitas: the Origin and Destiny of Community (2010).Google Scholar

65 See Susanna Lindroos-Hovinheimo's chapter in this volume, 18 German L.J. (2017).Google Scholar

66 See Esposito, Roberto, Immunitas: the Protection and Negation of Life (2011).Google Scholar

67 See e.g., Esposito, Roberto, Bíos: Biopolitics and Philosophy (2008).Google Scholar

68 Roberto Esposito & Rhiannon Noel Welch, Terms of the Political: Community, Immunity, Biopolitics 46 (2013).Google Scholar

69 Id. at 60.Google Scholar

70 See Vining, Joseph, Dignity as Perception: Recognition of the Human Individual and the Individual Animal in Legal Thought, in Understanding Human Dignity 573, 581 (Christopher McCrudden ed., 2013).Google Scholar

71 Barbara, supra note 8, at 23.Google Scholar

72 Roberto Esposito, Third Person: Politics of Life and Philosophy of the Impersonal 115 (2012).Google Scholar

73 Id. at 70–71.Google Scholar

74 Id. at 116.Google Scholar

75 See Klabbers, supra note 5, at 37, 56–57.Google Scholar

76 See id. at 61–64.Google Scholar

77 Id. at 65–66.Google Scholar

78 See Weil, Simone, Simone Weil: An Anthology 49–79 (Sian Miles ed., First Grove Press ed. 2000).Google Scholar

79 See Gilles Deleuze & Félix Guattari, 1730: Becoming-Intense, Becoming-Animal, Becoming-Imperceptible…, in A Thousand Plateaus Capitalism and Schizophrenia at 232 (Brian Massumi trans., 2008).Google Scholar

80 Esposito and Welch, supra note 68, at 122.Google Scholar

81 See Ohlin, Jens David, Is the Concept of the Person Necessary for Human Rights, 105 Colum. L. Rev. 209, 212 (2005).Google Scholar

82 See id. at 231.Google Scholar

83 Nijman, supra note 7, at 466.Google Scholar

84 See Lindroos-Hovinheimo, supra note 65.Google Scholar