Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:24:47.197Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Memory, Politics and Law – The Eichmann Trial: Hannah Arendt's View on the Jerusalem Court's Competence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

When the true scale of what would later be called ‘crimes against humanity', ‘genocide’ and, specifically, ‘the Holocaust’ became clear in the aftermath of the Second World War, a number of questions were raised. First, is this a new type of crime, in which evil manifests itself in a radically different way than it had earlier? Some disputed this. Evil exists at all times and it has always confronted people with an abyss of atrocities. With Rawls, one might then say that every ‘great evil’ is sufficient in itself and that making comparisons is not necessary, even if the Holocaust cannot be detached from earlier ravages of evil such as the Inquisition and antisemitism. Others thought this question ought to be answered positively. Adorno and Levinas formulated their philosophies in part as a response to the unique character of the Holocaust. Even now, more than a half a century later, the events associated with the Holocaust form a rich source for public debate, scientific inquiry and literary expression. Secondly, the question has been raised as to how one is to cope with this modern form of political evil and with a new type of criminal offender. Some argued in favour of the familiar recourse to politics and international law. Specifically, political crimes ought either to be dealt with politically or to be considered in the light of the principle of international law: par in parem non habet jurisdictionem. So, ordinary criminal law is not applicable where the mutual conduct of states is concerned. Others, however, including the Allied governments in the period immediately following the termination of hostilities, argued that these crimes were such that punishment would be inevitable. This might give rise to legal problems, but these crimes ought to be dealt with to the extent possible by means of ordinary criminal procedure.

Type
Articles: Special Issue: Confronting Memories – Memory, Politics and Law
Copyright
Copyright © 2005 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 Rawls, John, The Law of Peoples 22 (1999). See, also, his Political Liberalism lxii (2nd ed., 1996).Google Scholar

2 Some examples: the (ongoing) discussions on the Holocaust monument in Berlin; Robert Jan van Pelt / Deborah Dwork, Auschwitz. 1270 to the Present (1996); Jonathan S. Foer, Everything is illuminated (2002).Google Scholar

3 As examined in: The Origins of Totalitarianism (1966) (orig. as: Elemente und Ursprünge totaler Herrschaft) (1958).Google Scholar

4 Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem. A Report on the Banality of Evil 267 (1992) (orig. 1963).Google Scholar

5 For the precise background, see, for example, Annette Wieviorka, Die Entstehung des Zeugen, in: Hannah Arendt Revisited. ‘Eichmann in Jerusalem’ und die Folgen 140 (G. Smith, ed., 2000).Google Scholar

6 This then is the title of the report of the ‘Dutch journalist’ (cf., H. Arendt, note 4, 282): Harry Mulisch, De zaak 40/61 (1961).Google Scholar

7 See Wieviorka (note 5), 149.Google Scholar

8 Fackenheim, Emil, To Mend the World 237 (1982), comments on and rejects Arendt's thesis of the banality of evil as a result of those clips.Google Scholar

9 Not to be confused with the ‘Survivors of the Shoah Visual History Foundation', which was founded by Spielberg after filming Schindler's List with an aim of capturing Holocaust survivors’ testimonies on film, see http://www.vhf.org/.Google Scholar

10 This report led to a split between Arendt and Gershom Scholem, see, Stéphane Mosès, Das Recht zu urteilen: Hannah Arendt, Gershom Scholem und der Eichmann-Prozess, in: Garry Smith (note 5), 78. On the ‘civil war’ among intellectuals in New York, which was caused by Arendt's report, see, for example, Anthony Grafton, Arendt und Eichmann am Esstisch, in: G. Smith (note 5), 57.Google Scholar

11 Daniel Goldhagen, Hitler's willing executioners: ordinary Germans and the Holocaust 592-3 (2nd ed., 1996).Google Scholar

12 The element that was seen as most disturbing was Arendt's evil qualification of Leo Baeck, president of the Berlin Jewish Council, as ‘Jewish Führer', a qualification she deleted in later editions of her book, Arendt (note 4), 119.Google Scholar

13 Parvikko, Tuija, Positivists versus Moralists. The Eichmann Trial and International Law, Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought 4 223, 233 (2000).Google Scholar

14 Id., 235.Google Scholar

15 See Arendt (note 4), 9-10.Google Scholar

16 Gideon Hausner, Justice in Jerusalem 323 (1966).Google Scholar

17 Richard Wolin, Heidegger's Children 55 (2001); Amos Elon, Hannah Arendts Exkommunizierung, in: Smith (note 5), 25.Google Scholar

18 Because of the German-Jewish descent, compared to the ‘Galician’ Hausner? See: Hannah Arendt / Karl Jaspers, Letter of April 13th 1961, in: Hannah Arendt / Karl Jaspers. Briefwechsel 1926-1969 472 (1985).Google Scholar

19 Scholem protests fundamentally, especially against Arendt's harsh judgement: ‘Ich finde in Ihren Darstellungen des jüdischen Verhaltens unter extremen Umstände kein abgewogenes Urteil, ‥ Ich masse mir kein Urteil an. Ich war nicht dabei', in: Mosès, note 10 above at 79. This is not a minor allegation, as Arendt prided herself in understanding political judgments very well, especially in: Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy (H. Beiner, ed., 1982).Google Scholar

20 See Arendt (note 4), 125.Google Scholar

21 In summary, functionalists stress the bureaucratic and modern character of the the Holocaust, which is than said to have begun by the end of 1941 as a result of the failure of the Nazi deportation and emigration policy and the military losses in Russia; Intentionalists argue that the Holocaust was actually willed and planned by Hitler from the very beginning of his political career. Functionalism in Arendt can already be found in her 1948 text: Organized Guilt and Universal Responsibility, e.g., in: Collective Responsibility 273 (Larry May / Stanley Hoffman, eds., 1981). And in her report of a visit to Germany in 1949-1950, now e.g.,in: Hannah Arendt, Besuch in Deutschland (1973). See, for a ‘functionalist view’ deeply inspired by Arendt, Zygmunt Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust (1993).Google Scholar

22 Apart from that, Hilberg considered his life work ruined by Arendt's careless use of it, see Gary Smith, Einsicht aus falscher Distanz, in: Smith (note 5), 7.Google Scholar

23 See, also, Hannah Arendt and Karl Jaspers, Letter of October 19th 1946 and Letter of December 17th 1946 (note 18) 99, 106.Google Scholar

24 Bernstein, See Richard, Did Hannah Arendt Change her Mind? From Radical Evil to the Banality of Evil, in: Hannah Arendt. Twenty Years Later 127 (Jerome Kohn / Larry May, eds., 1996).Google Scholar

25 See Arendt (note 4), 54.Google Scholar

26 See Arendt (note 4), 114. See, also, http://www.ghwk.de.Google Scholar

27 Margalit, See Avishai / Motzkin, Gabriel, Anstifter und Vollstrecker: Hannah Arendts Authentizitätsbegriff als Kriterium zur Beurteilung Adolf Eichmanns, in: Smith (note 5), 202; Thomas Mertens, Arendt's Judgment and Eichmann's Evil, Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought 2 58 (1998).Google Scholar

28 See Arendt (note 4), 252, 287-8 (emphasis in the original).Google Scholar

29 See, also, Peter Novick, The Holocaust in American Life 134 (1999).Google Scholar

30 The existence of the Nuremberg Trials may give the impression that a large part of the crimes committed by the Nazi regime and during the war has been prosecuted. This is not the case. Only a limited number of ‘big fish’ have been tried, but in many cases there has not been a legal ‘Vergangenheitsbewältigung', see, for example, Friedrich Jörg, Freispruch für die Nazi-Justiz (1983); Tim Bowder, Blind Eye to Murder (2nd ed., 1995) (orig. 1981).Google Scholar

31 See, also, Novick (note 29), 54-58.Google Scholar

32 See the Versailles Treaty, Par. 227-9; Bowder (note 30), 17-19; Geoffrey Robertson, Crimes against Humanity. The Struggle for Global Justice 225-6 (2000).Google Scholar

33 Robertson, See, id., 211; Judith Shklar, Legalism 159 (1964).Google Scholar

34 Carl Schmitt, Völkerrechtliche Grossraumordnung mit Interventionsverbot für raumfremde Mächte (1939), in: Staat, Grossraum, Nomos: Arbeiten aus den Jahren 1916-1969 287 (Günther Maschke, ed., 1995).Google Scholar

35 Similarly, recently, for example, john Rawls, The Law of Peoples (note 1), 98-100, drawing on Michael WALZER's classic Just and Unjust Wars (2nd ed., 1992) (orig. 1977).Google Scholar

36 In a way, the war only provided the context in which the genocide became possible: ‘a crime that could not be explained by any utilitarian purpose,’ Arendt (note 4), 275.Google Scholar

37 Already before the Second World War, there were attempts, predominantly by Robert Lemkin, to codify the crime of genocide. See Samantha Powers, “A Problem from Hell“: America and the Age of Genocide (2002) and its review by Brian Urquhart, Shameful Neglect,12 7 The New York Review of Books 49 (2002). See, also, Vivian Grosswald Curran, The Politics of Memory/Erinnerungspolitik and the Use and Propriety of Law in the Process of Memory Construction, 14 Law and Critique 309 (2003).Google Scholar

39 Paulson, Stanley L., Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg,in 4 Philosophy and Public Affairs 132 (1974).Google Scholar

40 See Robertson (note 32), 218.Google Scholar

41 See Arendt (note 4), 254; See, also, Seyla Benhabib, Identität, Perspektive und Erzählung in Hannah Arendts ‘Eichmann in Jerusalem', in: Smith (note 5), 109.Google Scholar

42 The Rome Statute determines in its article 11: ‘The Court has jurisdiction only with respect to crimes committed after the entry into force of this Statute'; and in article 24: ‘No person shall be criminally responsible under this Statute for conduct prior to the entry into force of the Statute'.Google Scholar

43 See Arendt (note 4), 261.Google Scholar

44 Id., 261-2. See, also, Moishe Postone, Hannah Arendts ‘Eichmann in Jerusalem': Die unaufgelöste Antinomie von Universalität und Besonderem, in Smith (note 5), 273.Google Scholar

45 See Arendt (note 4), 263.Google Scholar

46 Article 6 reads: ‘Persons charged with genocide or any of the other acts enumerated in article III shall be tried by a competent tribunal of the State in the territory of which the act was committed, or by such international penal tribunal as may have jurisdiction with respect to those Contracting Parties which shall have accepted its jurisdiction.'Google Scholar

47 See Arendt (note 4), 263-5.Google Scholar

48 Similarly Benhabib (note 41), 110.Google Scholar

49 See Arendt (note 4), 260.Google Scholar

50 See Shklar (note 33), 170.Google Scholar

51 See Arendt (note 4), 269.Google Scholar

52 Id., 269; Benhabib (note 41), 111: ‘den Genozid an einem Volk allein aus dem Grund, weil es in dieser spezifischen Gestalt als eine von vielen Möglichkeiten der ‘menschlichen Vielfalt’ auf der Erde existiert'.Google Scholar

53 Arendt (note 4), 270.Google Scholar

54 See Postone (note 44), 275.Google Scholar

55 See Wolin (note 17), 43.Google Scholar

56 See Arendt (note 4), 270.Google Scholar