Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T02:27:23.092Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Meditating the Different Concepts of Corporate Criminal Liability in England and Germany

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Today's world has been deeply affected by globalization. Different cultures have deepened their knowledge of each other and are forced to create common solutions to worldwide problems. This has led to an increasing interest in comparing different nations’ approaches to common problems.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2010 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 See M. Reimann & R. Zimmermann, Preface to The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Law, i, at v (M. Reimann & R. Zimmermann eds., 2006); A. Harding & E. Örücü, Preface to Comparative Law in the 21st Century, i, at vii et seq. (A. Harding & E. Örücü eds., 2002).Google Scholar

2 Reimann, supra note 1, at v et seq.Google Scholar

3 See A. Peters & H. Schwenke, Comparative Law Beyond Post-Modernism, 49 Int'l & Comp. L.Q. 802 (2000) (presenting some labels for the views engaging in this debate: critical comparisons, new approach, cultural immersion approach, engaged comparativism, discourse analysts, Utah group).Google Scholar

4 See S. Beale & A. Safwat, What Developments in Western Europe Tell Us about American Critiques of Corporate Criminal Liability, 8 Buff. Crim. L. Rev. 89, 126 et seq. (2005) (describing some European Transnational Proposals).Google Scholar

5 See infra Part I.2.Google Scholar

6 See Jansen, N., Comparative Law and Comparative Knowledge, in The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Law 305, 306 (M. Reimann & R. Zimmermann eds., 2006).Google Scholar

7 See Frankenberg, G., Critical Comparisons: Re-thinking Comparative Law, 26 Harv. Int'l L.J. 411, 416 et seq. (1985); P. Legrand, European Legal Systems are not Converging, 45 Int'l & Comp. L.Q. 52 (1996). This also might have been a reason for its continuing neglect, already diagnosed. See Gutteridge, Harold Cooke, Comparative Law—An Introduction to the Comparative Method of Legal Study and Research (1946) (diagnosing the continuing neglect).Google Scholar

8 See Zumbansen, P., Comparative Law's Coming of Age?, 6 German Law Journal 1073, 1075 (2005).Google Scholar

9 Frankenberg, supra note 7, at 433.Google Scholar

10 See Ashworth, A., Principles of Criminal Law 113 et seq. (5th ed. 2006).Google Scholar

11 See Beale & Safwat, supra note 4; C. C. Hartan, Unternehmensstrafrecht in Deutschland und Frankreich—Ein Rechtsvergleich angesichts europäischer Harmonisierungsbestrebungen (2006); Markus Wagner, Corporate Criminal Liability: National and International Responses, 25 Commonwealth L. Bull. 600 (1999); Markus Wagner, Commercial and Financial Fraud: A Comparative Perspective, Background Paper for the International Society for the Reform of Criminal Law 13th International Conference, The International Centre for Criminal Law Reform and Criminal Justice Policy (1999), available at http://www.icclr.law.ubc.ca/Publications/Reports/CorporateCriminal.pdf; Celia Wells, Corporate Manslaughter: A Cultural and Legal Form, 6 Crim. L.F. 45 (1995); Celia Wells, Corporate Criminal Liability in Europe and Beyond, 39 New S. Wales L. Soc'y J. 62 (2001).Google Scholar

12 See Tesco Supermarkets v. Nattrass [1972] A.C. 153 (H.L.) (appeal from Divisional Court of the Queen's Bench Division).Google Scholar

13 See Norrie, A., The Limits of Justice: Finding the Fault in the Criminal Law, 59 Mod. L. Rev. 540, 543 (1996)(connecting this to the liberal “conception of the individual as an abstract, universal subject endowed with rational action, autonomy and self-determination.”). Norrie continues by stating “[t]he individual is a unified, centred being who acts as the basis for legitimating the state, law and punishment. … The rational subject receives ‘just deserts’ from the state through law. The ‘penal equation'—crime plus responsibility equals punishment—is founded on liberal bedrock.” Norrie refers to Kant and Hegel.Google Scholar

14 See Mitsch, W., Recht der Ordnungswidrigkeiten 41 (2005); Case No. 2 BvL 2/69, 16 July 1969, BVerfGE 27, 18 (33).Google Scholar

15 See Khanna, V., Corporate Criminal Liability: What Purpose Does It Serve?, 109 Harv. L. Rev. 1477, 1490 (1996) (“Even now, Germany does not impose criminal liability on corporations.”).Google Scholar

16 Id. at 1488.Google Scholar

17 Stessens, G., Corporate Criminal Liability: A Comparative Perspective, 43 Int'l & Comp. L.Q. 493, 496–497 (1994) (emphasis added).Google Scholar

18 Id. at 493 (emphasis added).Google Scholar

20 Id. at 518.Google Scholar

21 Beale & Safwat, supra note 4, at 162.Google Scholar

22 Id. at 122 (emphasis added).Google Scholar

23 See Lagodny, O., The Case of Substantive Criminal Law Before the Bars of Constitutional Law—An Overview from the Perspective of the German Legal Order, 7 Eur. J. of Crime, Crim. L. & Crim. Just. 277, 285 et seq. (1999).Google Scholar

24 See Beale & Safwat, supra note 4, at 122 (referring to M. Pieth, Commentary on: National and International Developments: An Overview, in Criminal Responsibility of Legal and Collective Entities, 113, 116 (A. Eser & G. Heine & B. Huber eds., 1999) (“[T]he fear [of German scholars] is that [the] essential safeguard of both substantive and procedural law would be put at risk from derogations of the “principle of personal guilt or blameworthiness.”))Google Scholar

25 Id. at 139.Google Scholar

26 Wagner, supra note 11, at 10.Google Scholar

27 See e.g. Peters & Schwenke, supra note 3, at 802; T. Flessas, Aphorisms, Objects, Culture, in Nietzsche and Legal Theory, Half-written laws 105, 108 (P. Goodrich & M. Valverde eds., 2005) (“The emphasis on knowledge is intimately connected with the definition of ‘culture’ in modernity.”)Google Scholar

28 See Peters & Schwenke, supra note 3, at 802.Google Scholar

29 On early methodology, see Gutteridge, supra note 7; O. Kahn-Freund, On Uses and Misuses of Comparative Law, 37 Mod. L. Rev. 1 (1974) (reminding that in case of “transplantation” of laws to a foreign system questions about adjustment and rejection have to be asked and the context taken into account).Google Scholar

30 Frankenberg, supra note 7, at 411.Google Scholar

31 The dialecticism of continental philosophy was heavily criticised by Popper (1937) for accommodating contradiction. This seems to be one of the crucial points: Is a contradiction resolvable or does the “aporia” have to be accepted?Google Scholar

32 Named after the publications on this topic in the Utah Law Review (1997).Google Scholar

33 Berman, N., Aftershocks: Exoticization, Normalization, and the Hermeneutic Compulsion, 1997 Utah L. Rev. 281, 286 (1997) (claiming that “in face of exoticization, normalize, in the face of normalization, exoticize, in the face of the hermeneutic compulsion, formalize and fragment.”).Google Scholar

34 See Legrand, P., Comparative Legal Studies and Commitment to Theory, 58 Mod. L. Rev. 262 (1995) (stating the observation that, following his claims will “naturally take the comparatist away from the traditional approaches to comparative legal studies which … do not accept the need for theory and obstinately pursue similarity and consensus as if confined to a groove” does not help to enter a constructive dialogue with practical comparatists).Google Scholar

35 See id.Google Scholar

36 Frankenberg, supra note 7, at 439.Google Scholar

37 See Habermas, J., The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity 92 et seq. (1990) (discussing Nietzsche's and Derrida's refusal of metaphysics).Google Scholar

38 Stramignoni, I., Meditating Comparisons or the Question of Comparative Law, 4 San Diego Int'l L. J. 57, 77 (2003).Google Scholar

39 Derrida, J., Writing and Difference 360 (2006).Google Scholar

40 See generally Tanner (1994).Google Scholar

41 See Flessas, supra note 27, at 109 (stating that Nietzsche sees the “ground(s) of knowledge as flawed exactly because, instead of deriving self-knowledge through experiencing our own, individual lives, the space of knowledge is extra-life.”).Google Scholar

42 See Nietzsche, F., Beyond Good and Evil, aphorism 464 (1898) (“He who fights monsters should look into it that he himself does not become a monster. When you gaze long into the Abyss, the Abyss also gazes into you.”).Google Scholar

43 Nietzsche, F., On the Genealogy of Morals III, in Basic Writings of Nietzsche 12 (Walter Kaufmann & Peter Gay trans., 2000).Google Scholar

44 Nietzsche, supra note 43, at On the Genealogy of Morals I, 1.Google Scholar

45 This is not in a strictly historical sense, as Nietzsche considers normal historians not to be concerned about history—what is relevant for him is the “real origin,” the ahistorical but thus even more true narrative.Google Scholar

46 Nietzsche, supra note 43, at On the Genealogy of Morals III, 27. “All great things bring about their own destruction through an act of self-overcoming in the nature of, life – the lawgiver himself eventually receives the call: Submit to the law you yourself proposed.” Id.Google Scholar

47 Nietzsche, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nietzsche/.Google Scholar

48 See Yovel, J., Gay Science as Law: An Outline for a Nietzschen Jurisprudence, in Nietzsche and Legal Theory, Half-written laws 23, 25 (Peter Goodrich & Mariana Valverde eds., 2005) (“Nietzsche's prophecies, we must keep in mind, are untimely meditations. He is ‘pregnant with future’ [reference to GM II 16, not from the author].”).Google Scholar

49 See Cross Cultural Perspectivism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (showing that it can rightly be questioned if cross-cultural perspectivism is an empirical fact or merely a plausible assumption), available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/supplement1.html#crosscultperception.Google Scholar

50 One facet of a Nietzschean view onto the world is exploring the genealogy of concepts, truths, and realities. See Owen, D., Nietzsche, Re-evaluation and the Turn to Genealogy, 11 Eur. J. of Phil. 249 (2003) (providing the reasons for his genealogical approach).Google Scholar

51 Stramignoni, supra note 38, at 77.Google Scholar

52 See Teubner, G., Legal Irritants: Good Faith in British Law or How Unifying Law Ends Up in New Divergences, 61 Mod. L. Rev. 11 (1998).Google Scholar

53 See Albert, M., Capitalism against Capitalism 124 (1993) (“They are, first and foremost, egalitarian societies.”).Google Scholar

54 See T. W. Adorno & T. Y. Levin, On the Question: “What Is German?”, 36 New German Critique 121, 122 (1985).Google Scholar

55 See Albert, supra note 53, at 110, 124.Google Scholar

56 See C. Pounder & F. Kosten, Managing Data Protection 1 (2nd ed., 1994).Google Scholar

57 See Albert, supra note 53, at 100.Google Scholar

58 See Royle, E., Modern Britain: A Social History 1750–1985, 155 (1987).Google Scholar

59 See Ewald, W., Comparative Jurisprudence (I): What Was It Like to Try a Rat?, 143 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1889 (1995).Google Scholar

60 See Midgley, J., The Role of Legal History, 2 Brit. J. of L. & Soc'y 153 (1975).Google Scholar

61 M. Dübber, Book Review: Evans, Richard J., (1996) Rituals of Retribution: Capital Punishment in Germany, 1600–1987, New York, 19 Law & Hist. Rev. 449, 452 (1996).Google Scholar

62 See Kant, I., Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals (Thomas Kingsmill Abbott trans., 2007) (showing the Kantian Interpretation of human dignity)Google Scholar

63 Legrand, supra note 7, at 70 et seq.Google Scholar

64 See Iwai, K., Persons, Things and Corporations: The Corporate Personality Controversy and Comparative Corporate Governance, 47 Am. J. Comp. L. 583 (1999).Google Scholar

65 See Personal Identity, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/identity-personal/.Google Scholar

66 See Habermas, supra note 37, at 294 (calling the Kantian philosophy the “philosophy of the subject”).Google Scholar

67 See Schaber, P., Menschenwürde und Selbstachtung: Ein Vorschlag zum Verständnis der Menschenwürde, 63 Studia Philosophica, 93 (2004).Google Scholar

68 See Singer, P., Practical Ethics (2nd ed., 1994).Google Scholar

69 See id. at 90 et seq.Google Scholar

70 See Hymers, J., Not a Modest Proposal: Peter Singer and the Definition of Person, 6 Ethical Persp. 126 (1999).Google Scholar

71 See Legrand, supra note 7, at 56.Google Scholar

72 See id. at 65 (stating that Simpson said “the common law mind … is repelled by brevity, lucidity and system.”).Google Scholar

73 See id. at 67 (stating that Lord Macmillan said “the life of law has not been logic; it has been experience.”).Google Scholar

74 See id. (stating that Copper said “[t]he instinct of the civilian is to systematize. The working rule of the common lawyer is solvitur ambulando.”).Google Scholar

75 See Lacey, N., State Punishment: Political Principles and Community Values 16 et seq. (1988).Google Scholar

76 This is connected with Kant and Hegel defending a retribution theory. Also notable is also Feuerbach, who partly created German criminal law and follows an absolute justification of punishment, similar to Kant's. See Rosbach, O., Strafrecht und Gesellschaft bei Anselm von Feuerbach, Forum Historia Iuris, 1 Dec. 2000, http://www.forhistiur.de/index_de.htm.Google Scholar

77 See Lagodny, supra note 23, at 279, 282 et seq. (providing the meaning of “criminalization” in German law).Google Scholar

78 See Reiman, J., The Rich Get Richer and the Poor Get Prison (2000).Google Scholar

80 See Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations (G.E.M. Anscombe trans., 1953).Google Scholar

81 See Corporation, Merriam-Webster's Dictionary of Law, http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/corporation.Google Scholar

82 See Wells, supra note 11 (stating that the debate in Germany is about Unternehmensstrafbarkeit and not about juristische Personen); H. J. Hirsch, Strafrechtliche Verantwortlichkeit von Unternehmen, 107 Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 285 (1995) (describing the debate in Germany about Unternehmensstrafbarkeit instead of juristische Personen).Google Scholar

83 See Albert, supra note 53.Google Scholar

84 Lane, C., Changes in Corporate Governance of German Corporations: Convergence to the Anglo-American Model?, 7 Competition & Change 79, 86 (2003).Google Scholar

85 See Iwai, supra note 64.Google Scholar

86 Thus this situation in England was the case before Bentham and his utilitarianism became influential.Google Scholar

87 Bakan, J., The Corporation: The pathological pursuit of profit and power 6 et seq. (2004).Google Scholar

88 There are wrong understandings of civil law. See Bernard, T. J., The Historical Development of Corporate Criminal Liability, 22 Criminology 3 (1984). He states that they never developed the concept of juristic persons. This does not mirror reality. Albert, supra note 53, at 103 (“In the neo-American model, a company is a negotiable good like any other, whereas for the Rhine economies it is not just a commodity, but a community.”).Google Scholar

89 See Khanna, supra note 15, at 1482 et seq.Google Scholar

90 Midgley, supra note 60, at 154 (quoting Weber).Google Scholar

91 See Bernard, supra note 88 (stating that CCL evolved, even though judges did not regard it as useful). This is a naïve view onto judgments. If the concept would be unwanted, judges could have argued otherwise.Google Scholar

92 See Wells, supra note 11, at 45 et seq.Google Scholar

93 See Scholz, J. T., Enforcement Policy and Corporate Misconduct: The Changing Perspective of Deterrence Theory, 60 Law and Contemp. Probs. 253, 255 (1997).Google Scholar

94 See Khanna, supra note 15, at 1512, 1533 (showing that CCL does not lower this standard).Google Scholar

95 See Parker, J. S., Doctrine of Destruction: The Case of Corporate Criminal Liability, 17 Managerial and Decision Econ. 381, 383 (1996).Google Scholar

96 Pounder, supra note 56, at 1.Google Scholar

97 See Parker, supra note 95.Google Scholar

98 See Bernard, supra note 88 (observing that the concept grew because of the judicial interpretation of common law).Google Scholar

99 See Pounder, supra note 56, at 1.Google Scholar

100 See Stramignoni, supra note 38, at 77.Google Scholar

101 Recently Austria (Verbandsverantwortlichkeitsgesetz, since 2006) and France. See Hartan, supra note 11, at 96 et seq.Google Scholar

102 See Peters & Schwenke, supra note 3 (discussing the growing U.S. skepticism).Google Scholar

103 See Reimann & Zimmermann, supra note 1, at v.Google Scholar

104 See Hartan, supra note 11, at 12.Google Scholar