Article contents
The Idea of Early-Conflict Constitution-Making: The Conflict in Ukraine Beyond Territorial Rights and Constitutional Paradoxes
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
Abstract
Using the crisis in Ukraine and the annexation of Crimea as a foil, the aim of this article is three-fold. First, it offers an internal critique of the influential answers that normative theory and international jurisprudence provide to the paradox of constitutionalism. Second, building on critical engagement with these approaches, this article mobilizes constitutional theory to find a constructive response to the crisis in Ukraine that goes beyond the prescriptions offered either by normative theory or international jurisprudence. In doing so, it seeks to sketch a broad constitutional framework not for post but rather for early-conflict constitution-making. The final aim of this article is to contribute to a richer self-understanding of constitutional theory vis-à-vis its disciplinary neighbors.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- German Law Journal , Volume 16 , Issue 3: Special Issue - The Crisis in Ukraine , July 2015 , pp. 658 - 690
- Copyright
- Copyright © 2015 by German Law Journal GbR
References
1 The Constitution of Ukraine 1996, art. 5.Google Scholar
2 Ivison, Duncan, Pluralism and the Hobbesian Logic of Negative Constitutionalism, 47 Pol. Stud. 81, 84 (199d9).Google Scholar
3 Loughlin, Martin & Walker, Neil, The Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and Constitutional Form 4 (2007).Google Scholar
4 Id. at 3.Google Scholar
5 Id. Google Scholar
6 Catala, Amandine, Secession and Annexation: The Case of Crimea, 16 German L.J. 581, 602-03 (2015) (providing a rare direct confrontation of that difficulty from the perspective of normative political theory, stating:Google Scholar
There is indeed, to some extent, some circularity at play in the idea of self-determination and peoplehood, as several contributors to the present volume note in the context of international law and of constitutional theory, respectively: Self-determination presupposes the very self or people that is supposed to emerge from it; the constitution constitutes the people that constitutes it. But I am not sure that either logical or chronological priority is what ultimately matters here. Rather, the issue is ultimately a normative one: peoples rightfully exercising political self-determination. If what results from the mutually constituting interaction between self and determination (or between people and constitution) are institutions that track the interests of the people they are supposed to represent, then if there is any circularity, it is a virtuous rather than a vicious one. And the relevant self or people will speak up to break up the circle if it becomes vicious rather than virtuous: i.e., if it runs counter to, rather than serves, the rightful exercise of political self-determination.
7 Loughlin, Martin, Constitutional Theory: A 25th Anniversary Essay, 25 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 183, 183 (2005).Google Scholar
8 Barber, Nick, The Constitutional State 2 (2010).Google Scholar
9 Wilson, Andrew, Ukrainian Nationalism in the 1990s: a Minority Faith 164(1997).Google Scholar
10 Putin Assails West, Hails Crimea As “Sacred” Russian Land In Address, Radio Free Eur. Radio Liberty (Dec. 4, 2014), http://www.rferl.org/content/russia-putin-address-west-crimea/26724829.html.Google Scholar
11 Fear Is in The Air Among Crimean Tatars, Radio Free Eur. Radio Liberty (Mar. 2, 2014), http://www.rferl.org/content/fear-is-in-the-air-among-crimean-tatars/25282748.html.Google Scholar
12 Miller, David, Territorial Rights: Concept and Justification, 60 Pol. Stud. 252, 258 (2012).Google Scholar
13 Id. Google Scholar
14 Kuzio, Taras, Nationalism, Identity and Civil Society in Ukraine: Understanding the Orange Revolution, 43 Communist & Post-Communist Stud. 285, 291 (2010).Google Scholar
15 See Katchanovski, Ivan, Regional Political Cleavages, Electoral Behavior, and Historical Legacies in Post-Communist Ukraine, in Aspects of the Orange Revolution III: The Context and Dynamics of the 2004 Ukrainian Presidential Elections 55 (Ingmar Bredies et al. eds., 2007).Google Scholar
16 Kizilov, Mikhail, Slave Trade in the Early Modern Crimea from the Perspective of Christian, Muslim, and Jewish Sources, 11 J. Early Mod. Hist. 1, 10 (2007).Google Scholar
17 Miller, David, National Responsibility and Global Justice 214 (2009).Google Scholar
18 Meisels, Tamar, Territorial Rights 40 (2005).Google Scholar
19 “Crimea Cradle of Russian Christianity”: Key Quotes from Putin's Meeting with Historians, Russia Today (November 8, 2014), http://rt.com/news/203467-putin-speech-crimea-wwii/.Google Scholar
20 Meisels, supra note 18, at 35.Google Scholar
21 See id. at 40.Google Scholar
22 See id, at 60.Google Scholar
23 Waldron, Jeremy, Superseding Historic Injustice, 103 Ethics 4 (1992) (opposing the idea of the moral statute of limitations); see generally Roberts, Rodney, The Morality of the Moral Statute of Limitations on Injustice, 7 J. Ethics 115 (2003) (addressing the question of whether a statute of limitations on injustice is morally justified).Google Scholar
24 See Program of Retro Poroshenko Bloc (Aug. 27, 2014), http://solydarnist.org/?page_id=874.Google Scholar
25 Address by President of the Russian Federation, President of Russia (Mar. 18, 2014), http://eng.kremlin.ru/news/6889.Google Scholar
26 Solchanyk, Roman, Ukraine and Russia: The Post-Soviet Transition 145 (2001).Google Scholar
27 Paterson, Tony & Foster, Peter, Ukraine Crisis: Angela Merkel Accuses Putin of “Stealing” Crimea, The Telegraph (March 12 2014), http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/europe/ukraine/10692259/Ukraine-crisis-Angela-Merkel-accuses-Putin-of-stealing-Crimea.html; Daniel Hurst, Australia Imposes Sanctions on Russia After It “Steals” Crimea from Ukraine, The Guardian (March 19, 2014), http://www.theguardian.com/world/2014/mar/19/australia-imposes-sanctions-on-russia-after-it-steals-crimea-from-ukraine; Russia's Duma Ratifies Crimea Annexation, Radio Free Eur. Radio Liberty (March 20 2014), http://www.rferl.org/content/russia-annexation-crimea-ratification/25304008.html; Sergey Lavrov, Foreign Minister, Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Russian Federation, Speech and Answers to Questions at the 349th Extraordinary Session of the Federation Council of the Federal Assembly of the Russian Federation (Mar. 21, 2014).Google Scholar
28 Stilz, Anna, Nations, States, and Territory, 121 Ethics 572, 578 (2011).Google Scholar
29 Id. at 579.Google Scholar
30 Id. at 591.Google Scholar
31 Banai, Ayelet, The Territorial Rights of Legitimate States: A Pluralist Interpretation, 6 Int'l Theory 140, 144-46 (2014).Google Scholar
32 Stilz, supra note 28, at 592.Google Scholar
33 Nasadyuk, Irina & McGee, Robert, Tax Evasion in Ukraine: A Survey of Opinion 1, 5, 10 (2006).Google Scholar
34 Stilz, supra note 28, at 594.Google Scholar
35 See id. passim. Google Scholar
36 See Oklopcic, Zoran, Farewell to Rhetorical Arms: Unraveling the Self-Determination of Peoples, In Recognition versus Self-Determination: Dilemmas of Emancipatory Politics 101 (Avigail Eisenberg et al. eds., 2014).Google Scholar
37 See Wheatley, Steven, Modelling Democratic Secession in International Law, in Nationalism and Globalisation: New Settings, New Challenges 32 (forthcoming 2015) (arguing the peoples of Crimea, Donetsk and Lugansk do not have a right to secede, not because those populations do not have a right to self-determination or must subject themselves to the authority of the Ukrainian State, but as a consequence of the failure of the authorities and the populations to engage in reasoned, democratic deliberations concerning the allocation of political authority in the region).Google Scholar
38 Roth, Brad R., Sovereign Equality and Moral Disagreement: Premises of a Pluralist International Legal Order 81 (2011).Google Scholar
39 Id. Google Scholar
40 Id. at 100.Google Scholar
41 Id. Google Scholar
42 Id. at 184.Google Scholar
43 Id. at 274; see also, supra note 14.Google Scholar
44 Roth, supra note 38, at 24.Google Scholar
45 Id. at 204.Google Scholar
46 Id. at 205.Google Scholar
47 See Miller, Russell A., Self-Determination in International Law and the Demise of Democracy? 41 Colum. J. Transnat'l L. 601, passim (2003) (providing a skeptical account of the democratic promise of self-determination).Google Scholar
48 Roth, supra note 38, at 161.Google Scholar
49 See id. at 127.Google Scholar
50 See id. Google Scholar
51 See Franck, Thomas, Humanitarian intervention, in The Philosophy of International Law 531 (Samantha Besson & John Tasioulas eds., 2010) (providing an example of such a debate that under the cloak of juridical and normative judgments features a comparative calculus of human suffering and a dispute about what is the relevant time frame for judging the legitimacy of humanitarian intervention); see also Danila Zolo, Humanitarian Militarism?, in The Philosophy of International Law 549 (Samantha Besson & John Tasioulas eds., 2010).Google Scholar
52 Fazal, Tanisha M., State Death: The Politics and Geography of Conquest, Occupation and Annexation 230 (2011).Google Scholar
53 Id. Google Scholar
54 Id. at 239.Google Scholar
55 Id. at 232.Google Scholar
56 Id. at 234.Google Scholar
57 Id. at 234-35; see also Antony Anghie, Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law 279 passim (2004).Google Scholar
58 I am convinced this would occur even if the shape of a territory were readjusted to include localities — historically important members of the nation, currently not a part of it.Google Scholar
59 Catala, supra note 6.Google Scholar
60 Id. at 283–86.Google Scholar
61 By federalization, I mean an institutional outcome of constitution-making that would result in the creation of one or more territorial autonomies within a state which would, in turn, be represented at the central level of decision-making. I hasten to add, however, that this process need not necessarily result in a federation. The exact content of such a federal-like solution would emerge through negotiations as parties negotiate (and trade-off) the territorial extent of the autonomy, its jurisdiction, and the powers and composition of the central organs of government.Google Scholar
64 Arato, Andrew, International Role in State-Making in Ukraine; The Promise of Two-Stage Constituent Process, 16 German L.J. 691 (2015).Google Scholar
63 See Oklopcic, Zoran, Provincializing Constitutional Pluralism, 5 Transnat'l Legal Theory 331 (2014) (defending a similar claim).Google Scholar
64 Reference re Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217 (Can.).Google Scholar
65 Id. at para. 103.Google Scholar
66 See Choudhry, Sujit, Does The World Need More Canada?, 5 Int'l J. Const. L. 606 (2007) (providing a skeptical view that the world needs “more of Canada”).Google Scholar
67 I mention this because some of the current approaches in comparative constitutionalism would object to such migration on contextualist grounds, arguing that each polity's constitutional order is a unique manifestation of its culture and history. Indeed, the Secession Reference itself suggests as much as it develops the meaning of the four unwritten principles from an interpretation of the relevant episodes in early Canadian constitutional history and relevant constitutional jurisprudence. While this objection legitimately demands caution in migrating and adapting constitutional ideas, it cannot be taken as credible in its strangest form, namely that a constitutional order is an expression of a particular people's values and ideals. If my critique of territorial rights discourse has been persuasive, it would also have undermined the insistence on the legitimacy of a putative territorial people. By uncovering constituent attachments as a suppressed ideal behind the vocabulary of the people, the migration of the Secession Reference is actually justified on normative grounds—as a way to respond to this ideal, implicit among all those who believe in the idea of popular sovereignty.Google Scholar
68 See Frankenberg, Gunter, Constitutional Transfer: The IKEA Theory Revisited, 8 Int'l J. Const. L. 563 (2008) (providing a critical account of the logic of decontextualization in the migration of constitutional ideas).Google Scholar
69 2 S.C.R. 217, at para. 92.Google Scholar
70 Id. Google Scholar
71 Id. Google Scholar
72 See Oklopcic, Zoran, Anxieties of Consent: Theorizing Secession Between Constitutionalism and Self-Determination, 22 Int'l J. Minority & Group Rts. 259 (2015) (providing my further defense of this view, against the claims that “the duty to negotiate” requires secessionists to persuade other participants that the essence of their demand is legitimate).Google Scholar
73 Elecciones para cambiar la UE, El Pais, May 17, 2014 (stating that in the context of debates over the secession of Catalonia, for example, some have argued that its secession would provoke a “domino effect” in the rest of the “España invertebrada,” “spineless Spain”—a term invented by Ortega y Gasset—whose political unity has always been a precarious achievement).Google Scholar
74 2 S.C.R. 217, at para. 88.Google Scholar
75 See, e.g., Jens Bartelson, Visions of World Community 11 (2009).Google Scholar
76 See Damrosch, Lori Fisler, Politics Across Borders: Nonintervention and Nonforcible Influence over Domestic Affairs, 83 Am. J. Int'l L. 1 (1989) (providing a comprehensive survey of legitimate forms of interference from the vantage point of international law).Google Scholar
77 Krastev, Ivan, What Does Russia Want and Why?, Prospect (Mar. 6, 2014), http://www.prospectmagazine.co.uk/politics/what-does-russia-want-and-why.Google Scholar
78 While the recent antipathy towards federalism in Ukraine is exacerbated by Russia's insistence on federalism as the appropriate constitutional framework for the resolution of the conflict, its roots are deeper. The Ukrainian elite's insistence on unitary statehood can in good part be explained by its assimilation of what it has considered to be “European” political and constitutional imaginary. The “return to Europe,” as a geopolitical orientation, has entailed as its complement the adoption of what is seen as the “European” (in effect, French) constitutional form of a “unitary state,” and the repudiation of its own Soviet, federalist, constitutional heritage. Kataryna Volczuk, Catching Up with “Europe”? Constitutional Debates on the Territorial-Administrative Model in Independent Ukraine, 12 Regional & Fed. Stud. 65 (2002). Equally, federalism was rejected by invoking the alleged purpose of American federalism whose purpose was to centralize, not devolve political power. Ukraine was already a unified state, so, consequently, federalism was unnecessary. Id. at 75.Google Scholar
79 Krastev, supra note 77.Google Scholar
80 See, e.g., Knaus, Gerald & Martin, Felix, Travails of the European Raj, 14 J. Democracy 60 (2003) (giving a critique of the tutelage of the EU over Bosnia and Herzegovina).Google Scholar
81 Roth, supra note 38, at 199.Google Scholar
82 Some have defended this practice as a matter of uti possidetis rule. Others, such as Jure Vidmar, have defended it in terms of the “historical pedigree” of such units. See Vidmar, Jure, Democratic Statehood in International Law: The Emergence of New States in Post-Cold War Practice (2013).Google Scholar
83 See, e.g., Peter Radan, The Break-up of Yugoslavia and International Law (2002); see also Suzanne Lalonde, Determining Boundaries in a Conflicted World: The Role of Uti Possidetis (2002).Google Scholar
84 See Z-4 Plan for Croatia; See Draft Agreement on the Krajina, Slavonia, Southern Baranja and Western Sirmium (Z-4 Plan) (Jan. 18, 1995), http://www.liv.ac.uk/library/sca/owen/boda/sp10a.pdf.Google Scholar
85 Goodby, James, When War Won Out: Bosnian Peace Plans Before Dayton, 1 Int'l Negotiation 501, 509 (1996); see also Saadia Touval, Coercive Mediation on the Road to Dayton, 1 Int'l Negotiation 547 (1996).Google Scholar
86 See supra Part D.Google Scholar
87 See, e.g., Rompuy, Herman van, Cinq ans à la présidence du Conseil européen: Discours à Sciences Po, http://www.consilium.europa.eu/uedocs/cms_data/docs/pressdata/fr/ec/145952.pdf (“Il faudra une solution globale. Il faudra trouver une façon pour l'Ukraine d'ětre un pays décentralisé (ou fédéralisé) et inclusif.”); see also Germany's Vice-Chancellor Backs “Federalization” in Ukraine, Reuters (Aug. 23, 2014) http://www.reuters.com/article/2014/08/23/us-ukraine-crisis-germany-gabriel-idUSKBN0GN08X20140823.Google Scholar
88 Improvement in the aggregate allegiances can also be discerned from some influential approaches to consociational democracy, however. The defense of “liberal consociationalism” in the Iraqi context, offered by John McGarry and Brendan O'Leary, insists on “ensur[ing] that the rights of individuals as well as groups are protected.” John McGarry & Brendan O'Leary, Iraq's Constitution of 2005: Liberal Consociation as Political Prescription, 5 Int'l J. Const. L. 670, 675-76 (2007). But the way in which liberal constitutionalism manifests itself institutionally, on the ground, is through the constitutionalized possibility of the territorial reconfiguration of Iraq's governorates, through referenda called triggered by popular initiative. The net result of such process would be the manifestation of the same ideal—improvement in the aggregate satisfaction of individual constituent attachments over the reconstituted territory—already offered in this article as a more compelling answer to the annexation objection.Google Scholar
89 Roth, supra note 38, at 128.Google Scholar
90 Koskenniemi, Martti, National Self-Determination Today: Problems of Legal Theory and Practice, 43 Int'l & Comp. L.Q. 241, 264 (1994).Google Scholar
91 Roth, supra note 38, at 24.Google Scholar
- 1
- Cited by