1. Introduction
In the European Union (EU), legal integration faces resistance from several directions. This reality is also reflected in the study of EU law. The unifying theme of critical EU law scholarship is to problematise the role of law in the integration project. Aclassic argument in critical research on EU law is that the proactive role of law as a driver of more or deeper integration undermines political decision-making processes and democratic institutions both in the EU and in its Member States. More recently, the EU’s arduous ventures through various crises have added new layers to critical interventions. The law arguably runs into the risk of becoming reactive at best, and obsequious at worst, when rapidly escalating eventualities called for swift inter-governmental actions between the Member States in response to the financial and migration crises. The rule of law crisis within some Member States has simultaneously added a more inward-looking tenet to the EU’s crisis management. The prolonged COVID-19 outbreak, together with the EU’s pandemic recovery package, also raised the concern that the crisis mode is subtly becoming a new normalcy in the EU – a scenario which enhances the need for further critical scholarship.
It must be noted that the term ‘critical scholarship’ has various meanings. Legal scholars may deliberately engage with critique at different analytical levels, some of which go deeper into methodological questions than others.Footnote 1 On one level, all scientific research, including legal research, claims to be critical. On another level, the meaning of critical research can be narrowed down so that only projects that explicitly identify with the substantive research themes raised by the Frankfurt-style critical theory and its offspring,Footnote 2 including the Critical Legal Studies (CLS) movement, would count as critical.Footnote 3 This article concedes to neither of these claims. Different branches of the CLS movement should be of interest to EU law scholars to the extent that they ‘interrogate the deeper political, historical and philosophical logics which underpin the power of law’.Footnote 4 But reinventing EU legal studies as one subfield of CLS is not a solution to the current divisions within EU law scholarship. This is so because the challenge is more methodological than substantive. That is, the question of what critique means to EU legal studies in fact asks how EU law is and should be researched.
The central question in this article is what additional value critique can bring to the study of EU law at the time of various and prolonged crises. In answering this question, the article maintains that the methodological underpinnings of critical EU law scholarship call for a closer scrutiny and that the absence of such scrutiny undermines critique’s ability to contest and transform the law. This analysis highlights that calling research critical does not automatically make it critical from a methodological perspective and that critical EU law scholarship can learn from critical social theory in recasting critique as a method. This quest for a more elaborate critical method is important because the methodology of critique always feeds into what critique tells us about its object (ie EU law). One might assume that the strong emphasis on research that self-identifies as critical would have generated an equally strong interest in the methodology of critique in EU legal studies. However, questions concerning the critical method have gone largely unnoticed in this context. This observation applies both to the revisionist and the rejectionist strands of critique. The former refers to critical scholarship that seeks to transform and rejustify EU law. The latter describes critical interventions that focus on contesting, rather than transforming, EU law.Footnote 5
This article responds to the perceived lack of methodological engagement in critical EU law scholarship in two consecutive steps: The article first illustrates how much of the contemporary critical discourse on EU law remains confined to the so-called role of law debate, sidestepping the underlying methodological questions about the law and critique. It then explains how the necessary methodological turn in the critical study of EU law can be advanced with reference to the critical theory of society.Footnote 6 This analysis accredits critical social theory for introducing a dialectical method of critique that is not readily available in the legal-normative critique of EU law.Footnote 7 The value of critical social theory to EU law scholarship lies in clarifying what a methodologically more self-conscious normative critique of EU law looks like – both in theory and in practice.Footnote 8 This inquiry into the potential synergies between EU legal studies and the critical theory of society invites us to explore one aspect of EU law scholarship from the perspective of another discipline, that is, critical social theory. This approach has repercussions that need to be explained before proceeding any further.
First, launching a meaningful cross-disciplinary discourse requires a certain degree of familiarity with the terminology of both disciplines. Second, some concepts in social theory and philosophy are identical to legal concepts but their actual meaning is different. One key example is ‘positivism’, which means different things in law, philosophy, and sociology. The term ‘positivism’, when used in social philosophy, refers to the (contested) view that all genuine knowledge can be verified through empirical analysis and that empirically observable ‘factual’ data constitutes the only possible object of social scientific knowledge.Footnote 9 This article makes a particular effort to ensure that the terminology of critical social theory is accessible to a reader who might be curious about critical theory without being fully versed in the conceptual jargon of critical theorists. But there is no way around the fact that a meaningful engagement with critical social theory requires some willingness to expose oneself to a conceptual apparatus that may at times seem ‘too general, theoretical, and abstract’ to a legal scholar.Footnote 10 How the reader experiences this exposure is linked to a broader question of how theory is perceived in EU law scholarship – a topic that will be discussed in more detail at the end of this article.
The present article does not dismiss any of the existing critical interventions in the field of EU law. On the contrary, it seeks to complement them – looking for the ways in which EU law scholarship can further evolve in its critical ambition. Thus, the critical theory of society is not viewed as a panacea for the complex substantive issues raised by critical EU law scholars,Footnote 11 but as an instructive example of how normative critique can coexist with a heightened sensitivity to methodological and epistemological choices that underpin critical projects in law. Here epistemological claims are defined as claims about what can be known. The links between epistemology and critical methodology highlight the way in which both the critic and critique are always shaped by a preceding rationalisation of society.Footnote 12 From this perspective, it appears problematic that EU law scholarsFootnote 13 often identify the ‘critical project’Footnote 14 with the substantive content of their research – meaning that research is viewed as genuinely critical only to the extent that it is sceptical about some aspects of legal integration. In this article, placing the analytical focus on the methodology of critique indicates that it is necessary to make a clearer distinction between substantive criticism and critique as a methodological commitment in the study of EU law.
The article is structured as follows: After this introduction, Section 2 offers a short overview of how critique has gained more ground in the study of EU law in parallel with the EU’s attempts to manage its various crises. Section 3 clarifies where the alleged methodological gaps lie in the critical study of EU law. This analysis lays the groundwork for the argument that the critical project, in all its diversity, needs to be rethought in methodological terms. Section 4 considers what specific lessons EU law scholars could draw from the critical theory of society to strengthen the methodology of critique. This part of the article uses the alienation critique and the ideology critique of EU law to illustrate what a more dialectical method of critique requires from the critical study of EU law and how a methodologically more self-reflexive critique of EU law might develop. Section 5 ends the article with a discussion on how to overcome the existing obstacles to critical engagement, as discussed here. This includes considering what factors may prevent EU law scholars from adopting a cogent critical method, why even scholarship that self-identifies as critical falls short of achieving this goal, and how this could be remedied.
In the absence of a more developed critical method, competing rationalisations of society that inform the critique of EU law remain undiscussed and concealed. Here the term ‘social rationalisation’ refers to cognitive processes that make certain forms of society and social relations look normal to us and that are often partly subliminal. The critic, too, examines social reality through his/her socialisation into a particular place and time. Adeliberate engagement with such rationalisations is difficult without a more dialectical critical method, which unfolds the intersections between conceptual ideas and material reality not just in EU law, but also in its critique. Placing the critical focus on this interplay rejects any simple idea of non-normative empirical research as a solution to the methodological challenges of EU law scholarship. This means that the ‘critical turn’Footnote 15 in EU legal studies cannot be reduced to a mere empirical turn and that the critical potential of mere ‘facticity’ is always limited.Footnote 16 These findings highlight the need to integrate social theory into the critical study of EU law. As such, this article contributes to a much broader discussion on the role of socio-legal research in EU law.Footnote 17 That the rich tradition of critical social theory is still largely absent in EU law scholarship sets the field apart, for instance, from the study of international law. It is a collective task of EU law scholars to mend this rupture.
2. Crises and critique: on the growth of critical voices in EU legal studies
The growing interest in the critique of EU law can be explained by multiple factors, some of which are old and some more recent. The diversity of critical voices means that any attempt to systematise them is vulnerable to the charge of over-simplification. Aclassic argument against the ‘integration through law’Footnote 18 paradigm holds that the law cannot legitimately replace political decision-making processes in the EU.Footnote 19 From this perspective, a significant turning point in the study of EU law was when EU law scholars started to more systematically cast critical light on the progressive narratives of constitutionalisation in the EU legal order.Footnote 20 Many of the subsequent critical claims directly follow from, or were intensified by, the Eurozone crisis,Footnote 21 which triggered an intense debate on the use of crisis lawFootnote 22 and the so-called authoritarian turnFootnote 23 in the EU. These openings raise paradigmatic questions about where the political authority lies in the EU. But the financial crisis is not the only crisis that has afflicted the EU.Footnote 24 The EU’s responses to the more recent economic and humanitarian crises within and outside its borders have generated criticism that the EU legal order yields to the politics of integration with too much complacency. At the same time, the ongoing, and seemingly intensifying, rule of law crisis in some EU Member States exposes the complex interaction between political and legal dimensions of the EU’s internal crisis management strategy.
Critical EU law scholarship is divided between what can be called the rejectionist and the revisionist forms of critique. The central difference between these two approaches is how redeemable they envisage EU law. The rejectionist critique depicts EU law as potentially undemocratic by nature, whereas some of the crisis-related critical interventions call for a renewed normative justification for the law and its application in the EU. For instance, Joerges and Kreuder-Sonnen refer to ‘undemocratic processes which undermine the legal authority structures…and which are ruled by executive discretion beyond judicial review’ in their analysis of EU crisis law.Footnote 25 Simultaneously, judicial review, in general, and the post-crisis case law of the Court of Justice of the European Union, more particularly, constitute part of the problem insofar as they legitimate controversial measures and policies by EU institutions, which lack direct democratic control by EU citizens.Footnote 26 The Court’s role in justifying the actions of the European Central Bank in the so-called Weiss saga provides a recent, much-debated, example of these concerns.Footnote 27 These differences notwithstanding, both the rejectionist and the revisionist forms of critique proceed from the legitimacy of legal integration, or its legitimacy deficit, read in conjunction with the EU’s perceived democratic and justice deficits.Footnote 28 Critical scholars diverge in how they define the root causes and mutual relations of these three deficits. But contesting the present role of law in the project of European integration emerges as a major unifying theme between them.Footnote 29
EU law, in general, and EU crisis law, in more particular, have been criticised for ‘technical formalism’ and for replacing such formalism by what some authors call ‘empty functionalism’.Footnote 30 In legal theory, formalism refers to the idea that legal rules can exist and operate independent of the surrounding social and political realities.Footnote 31 Functionalism, for its part, refers to a mindset that is mainly interested in the functions that the law can serve in society. The combined critique of formalism and functionalism points to the ways in which the law arguably ‘contends itself with political obedience’ and operates as a tool for validating political and economic ‘necessities’ of European integration.Footnote 32 Critical scholars perceive a distorted relationship between the economic and political goals of integration and their implementation by legal means in the courts. Again, the Eurozone crisis is the primary example of how the analytical distinction between the law and the extra-legal has become blurred in EU law. The EU’s dealings with the COVID-19 pandemic recovery package may mirror some of these concerns – although the different circumstances also suggest a different degree of social, if not political, legitimacy.
The proximity between critique and crises in the study of EU law indicates that the role of critical scholarship is unlikely to diminish in the near future.Footnote 33 But critical interventions on and around the legitimacy of EU law are by no means limited to the EU’s response to the recent crises. EU free movement law, with its core principles of non-discrimination on grounds of nationality and market access, also raises concerns about the potentially depoliticising and alienating effects of EU law in the Member States.Footnote 34 Since much of EU citizenship law is based on a similar logic of prohibited restrictions and accepted justifications, it is likewise vulnerable to the criticism that it may have alienating effects – particularly from the perspective of those nationals of the Member States who have not exercised their right to free movement and are not direct beneficiaries of EU citizenship rights. Unlike the critique of EU crisis law, this type of critical scholarship usually depicts the EU judiciary too independent, rather than too obedient. As such, the critique of EU free movement law aligns itself with the classic opposition to the ‘integration through law’ paradigm and highlights the value of democratic politics and governance over legal interventions not just at the level of EU institutions, but also within the Member States.Footnote 35
Although few of these concerns are new as such, the seemingly perpetual cycle of crises reinforces the need to rethink the fundamentals of European integration, including what role(s) the law can and cannot assume in the EU. At the same time, it is problematic if critical scholarship fails to look beyond the confines of the traditional ‘role of law’ debate. As will be seen in the next section, this focus unhelpfully binds the critical project to the functionalist and instrumentalist paradigms, which critique seeks to attack. Afurther source of concern, also discussed in the next section, is how critical EU law scholarship exerts the analytical distinction between ‘validity’ and ‘facticity’ as a tool for critique.Footnote 36 This question about the critical potential of ‘facticity’, understood here as the realm of non-normative and empirically observable facts, is a recurring theme both in critical theory and in this article. Since our perceptions of reality are always mediated, a categorical distinction between facticity and validity may do more harm than good to the critical study of EU law. This means that the relationship between an empirical and a normative critique of EU law must be carefully rethought if the objective is to avoid these qualms.Footnote 37
To sum up, the critique of EU crisis law is not exhaustive of the breadth of critical research on EU law. But the strong links between crisis and critique mean that the recent analyses of EU crisis law offer a particularly illuminating case study of what general concerns motivate critical interventions in EU legal studies. This is so because the EU’s turn to crisis law has accentuated the existing concerns about the legitimacy of EU law. Moreover, it can safely be hypothesised that many of the methodological grievances that are visible in those branches of EU legal studies that explicitly self-identify as critical will be even more persistent in scholarship that is less articulate about its critical commitment. Although the observations made in relation to one specific field of critical EU law scholarship (ie the study of EU crisis law) cannot be generalised into the other branches of EU legal studies without a careful case-by-case consideration, they are indicative of a further research need in this area. The next section of this article will accordingly have a closer look at why the critical project in EU legal studies still appears lacking from a methodological perspective.
3. Critique vs. criticism: on the incompleteness of the critical method in EU legal studies
While it is not always easy, or even advisable, to draw a line between mainstream and critical approaches, few authors seem to disagree on the presumption that critically oriented research has a legitimate place in EU legal studies. This positive mindset towards critical scholarship is captured in the statement that critique has a ‘value all of its own’.Footnote 38 What may first sound like a truism about the value of critical scholarly engagement opens up a more difficult question of under what conditions critique will add something fruitful to the study of EU law. Classifying scholarship as critical does not automatically mean that it is critical in any analytically distinctive sense. Furthermore, calling a piece of research critical does not denote that it would be non-normative or less normative than the seemingly non-critical forms of legal scholarship. What ideally distinguishes critical from non-critical research is the critical method. This inquiry into the methodology of critique gains additional weight from the premise that, as a potential discourse of power,Footnote 39 critique plays a role in shaping social reality in which it is articulated. Therefore, it is worrying if EU law scholarship falls short of articulating what the methodological commitment to critique means. This section will set the parameters for the ensuing methodological discussion by unpacking the relationship, first, between critique and criticism and, second, between a normative and a non-normative critique of EU law.
A. What makes the critique of EU law critical?
A recent definition of the ‘critical turn’ in EU legal studies refers to ‘a growing current of thought which considers the model of integration through law a failure’.Footnote 40 There is no doubt that this characterisation is descriptively accurate. The previous section demonstrated that critical EU law scholarship, either directly or indirectly, challenges the presumption of law as a legitimate and/or effective tool for deeper integration between the Member States. This type of critique promises to redeem the law from functionalism coated in unfounded idealism. From a more positive angle, it can be seen as a first step towards redefining the role of law in the European project.Footnote 41 The charge of functionalism is commonly linked to an instrumentalising conception of law in the EU legal order.Footnote 42 As noted in Section 2, instrumentalism refers to the view that the law is justified to the extent that it serves particular policy goals. The ‘instrumentalisation of law’ may also explain the general lack of interest in methodological questions in EU legal studies.Footnote 43 But focusing on what roles the law cannot and should not have in the integration project means that critique is still defined by the traditional paradigms of European integration theory. Even when critical research seeks to rethink the fundamentals of EU law (eg its alleged functionalism and instrumentalism), it seems unable to operate outside the framework which analyses the law in terms of its effects.
The difficulties of breaking through the boundaries of the functionalist discourse not only create a paradox at the heart of critical EU law scholarship, but also risk leaving critical interventions underdeveloped by not taking notice of critique’s methodological underpinnings. Much of critical EU law scholarship operates at the level of normative political theory and legal philosophy, with little or no discussion on what other meanings could be assigned to critique. The post-Kantian idea of critical philosophy wanted to separate critique from purely justificatory arguments. In EU legal studies, however, the need for critique is often explained by the perceived lack of ‘normative vision’ and ‘theoretical foundations’ in EU law.Footnote 44 Comparing and evaluating different normative theories against one another without question forms an important part of critical EU law scholarship. But a genuinely ‘critical turn’ in EU legal studies cannot be accomplished without a more intentional and systematic engagement with the critical method. Otherwise, the risk is that qualifying research as critical simply becomes a tool for defending the author’s preferred political theory of the EU and its Member States against other feasible, but allegedly non-critical, normative-theoretical approaches to European integration.
Moreover, the critical study of EU law often presents itself as capable of straightforwardly uncovering the potentially harmful effects of EU law. As such, it seems to imply that a purely unmasking critique is possible. This framing of critique appears questionable if we take even half-seriously the argument that ‘[c]ritique is always motivated’.Footnote 45 It is not enough to argue that critique is needed to expose the possible ideology of EU law. On the contrary, it is equally important to explore the potentially ideational, or even ideological, elements of critique itself. Abasic definition of ideology is a system of ideas, ideals, or beliefs. But the term ‘ideology’ is often used with a more negative connotation to describe how the dominant social groups use their particular ideas to maintain and justify their power over other groups in society. The term ‘ideational’ can be used as a less politically charged alternative to ‘ideological’. These observations about unmasking critique also apply to a rejectionist critique of EU law, which no longer looks for a revised normative justification for legal integration. Probing into the underlying rationalisations of critique is nevertheless difficult without a more developed critical method. Here the nodus is not that critique is inherently normative (as it often is), but that its normativity becomes concealed when critique lacks adequate methodological reflexivity.
From this perspective, it appears problematic that the critical motif in EU law scholarship is commonly equated to the substance of research, that is, to whether a given piece of scholarship adopts a negative or sceptical view on European legal integration. This is illustrated in how the term ‘fundamental critique’ is used to describe how rejectionist critique is, that is, how uncompromisingly it argues that EU law has harmful effects either at the level of the EU’s own institutions and governance or within the Member States.Footnote 46 While substantive criticism has a valid place in the study of EU law, it would be unsatisfactory to discern the growing interest in critical research as a mere raise of scepticism amongst EU law scholars. For instance, Geoffrey Samuel points out that ‘methodology and the source of knowledge cannot be divorced’ and ‘[t]o take the methods seriously is to take knowledge (epistemology) seriously’.Footnote 47 Here the term ‘epistemology’ refers to what can be known and why. That the link between methodology and epistemology has not received sufficient attention in EU legal studies means that critique is frequently assimilated with criticism, without considering what further criteria define a fully developed critical method. Moreover, as will be seen in the next part of this section, recourse to supposedly non-normative, quantitative and qualitative, empirical research cannot alone fill these methodological gaps in the normative critique of EU law. Empirical critique, while important, comes with its own baggage of often unpronounced assumptions of social reality.
B. The complex relationship between a non-normative and a normative critique of EU law
The rise of empirical research methods in the study of EU law owes to the earlier scholarship, which demonstrated that political science research in the European Studies movement needs to integrate the study of legal integration into its research agenda.Footnote 48 But it is clear that the empirical analysis of European law also has value that is independent of political science. EU environmental law scholarship offered an early example of how a critical sociological perspective confronted the more traditional narratives and conceptions of EU law.Footnote 49 The sociological analysis challenged the dominant view of law ‘as formal, relatively autonomous and instrumental in character’ in the study of EU law.Footnote 50 In particular, it promised to ‘distinguish more clearly between questions about the nature of law and its role in EU integration’.Footnote 51 By now, the use of empirical sociological and socio-legal research methods has expanded from environmental regulation to several other fields of EU law.Footnote 52 While a sociological critique can have significant implications for how legal integration is theorised,Footnote 53 socio-legal research on EU law primarily draws on the quantitative or qualitative primary data, rather than on social theory.Footnote 54 Because descriptive research designs tend to leave the relationship between normative and non-normative critique unexplored, they also leave the methodological turn for critical EU law scholarship unfulfilled.
A non-normative critique promises to describe social reality without making any normative-evaluative claims. The so-called new or critical history of European law provides a prominent example of how the critique of EU law can learn from other disciplines, while simultaneously reflecting the difficult relationship between a non-normative and a normative critique of EU law.Footnote 55 The historical study of legal institutions and practices applies the non-normative methods of historical analysis to the study of EU law. Here the promise is that the study of primary archival sources ‘significantly amends the conventional understanding of the legal dimension of European integration as reflected in the work of legal scholars and social scientists’.Footnote 56 Yet, in critical history, the analysis often takes a normative turn at the end: what distinguishes critical history from other forms of historiography is that critical history extends from the descriptive to the interpretative analysis of empirical findings. One example of this is when the history of European law is interpreted through the lens of ‘judicialisation’.Footnote 57 As soon as the critical focus moves from describing archival sources to their normative-interpretative analysis, the above questions about the critical method will resurface. This is why the critical history of EU law should pay attention to the ongoing discussion on the limits of history as a tool for critique in international law.Footnote 58
These observations about sociological and historical critiques of EU law explain why the use of empirical research methods cannot replace the search for a more developed critical method in the study of EU law. This is so because the idea of a purely descriptive, non-normative critique is an oxymoron. When the findings of empirical research are used to advance the critical project, the critic faces a set of methodological questions that are not different from methodological and epistemological challenges that foil a purely unmasking critique of EU law. It has been noted that socio-legal research often lacks ‘a sophisticated approach to the complexity of interactions between legal and extra-legal practices’.Footnote 59 The lack of social-theoretic analysis is particularly problematic for EU law scholarship because the relationship between EU law and its social, political, and economic contexts is meant to carry so much explanatory weight in the critique of EU law. If these relationships remain under-theorised, that will undermine the credibility of critical EU law scholarship.
The limits of non-normative empirical research bring us back to the question of how ‘facticity’ and ‘validity’ interact in the critique of EU law.Footnote 60 When critical EU law scholars contrast the law with political, economic, or social facts, they often draw on what counts as the ‘external’ tension between facticity and validity in the Habermasian account of modern law.Footnote 61 The non-normative analyses of EU law go further to expose what Habermas calls the ‘internal’ tension between facticity and validity in the law: ‘the facticity of the enforcement of law is intertwined with the legitimacy of a genesis of law that claims to be rational’.Footnote 62 For Habermas, however, the internal tension between facticity and validity is not limited to the law, but the ideational element of validity has its origins in the forms of language and communication.Footnote 63 In other words, claims to validity, understood as rationality, form an integral part of all social relations (not just legal relations) that are based on linguistic interaction. This short glimpse of Habermas’ thought further supports the argument that, for the purposes of EU law scholarship, the critical method cannot be purely descriptive and that the crucial question is how critical EU law scholars navigate the entanglement between facticity and validity not just in law, but also in critique.
To sum up, the visible growth in critical scholarship is not yet matched with a sufficiently developed methodology of critique in the study of EU law. Arevisionist critique, which calls for a renewed normative-theoretical vision of EU law, would benefit from contemplating the facticity of law itself, that is, the ways in which the world of social, political, and economic facts is not external to the law. Amore rejectionist critique of EU law, for its part, cannot hide behind the veil of facticity but needs to encounter the normative-ideational dimension of the critical project itself. These blind spots in different types of critical interventions go unnoticed insofar as the focus on substantive criticism eclipses methodological and epistemological choices that shape critique from the outset. The relevant methodological openings, such as critical history or sociological critique, raise important questions about how EU law is researched. Because these approaches tend to remain confined to specific sub-fields of EU law, their contribution to a broader debate on the methodology of critique in EU legal studies is not yet fully visible. Moreover, the critical potential of empirical socio-legal research on EU law is hindered by the lack of engagement with social theory. With these concerns in mind, the next section will consider what methodological lessons the normative critique of EU law could draw from critical social theory.
4. Enhancing the critical method in EU legal studies: a view from critical social theory
Theoretical socio-legal study is still underrepresented in EU legal studies and its elision is particularly problematic for the critical study of EU law. Social theory is a broad and diverse sphere of study – and so is critical theory as one of its branches. Social theory investigates the nature of society by combining theoretical and empirical analyses of social conditions. One definition of social theory is ‘systematic, historically informed and empirically oriented theory seeking to explain the nature of the “social”’.Footnote 64 The social, for its part, can be defined as ‘the general range of recurring forms, or patterned features, of interactions and relationships between people’.Footnote 65 Questions posed by social theory become relevant from the perspective of EU law as soon as we accept the claim that ‘[l]aw presupposes a conception of the social’.Footnote 66 Although sociological analyses cannot account for the ‘inner’ normativity of the law, they play an important role in clarifying how this normativity is generated and sustained at different times and in different places.Footnote 67 Here the law’s sociality refers to how ‘socio-historical contexts of law and other institutions’ give rise to normative content.Footnote 68 Social theory provides a lens through which this question can be examined in the study of EU law. But it also highlights the complexity of this task because social reality is neither pregiven nor purely material but is shaped by a complex web of social rationalisations.
The previous section demonstrated how the lack of adequate methodological engagement conveys a problematic presumption of neutrality and objectivity, that is, ‘facticity’, in the critical project in EU law. This charge was brought against both the theoretical and the empirical forms of unmasking critique. As a way out of this impasse, this section will discuss how critical social theory can enrich the methodology of critique in EU law scholarship. This analysis will first briefly explain what it means to discern critical social theory as a method of critique, rather than as a comprehensive substantive theory of society. It will then introduce the dialectical method of critique, as it emerges from the critical theory of society. The central question in this section is what these methodological insights can add to the critical study of EU law. Two examples, the alienation critique and the critique of ideology, clarify how a more dialectical mode of critique can elucidate critique’s underlying social rationalisations. Areader who disdains anything resembling abstract theory may want to skip Section 4.B. This, however, would leave the emerging picture of critical dialectics incomplete.
A. Critical social theory as a method
This article views the critical theory of society as a method, rather than as a comprehensive theory of society. This qualification is important because it allows us to draw on critical social theory, without succumbing to its more problematic claims about society and social rationality. Developing both empirically and philosophically grounded theory was central to critical theory from the outset.Footnote 69 The main focuses of social critique were political economy, social psychology, and cultural theory. The interdisciplinary research agenda of the early Frankfurt School critical theory held that philosophical reflection cannot be dissociated from social reality, although it cannot be reduced to a mere description of social reality either.Footnote 70 This approach resulted in a critique of positivism in social sciences,Footnote 71 and in an equally strong critique of idealismFootnote 72 in philosophy.Footnote 73 This type of social critique required a ‘philosophical-historical’ starting point that could locate theory in the ‘historical process’.Footnote 74 In the early stages of critical theory, this was a materialist (Marxist) account of history, as opposed to the idealist (Hegelian) theory of history. Acommon vantage point in different branches of critical theory was to view late capitalism as an expression of distorted social rationality.Footnote 75
A strictly materialist theory of society came with a set of reductive philosophical and historical assumptions. First, the early critical theory generated ‘closed functionalism’ in social analysis and obscured the line between descriptive and prescriptive analysis.Footnote 76 For instance, Axel Honneth argues on this basis that ‘the basic historical-philosophical and sociological assumptions of the Frankfurt School can no longer be defended’.Footnote 77 Second, the early critical theory failed to address questions concerning gender and race. As Honneth notes, it is important to recognise the unique methodological bequest of critical theory, while maintaining distance from its more problematic claims about social rationality.Footnote 78 For it is not the reductionist materialism of the early critical theory, but its understanding of the critical method, which can contribute to the study of EU law. This is not to say that the analysis of EU law cannot benefit from the materialist theories of society, as is demonstrated by the recent scholarship on the ‘material constitution’ both in the EUFootnote 79 and beyond.Footnote 80 But neither the material nor the ideational analysis of social reality is adequate on its own because there is a constant interplay (and mutual dependence) between the two.
The central role of methodological questions in critical social theory is captured in the statement that: ‘Critical theory, after all, is not a homeland but a method. It is a strategy of reflection that aims to trouble all forms of untroubled cathexis [emotional investment] – even the cathexis with critical theory itself.’Footnote 81 The point is not that social critique would be non-normative – on the contrary, it is openly normative. The major difference in comparison to the legal-normative critique of EU law is that, in its normativity, critical social theory appears more reflexive and, thus, methodologically more developed than critical EU law scholarship. The next part of this section will clarify this by exploring in more detail the following methodological commitments within the critical theory of society: the co-existence of meta-critique and critique’s immanence, the role of mediation and contingency in social critique, and the negativity of critical dialectics. The crucial question for this article is how critical dialectics can strengthen the critical method in the study of EU law. The subsequent part of this section will seize this question with a particular focus on the alienation critique and the ideology critique as two tentative examples of how the critique of EU law can build on the methodological commitments of critical theory.
B. Re-assembling the critical method for EU law: the four components of critical dialectics
What differentiates the critical theory of society methodologically from other branches of social theory? And in which sense can critical social theory steer the critique of EU law? The dialectical method of critique is based on ‘the ongoing determination of the relation, opposition, and necessary connection’.Footnote 82 It will be introduced by explaining why the commitment to metacritique, critique’s immanence, contingency, and negativity are so important to critical theory and how these methodological dispositions frame the relationship between theory and practice. But before having a closer look at the methodology of critical dialectics, it is important to reiterate that critical theory is particularly interested in, and sensitive to, interactions between ideas and materiality. In the end, the dialectical method of critique helps us to discern how social rationalisations are always embedded in particular social realities – and viceversa. This finding is important because it has direct implications for what type of validity claims critique can make. The dialectical method of critique defies both the theoretical and the empirical versions of purely unmasking critique in the study of EU law. This means that the critique of EU law will need to reconsider its validity claims if it strives for a more dialectical mode of critique.
The first key component of critical dialectics is that a methodologically sound critique requires metacritique. The aim of metacritique is ‘to develop a self-reflexive examination. .. of the conditions for the possibility of a critical inquiry’.Footnote 83 This type of critical self-reflexivity is not prominent in critical EU law scholarship at the moment.Footnote 84 This is problematic because the lack of metacritique may easily produce a misleading idea of purely unmasking critique, which remains oblivious both to the epistemological and the ideational underpinnings of critique. Metacritique is driven by the idea that ‘every epistemology is determined by a normative commitment to how the world ought to be’.Footnote 85 The exercise of metacritique seeks to clarify this underlying ‘normative commitment’ and ‘its entanglement in a host of social conditions that would remain otherwise obscured’.Footnote 86 It is important to integrate a meta-critical perspective into the critique of EU law. However, in critical theory, the argument for metacritique comes with a further qualification: metacritique is not universally applicable but requires a conception of social rationality. Critical theory accordingly links the possibility of meaningful metacritique to critique’s immanence.
The second key component of critical dialectics is critique’s immanence. The notion of immanent critique derives the standards of critique from social practices that are critiqued.Footnote 87 In other words, these standards are viewed as internal to the object of critique. Ametacritique that is aware of its immanence needs to consider whether critique always requires prior identification with the ‘existing value horizon’.Footnote 88 That the question about critique’s immanence remains largely unaddressed in the critical study of EU law creates a stark contrast with the critical method in social theory.Footnote 89 This is clearly an area where critical theory can show the way for EU law scholars – although it does not offer any easy answers in this context. The immanence of critique does not automatically exclude ‘context-transcending’ claims of validity. In critical theory, the term ‘context-transcendence’ refers to normative propositions that ‘are at once immanent to the sociocultural context in question and transcend it’.Footnote 90 But recourse to context-transcendent claims creates a difficult justification problem at the heart of critical theory.Footnote 91 Critical theory has not always succeeded in solving this justification problem although connecting an immanent critical project with a context-transcending concept of rationality is what distinguishes critical theory from other forms of social critique.Footnote 92
One way forward is to reframe metacritique as a genealogical critique, which explores how normative ideas change over time and how these ‘shifts of meaning’ affect different social groups.Footnote 93 In the context of European integration, a genealogical critique can explore, for instance, how the ideas of democracy, equality, or constitution have changed over the course of the integration project and what implications these changes have from the perspective of varied social groups. Different offspring of critical theory agree that social reality is contingent – and that this claim of contingency also applies to concepts that describe social reality.Footnote 94 This is yet another area where critical EU law scholarship can fruitfully draw on critical social theory. Max Horkheimer’s early distinction between traditional and critical theory proceeded from the claim that ‘the facts which our senses present to us are socially preformed’.Footnote 95 T. W. Adorno, another key figure in the early critical theory, held that ‘[t]here is nothing that is not transmitted’.Footnote 96 This premise about the mediated (or ‘transmitted’) nature of social reality is methodologically important because it highlights that critique remains trivial unless it comes into terms with its social embeddedness.Footnote 97 From this perspective, the normative critique of EU law needs to more explicitly articulate and defend its underlying social rationalisations.
The third key component of critical dialectics is accordingly the principle of mediation and the related claim to contingency. Insofar as all ‘meanings are mediated’, social analysis necessarily includes ‘interpretation’ instead of ‘passive endorsement’.Footnote 98 Amajor concern both in the revisionist and the rejectionist analyses of EU crisis law is that the law has become a tool for political necessity. This concern refers to the ways in which the legal form is used to legitimise and justify the EU’s various external and internal crisis management strategies. When critical scholarship points to the ‘death of law in facticity’,Footnote 99 it uses vocabulary that is familiar to critical social theory. In critical theory, however, the principle of mediation also problematises the very idea of ‘facticity’Footnote 100 or ‘givenness’.Footnote 101 In Adorno’s thought, placing the critical focus on the non-conceptual reality results in materialism, understood as the object’s ‘primacy’ over subjective reason.Footnote 102 But the central role of mediation in social critique simultaneously helped Adorno to avoid ‘naïve realism’Footnote 103 and to maintain the possibility of a critical subject.Footnote 104 In other words, the mediated nature of the social calls for a critical analysis of facticity itself – as opposed to using facticity as a self-explanatory critical lens.
For instance, Brian O’Connor observes that ‘Adorno regards the notion of a “social” given as thoroughly suspicious’.Footnote 105 For Adorno, the principle of mediation expressed a reciprocal relationship between the subject (ie the critic) and the object (ie reality).Footnote 106 At the same time, the ‘otherness’ of the object (ie its facticity) countered any totalising vision of conceptual reasoning over the object.Footnote 107 The way in which Adorno questioned the unity of the subjective/conceptual reason and the objective reality provides an example of how mediation operates as a methodological tool in social critique.Footnote 108 This reinforces the claim that the methodological gaps within critical EU law scholarship cannot be filled by a descriptive, supposedly non-normative, critique (eg sociology and history) alone because the way in which social facts and practices are framed always depends on theoretical and epistemological assumptions that underpin such studies. In facing this challenge, the non-normative critique of EU law also needs to more explicitly articulate and defend its underlying social rationalisations.
The fourth key component of critical dialectics is its negativity. The negativity of critical dialectics seeks to ‘identify distortions, inversions, pathologies, illusions, paradoxes, contradictions, and crises’.Footnote 109 Negative dialectics hopes to avoid ‘essentialist theorisation’.Footnote 110 It does so by asserting that negative concepts do not require ‘pure’ or ‘positive’ versions of these same concepts.Footnote 111 The term ‘essentialism’ refers to a mode of thinking that reifies social identities (eg nationality or gender) as essential characteristics of people who belong to those groups. In contrast to Hegel’s ‘dialectical overcoming of difference’, negative dialectics aims at ‘sustaining difference and negativity rather than seeking their premature reconciliation’.Footnote 112 The important point from the perspective of this article is that negativity in critical social theory is first and foremost a methodological standpoint – although it is often misunderstood as a substantive disposition.Footnote 113 In EU law scholarship, the distinction between substantive and methodological negativism becomes blurred when the methodological commitment to critique is confused with substantive criticism. This is problematic because substantive criticism often operates in ways that would be labelled as ideological by critical social theory.Footnote 114 This point will be discussed in more detail in the next part of this section.
Negative dialectics dismisses any totalising attitude over the object of critique. As such, it raises the question of how EU law as an object of study relates to the critical observer. This question is closely linked to the relationship between theory and practice in critical social theory and, also, in critical EU law scholarship. The ‘unity’Footnote 115 of theory and practice is generally regarded as a central characteristic of critical social theory.Footnote 116 It implies that social critique cannot be separated from the need of social emancipation and change. The negative dialectical method rejects any simplistic vision of the ‘political realization’ of theory.Footnote 117 But critical theory cannot abandon the ‘confidence in the critical potentialities of human reason’ to the same extent as, for instance, poststructuralist or postmodern philosophy does.Footnote 118 Peter Gordon points out in his reading of Adorno that: ‘The primacy of the object. .. entails the persistence of the subject who confronts it. This subject. .. remains the only source of critical resistance against [philosophical] positivism.’Footnote 119 Axel Honneth, for his part, emphasises that: ‘Without a realistic concept of “emancipatory interest” that puts at its center the idea of an indestructible core of rational responsiveness on the part of subjects, this critical project will have no future.’Footnote 120
Similarly, the critique of EU law cannot avoid the difficult questions of what it means to reconcile the ‘diagnostic’ and ‘transformative’ aims of critique and whether the two can ever be meaningfully separated without annihilating the critical project as a whole.Footnote 121 The critique of EU law remains methodologically incomplete insofar as it builds on the idea of a purely unmasking critique – whether theoretical or empirical. It has been noted that ‘[a] method means a path: not the path that a thinker follows but the path that he/she constructs. . .’ and that ‘[e]xamining a method thus means examining how idealities are materially produced’.Footnote 122 This reference to materially produced idealities highlights that the critical project never exists in a vacuum but is always shaped by the same social dynamics that form its object. Ametacritical standpoint that is aware of its own immanence, the recognition of the mediated/contingent nature of social facts, and the negativity of critical dialectics enable critical research to come into terms with its social embeddedness. But how could the critical study of EU law operationalise these seemingly very abstract methodological positions? And what difference would that make? The next part of this section will explore these questions in more detail.
C. From an unmasking to a dialectical critique of EU law: two examples
The idea of ‘contestability’ is one of the guiding normative premises in critical theory. This means that the critical project has failed methodologically and intellectually as soon as it seems to reach a conclusion, beyond which no critical reflection is required. In practice, the underdeveloped methodology of critique leaves the critique of EU law to drift between Scylla and Charybdis, that is, between epistemological and cognitive authoritarianism, on the one hand, and philosophical and sociological positivism, on the other hand. In this context, epistemological authoritarianism refers to ‘restriction of knowledge of what counts as a rational interest to the epistemically privileged theorist’.Footnote 123 This warning against the hazards of authoritarianism may sound familiar to many EU law scholars, taking into account the recent discussion on latent authoritarian tendencies in the project of European integration.Footnote 124 While recourse to the law as a means of integration may be susceptible to turning democratic politics into ‘authoritarian liberalism’,Footnote 125 the unmasking critique of EU law is vulnerable to more subtle forms of epistemological authoritarianism. Therefore, it is important to consider how the critique of EU law could develop in a non-authoritarian way, without collapsing into reductionist philosophical and sociological positivism.
The alienation critique and the ideology critique provide two concrete examples of how a more deliberate engagement with critical dialectics can help the critique of EU law to navigate these pitfalls. These examples were selected because of ‘alienation’ and ‘ideology’ are familiar concepts both in critical EU law scholarship and in the critical theory of society. The alienation critique has its focus on how the individual subject relates both to itself and to the world, whereas the critique of ideology examines EU law from a more systemic/structural perspective. The alienation critique essentially asks ‘does EU law alienate citizens of the Member States?’ and, if so, ‘how does it alienate them?’ The ideology critique asks ‘does EU law have an ideology?’ and, if so, ‘what is that ideology?’ These two examples clarify what needs to change if critical EU law scholars seek to follow the methodological commitments of critical theory, as discussed in the previous part of this section. However, this discussion can only scratch the surface of what the methodological shift from an unmasking critique towards a dialectical critique means in practice.Footnote 126
Example I: The alienation critique of EU law
Alienation is a theme that recurs in critical EU law scholarship with some frequency but is not yet fully theorised. On the one hand, the concept of alienation is used as a seemingly self-explanatory critical device with little or no discussion on what it means in EU law. On the other hand, contributions that engage in discussing alienation in more detail do not necessarily do justice to the full potential of alienation critique in EU law scholarship. Both lapses are arguably due to the underdeveloped methodology of critique. In everyday language, alienation can be defined as ‘estrangement’ and ‘withdrawal’.Footnote 127 But alienation is also ‘the key concept of diagnoses of the crisis of modernity and one of the foundational concepts of social philosophy’.Footnote 128 For this reason, the alienation critique of EU law provides a particularly illuminating example of how critical dialectics can enrich the study of EU law.
The roots of alienation critique can be traced back to the Marxist tradition of social theory and to existential philosophy. Both the Marxist and the existentialist forms of alienation critique explore how self-alienation and social alienation are intertwined.Footnote 129 However, they offer profoundly different answers to this question.Footnote 130 The classic existential definition of alienation is presented by Sartre in Being and Nothingness.Footnote 131 For existentialists, the experience of self-alienation stems from our freedom to choose what meanings we give to life.Footnote 132 At the same time, alienation from others is viewed as unavoidable because consciousness arguably resists the way in which it is seen by others in inter-subjective relations.Footnote 133 The existential concept of alienation is often commended for how it explains the experience of self-alienation. But existential philosophy and critical social philosophy diverge on what role they assign to an ‘unalienated’ condition in the alienation critique. The existential accounts of alienation imply that alienation constitutes a diversion from authentic experience.Footnote 134 For critical theory, the existential critique of alienation is problematic insofar as it depicts political and social life as a cause of alienation.Footnote 135 These differences are not just substantive but also methodological. Therefore, the way in which the alienation critique of EU law develops has broader relevance to critical EU law scholarship.
EU citizenship and free movement law is the main context for the alienation critique in EU law scholarship. It was noted early on that:
These very values, which find their legal and practical expression in, e.g., enhanced mobility, the breakdown of local markets, and the insertion of universal norms into domestic culture, are also part of the deep modern and post-modern anxiety of European belongingness and part of the roots of European angst and alienation [italics added]. Ameaningful concept of European citizenship must address this paradox.Footnote 136
The presumed link between European citizenship and alienation is also established in the following statement:
The social legitimacy that citizenship case-law lends to the EU in some groups may be more than matched by alienation that it will inspire [italics added] in others. Moreover, the asymmetry between the capacity of the Court to present the underlying values and vision of this part of EU law so powerfully, and its inability to articulate or recognise the underlying values and visions of national measures when these are challenged, is striking.Footnote 137
Neither of these examples develops the theme of alienation further. However, a more detailed account of alienation in the study of EU law is provided by Alexander Somek.Footnote 138 Because Somek’s study on alienation is one of the few attempts, if not the only one, to dig deeper into the meaning of alienation in EU law, this section will use it as a basis for discussing how the alienation critique of EU law would benefit from a more dialectical method of critique.
Somek defines alienation both as ‘the experience of a lack or loss of free agency’ and as ‘the emotional recognition that the free agency is unavailable that is possible under conditions of social freedom’.Footnote 139 Somek observes in this context that ‘[i]t remains an open question, however, whether structures of social freedom are part of the ethos of the European Union and of its law.’Footnote 140 Somek, with reference to Marx, defines rights that individuals derive from EU law as ‘the rights of the egoistic man, of man separated from other men and from the community’.Footnote 141 Following Marx, Somek also links alienation to the relations of economic power: ‘[t]he root cause of alienation is that it is inherent in economic power to transform all economic relations into struggles over economic power.’Footnote 142 How economic power is generated arguably explains why ‘[a]lienation from others is the root of self-alienation’.Footnote 143 This is so because ‘the pursuit of economic power forces one to be indifferent to one’s own needs’.Footnote 144 However, as will be shown in this section, economic power alone is too narrow a perspective here. In addition to the economic relations of power, another key theme in Somek’s analysis of alienation is that of sociality.
The experience of alienation makes individuals ‘aware of the false realisation of human sociality’.Footnote 145 For Somek (and Marx), this observation about human sociality translates into a search for a ‘true community’: ‘Through our explicit embrace of our sociality the true community (das wahre Gemeinwesen) would appear before us in virtue of reflective insight.’Footnote 146 The quest for a ‘true community’ is contrasted with a ‘community in alienated form’.Footnote 147 Somek is aware that this vision of a ‘true community’ is vulnerable to the charge of essentialism.Footnote 148 However, instead of looking for a methodologically less essentialist theory of alienation, Somek states that:
This point may even have to be conceded inasmuch as a certain structure of interaction is deemed appropriate to human flourishing. But it does not entail the belief that individuals are the owners of some inner essence that becomes eclipsed by forms of system integration.Footnote 149
Be that as it may, the proposition that the ‘community in alienated form’ is ‘challenged through the anticipation of a community in non-alienated form’Footnote 150 has an essentialist tone. Besides the essentialist vision of a true and non-alienated community, Somek’s account of alienation problematically links social freedom to a communitarian ethos of sociality.
Somek emphasises that his preferred approach to alienation ‘is essentially conservative, not only because it leaves the market principally in place, but because it looks back to traditions of de-commodified human dealings’.Footnote 151 He mentions Michael Walzer’s communitarianism as one representative of the proposed approach.Footnote 152 Somek, now drawing on Hegel, envisages that ‘individual freedom can be “actual” only if it fits into an already existing social world’ and that ‘the participants in such an institutional setting recognise their mutual dependence and embrace it either affectionately or in a spirit of loyalty and solidarity’.Footnote 153 While Iagree with Somek on the importance of a social/relational perspective on human agency,Footnote 154 Ifind his approach to intersubjective dynamics problematic. The communitarian ideal of a ‘true community’ offers an oddly idealised picture of human social relations.Footnote 155 It can even be asked whether ‘traditions of de-commodified human dealings’Footnote 156 have ever existed, taking into account the human capacity for greed, envy, and egoism. This relates to the earlier observation that placing the analytical focus on economic power relations may easily result in a one-sided picture of both individual and social alienation.
To sum up, the alienation critique of EU law can be problematised on more than one axis: First, confining the analysis of alienation to economic power ignores other potentially relevant power relations. Second, externalising the source of alienation to the processes of commodification may produce an incomplete picture of what constitutes alienation both in relation to the self and in relation to the world. Third, the opposition between a ‘true community’Footnote 157 and a ‘community in alienated form’Footnote 158 gives the alienation critique a problematic essentialist tone. This essentialism is further developed in the communitarian vision of social freedom. On top of these observations, there is a parallel tendency in critical EU law scholarship to use the term ‘alienation’ without any attempt to theorise it. By way of provisional conclusion, it can be argued that the alienation critique either remains under-theorised or presents a series of problematic assumptions about social relations and power. But the purpose of this discussion is not to revisit the alienation critique of EU law in substantive terms. Instead, the critique of alienation is used here as an example of how a dialectical method of critique would remodel the critique of EU law.
If the alienation critique of EU law remains incomplete, how would a more dialectical method of critique ameliorate this? This can be clarified by having a closer look at how contemporary critical theory deals with alienation. Rahel Jaeggi’s book Alienation provides an instructive example of this. Jaeggi wants to challenge essentialism that ‘haunts’ the conception of alienation.Footnote 159 By essentialism, she refers to the substantive ideas of the nature and essence of the human being that characterise the idea of an unalienated condition.Footnote 160 In Jaeggi’s view, any such ‘theory of good life’ is vulnerable to the ‘charge of paternalism’.Footnote 161 Jaeggi redefines alienation as a failure to ‘appropriate’, that is, to make one’s life one’s own.Footnote 162 For her, the experience of self-alienation does not follow from ‘a falling away from one’s essence’ but, rather, it equals to ‘a disturbed relation to our own actions, desires, projects, or beliefs’.Footnote 163 From this perspective, establishing ‘a relation of appropriation’ to self and the world becomes a means of overcoming alienation.Footnote 164 Jaeggi maintains that this type of self-realisation is only possible ‘in relation to the social and material worlds’.Footnote 165 However, she argues that these relations require ‘conceptual clarification’Footnote 166 and moving away from ‘essentialist conceptions of self and community’.Footnote 167
Jaeggi’s alienation critique maps how relations of appropriation are ‘disturbed’.Footnote 168 The methodological negativism of this exercise seeks to clarify the ‘character’ of appropriated relations.Footnote 169 Here the negativity of critique entails that ‘the positive. .. can only be determined through the mediation of what should not be’.Footnote 170 Jaeggi suggests that analysing ‘successful and disturbed or deficient relations to self and world’ provides a necessary basis for studying social conditions, institutions, and practices.Footnote 171 Jaeggi, like Somek, views solidarity as ‘the opposite of social alienation’.Footnote 172 But she maintains that ‘[t]he rich social and ethical dimension of alienation critique can be made accessible without the strongly objectivistic interpretive scheme that is frequently associated with it’.Footnote 173 Thus, Jaeggi’s account of social solidarity differs from the more essentialist account of a ‘true community’ in the alienation critique of EU law. Jaeggi’s non-essentialist account of appropriation, together with her negative method, also calls into question the conservative idea that ‘appropriation is always to be understood as a reappropriation of something that already exists’.Footnote 174
Jaeggi’s non-essentialist theory-building is interesting from the perspective of European integration because the EU cannot compete with Member States in essentialist terms. However, for the purposes of the present article, the important question is not whether Jaeggi’s account of alienation is suitable for studying alienation in contemporary European societies. For instance, it can be argued that Jaeggi’s analysis of social institutions remains underdeveloped.Footnote 175 Neither was the aim of this brief discussion to fix the meaning of alienation for the study of EU law. Instead, this inquiry into the essentialist and the non-essentialist versions of alienation critique offered just one tentative example of how critical dialectics can change the critique of EU law. The alienation critique of EU law currently circumvents the more methodological questions about whether an unalienated condition is ever possible and how our preferred conception of unalienated life is always contingent, rather than pregiven. Ametacritical standpoint reopens these questions in the study of EU law. The negativity of critique, together with the principle of mediation, further clarifies how any substantive theory of authentic life is preceded by a choice between competing social rationalisations.Footnote 176 This inquiry into the alienation critique also illustrates how difficult it is to demarcate between the substance and the methodology of critique. But that reinforces, rather than dispels, the argument for strengthening the critical method in EU law scholarship.
Example II: The ideology critique of EU law
The alienation critique provided one example of how the critique of EU law can benefit from a more deliberate engagement with critical dialectics. But it is important to look beyond that example. Adialectical method of critique challenges the very idea of unmasking critique in critical EU law scholarship. This shift away from a purely unmasking critique can be examined by using the critique of ideology as a further example. The concept of ideology, understood as false consciousness, used to explain what distorted emancipatory processes according to the early critical theory. This understanding of ideology is no longer popular because the idea of a critic who is capable of unmasking ideological distortions is vulnerable to the charge of epistemological authoritarianism.Footnote 177 For instance, Ernesto Laclau explicitly rejects ‘the possibility of a metalinguistic vantage point which allows the unmasking of ideological distortion’.Footnote 178 Maeve Cooke, for her part, points out that, insofar as ‘theories of objectively necessary false consciousness seem to deny the capacity of human subjects to act in their own rational interests’, they ‘open themselves to accusations of epistemological and ethical authoritarianism’.Footnote 179 Here the important question is whether the unmasking critique of EU law can avoid this type of authoritarianism without collapsing into uncritical philosophical and sociological positivism. In answering this question, it is useful to have a closer look at how contemporary critical theorists deal with the issue of ideology.
Laclau asserts that a non-essentialist critique of ideology is possible and can provide a viable alternative to ‘new positivism and objectivism’ in social theory.Footnote 180 For Laclau, ‘[t]here is ideology whenever a particular content shows itself as more than itself’.Footnote 181 Ideology accordingly refers to ‘the illusion that the desired state of completion is actually accessible’ and to the ways in which ‘[d]esire for completion is projected onto some representation of the absent transcendent object’.Footnote 182 Laclau’s discourse theoretical approach to ideology is closely linked to his neo-Gramscian understanding of hegemonic articulation and struggle in the project of radical democracy.Footnote 183 For the purposes of the present article, the important observation is that the critical subject, too, may search for ideological closure by replacing a transcendent object with its historically particular representation. What is particularly interesting for EU law scholarship is that democracy is listed as the main example of ‘transcendent objects to which empty signifiers…refer’.Footnote 184 Because democracy is a ‘floating signifier’,Footnote 185 fixing its meaning happens ‘by making of it one of the names of the fullness of society’.Footnote 186 From this perspective, a ‘shared belief’ that a specific representation of the transcendent object is ‘adequate’ explains how social groups are formed and maintained.Footnote 187 This highlights that democracy, while important, cannot provide a self-explanatory critical lens for unmasking the deficits of EU law.Footnote 188
In the study of EU law, unmasking critique promises to expose the ideology or ideologies of EU law. Amore developed methodology of critique complements this by highlighting the need of an ‘intra-ideological’ critique of EU law. For Laclau, ‘[t]he illusion of closure is something we can negotiate with, but never eliminate’.Footnote 189 This means that ‘what is impossible is a critique of ideology as such; all critiques will necessarily be intra-ideological’.Footnote 190 But it has been noted that Laclau may proceed too swiftly ‘from the thesis of the necessity of the transcendent object to the thesis of the necessity of belief in its attainability’.Footnote 191 To avoid positivism, Laclau should arguably either clarify the rationality of ‘intra-ideological’ critique or to ‘allow for a reference point for criticism that goes beyond the ensemble of practices in a given social order’.Footnote 192 In other words, Laclau’s discourse theoretical approach is not able to fully account for what it actually means to replace a purely unmasking critique with a critique that is aware of its own ideological tendencies. This latter question is pressing for the critique of EU law. As will be seen in this section, it reinforces the earlier question of how critique can come into terms with its social embeddedness without losing its critical force.
The critique of ideology persists as an ‘indispensable method’ for critical social theory.Footnote 193 However, in contemporary critical theory, the critique of ideology extends to the critical project itself. The notion of ideology continues to refer to distorted forms of social rationality, that is, to ‘social pathologies’.Footnote 194 But ideology is now viewed both as ‘cognitive’ and ‘material’, including ‘habits and dispositions, in patterns of behavior and social practices’.Footnote 195 From this perspective, critical rationality becomes distorted if it fails to acknowledge the effects of ‘material conditions and practices’ on conceptual thinking.Footnote 196 The critique of ideology accordingly explores the ‘embeddedness’ of critical ideas and concepts in social reality.Footnote 197 Arevised ideology critique can be understood as a form of immanent critique because it can no longer detach itself from the ‘social formation that it seeks to understand, critique, and transform’.Footnote 198 Similarly, a methodologically sound critique of EU law must deal with its own ideational and ideological tendencies. This means that a plausible critique of EU law is not possible without a simultaneous critique of its ‘own constitutive conditions’.Footnote 199 Awareness of the inherent links between ‘critique’, ‘self-critique’ and ‘self-referentiality’ is central to a fully developed critical method.Footnote 200 An unmasking critique accordingly becomes ‘a form of self-critique, one in which reason itself is continually put on trial’.Footnote 201
In critical theory, the continuing relevance of ideology critique is supported by the view that social change is not unfeasible. For instance, Cooke argues that the concept of ideology is useful to social critique because it draws attention to ‘the difficulties that cognitive change for the better may involve’, as well as to the ways in which the reproduction of ‘social oppression’ may remain ‘hidden from the human subjects concerned’.Footnote 202 In this reading, the critique of ideology reflects the fact that theory and practice cannot be meaningfully separated in the critical project and that ‘praxis’ consists of ‘intentionally guided thought and action aimed at changing the social order for the better’.Footnote 203 In critical dialectics, methodological negativism explains how critique can detect social pathologies and distortions without falling into essentialist theorisation. But, as has been seen above in this article, the negativity of critical dialectics does not offer the critic any easy exit from the problematic of emancipation. Dismissing the transformative aspect of critique raises the concern that the critical project becomes radically disoriented. Interestingly, however, the unmasking critique of EU law often remains reticent about whether post-critique transformation is possible and/or even desirable. For this reason, the critical project comes across as incomplete in EU law.
This discussion on the problematic of unmasking/ideology critique clarifies what options are available to critical EU law scholarship: The critical project can strive for strong context-transcending validity claims, with all the difficulties that relate to epistemological authoritarianism. Or, critique can retreat into philosophical and sociological positivism and a schematic distinction between ‘facticity’ and ‘validity’. But this would dilute both the diagnostic and the transformative force of critique. Neither of these two options is satisfactory if the critical project takes seriously the interplay between the material and the ideational aspects of social reality. The third option would be to moderate critical claims by more explicitly linking them to particular models of social rationality that steer critique. This, however, is difficult without a more developed critical method. If ‘ideological closure’Footnote 204 can occur as part of the critical project itself, the critical method becomes the only available safeguard against such uncritical tendencies. Therefore, the critique of EU law needs a methodology that is alert to how competing social rationalisations (and pathologies) shape the critical project from the beginning because every critic is socialised at a particular time and place. This essentially means that the critique of EU law must come to terms with its nature as ‘intra-ideological’ critique – a concession that may not be easy for legal scholars. The next section will clarify why and what could be done about it.
5. Overcoming obstacles: how to advance critical engagement in EU law scholarship?
The EU is a deeply ideational project.Footnote 205 This is confirmed by the current EU Treaties,Footnote 206 as well as by the way in which the integration project emerged as a counter-reaction to fascism and totalitarianism. However, it is important to notice that, from the outset, there were several competing visions of what this project should entail and where its focus should lie.Footnote 207 The ideational nature of European integration has direct implications for what it means to study EU law. From the internal perspective, the EU legal order may have no other option than to claim for the autonomy of EU law in formalist terms. But it is problematic if EU law scholars adopt this intra-systemic justificatory perspective on EU law. This is also an area where the critical history of EU law has made a useful contribution in clarifying the peculiar symbiosis between the EU’s early institutional framework and its academic research.Footnote 208 The nature of the EU as an inherently ideational project requires a particular critical mindset from EU law scholars. At the same time, the EU’s prolonged crisis mode suggests that the need of critical research is increasing, rather than decreasing, in the foreseeable future. But the main thrust of this article was not that more critical research on EU law is needed. On the contrary, this article demonstrated that EU law scholars should more carefully reflect on what it means to conduct a methodologically sound critique of EU law.
Here the guiding premise is that EU law deserves to be critiqued better. In EU law scholarship, both the revisionist and the rejectionist strands of critique have methodological caveats that prevent them from reaching their full potential. Specific questions that merit further investigation in critical EU law scholarship include, but are not exhausted to, the following: What different purposes does critique serve in the study of EU law? Is it primarily deconstructive, constructive, or reconstructive? When is critique normative? Can it not be normative? If not, is the normativity of critique recognised or overlooked? Above all, from which standpoint is critique conducted? To what extent is critique immanent and/or genealogical? This article explained the silence of critical EU law scholarship on many of these questions by the general failure to transform the quest for critique into a methodological recalibration of how EU law is criticised – a matter that is arguably beyond the reach of the traditional ‘role of law’ debate. The perceived lack of interest in the critical method is problematic because the methodology of critique, that is, how critique is conducted, will always shape the findings of critique. Therefore, it is important to consider what factors may currently hinder more thoughtful critical engagement in EU law scholarship and what steps are needed to encourage such engagement.
The lack of methodological engagement may at least partly stem from the nature of legal training and its focus on reasoning and argumentation at the expense of methodological and epistemological questions.Footnote 209 This means that a more deliberate engagement with critical social theory will quickly take the legal scholar outside his/her ‘zone of proximal development’ (and also of his/her zone of comfort).Footnote 210 While most EU law scholars are not trained in the methods of social sciences or social theory, political and social scientists studying EU law may espouse the idea of facticity too uncritically. It can even be argued that a shift towards a more social-scientific study of law merely substitutes ‘one kind of normativity for another’.Footnote 211 But this article demonstrated that the focal point is not the normativity of critique as such. What is more important is whether critical scholarship is aware of the contingency and immanence of different critical interventions, and what epistemological commitments may inhibit this awareness in the study of EU law. This is important because, in the absence of adequate methodological engagement, the driving force of critique, that is, how the critic rationalises society tends to remain unpronounced.
Another explanation for this lethargy may relate to the common perception of EU law as a stabilising and integrating mechanism, rather than as a site of social or political struggle. Questioning this narrative of EU law would also recast what the EU as a ‘Community of law’ means and does not mean. It is also clear that EU law is researched differently if it is viewed as a ‘lesser evil’, rather than as a superior normative solution to the intricate coordination problems and interdependencies between the EU Member States. These are topics that critical EU law scholarship promises to cover, but its ability to do so is currently hampered by the lack of methodological sophistication. The central argument in this article was that neither EU law nor the critique of EU law can escape their embeddedness in a complex web of competing social rationalities. For this reason, the argument for a more developed critical method is necessarily an argument for a more prominent role of social theory in EU legal studies. But making this link between critical EU law scholarship and social theory unveils a deeper question of how the relationship between theory and practice is understood in the study of EU law.
In brief, a closer engagement with critical social theory may require that EU law scholars rethink what theory is and how it relates to the study of EU law. In critical theory, the theory-practice relationship is never just a one-way relationship. If theory is only viewed as a tool, it too becomes vulnerable to the charge of functionalism. Instead of viewing abstract theory as a synonym for bad or useless theory, it is important to consider for what purposes critical theory uses abstraction. In addressing this question, it is good to bear in mind that abstraction (eg in art) strives for freedom from the existing representational qualities. What may appear like abstract and futile theory from one perspective, may count as the necessary ‘labour of concept’ from another. Similarly, EU law needs theory that can push our thinking beyond the confines of what already exists, without losing sight of how the ideational and the material aspects of social reality always interact. This type of social-theoretic inquiry would also shed critical light on the conceptual abstractions that EU law scholarship already uses quite unapologetically.Footnote 212
In this article, the analysis of unmasking critique showed that critical EU law scholarship cannot sail under the flag of merely exposing the negative effects of European legal integration. Instead, the methodological commitment to critique must extend to critical interventions themselves. This is so because unmasking critique is always contingent on a preceding choice between competing social rationalisations. The dialectical method of critique maintains that any attempt towards metacritical reflection remains unsuccessful insofar as it is unable to recognise its own embeddedness in social reality. While critique as a methodological commitment is not reducible to a mere substantive criticism of EU law, a more developed critical method is a prerequisite for critique’s potential to contest and transform the law in substantive terms. But this quest for critical dialectics is not a ‘one-size-fits-all’ type of argument. Since critique is a multilayered phenomenon, each scholar will ultimately need to form their own understanding of what the commitment to critique as a method means and what level of methodological engagement is necessary for their scholarship. While this section can only provide some tentative guidelines for such critical self-reflection, it is clear that a dialectical method of critique would pay particular attention to the use of concepts in the exercise of critique.
A ‘dialectic scheme’ assumes ‘interaction’, rather than opposition, between ‘paradigm dichotomies’.Footnote 213 Recourse to dialectics means that critical research cannot rely on conceptual oppositions and binary categorisations without explicating how these categorisations are pre-structured, mediated, and rationalised. This would be an important change in the study of EU law because the critical discourse often builds on such conceptual dichotomies.Footnote 214 The primacy of the object over the critical subject also means that a dialectical method of critique resists any predetermined, totalising, conceptualisation of EU law as an object of critique. Acknowledging the contingency of our conceptual apparatuses has implications for how far critical claims can be generalised and, thus, for what validity claims the critical project can make. But the search for a more developed critical method is not reducible to the semantic analysis of what different meanings can be assigned to key concepts, such as a democratic polity, in the critique of EU law. The close links between practice and theory highlight that critique is rooted in ‘specific sets of social relations, institutional arrangements and processes of social reproduction’.Footnote 215 Since the critic is always socialised into a certain environment and culture with a tendency to normalise the existing patterns of socialisation, the rationalisation of the critical project – and the related quest for self-critique – become ever more important.
A dialectical critique cannot repress the internal divisions of cooperative social rationality that underlies critique.Footnote 216 Adialectical critique accordingly resists essentialist references to national affective unity, solidarity, and pre-political belonging as the normative basis for critiquing EU law. Critical dialectics also goes further than, for instance, system theory, in recognising that the critical subject may also be internally differentiated.Footnote 217 The dissolution of the always-coherent subject reinforces the argument that the critic’s insights are never representative of differentiated social reality as a whole. As such, the dialectical method of critique also points to the limits of non-normative descriptive approaches in the critical study of EU law. This article has shed light on the ways in which ‘facticity’ is currently both under- and overstated in EU law scholarship. On the one hand, the opposition between law and facticity is problematic when it fails to consider the materiality of the law itself. On the other hand, the dialectical method of critique highlights that extra-legal social reality, too, is always mediated. Arguments from facticity, whether political, economic, or social, can advance the critical study of EU law only insofar as the very idea of facticity is simultaneously subjected to critical scrutiny. This explains why empirical research cannot alone fill the gaps of critical EU law scholarship.
For critical EU law scholarship, the continuing challenge is how to conduct normative critique in a methodologically sound way that does not deny critique’s social embeddedness. Anchoring the critical discourse to what legitimises the law has provided valuable insights into the present ambivalence of the EU legal order, that is, to the way in which its foundations may lack an extra-legal constitutive moment/power beyond the Treaties.Footnote 218 But a more developed critical method would relieve critique from the constraints of the ‘role of law’ debate by moving the analytical focus to the critique of law as a conflict between various models of social rationality. This brings us back to the seemingly vexed relationship between the ‘explanatory-diagnostic’ and the ‘anticipatory-transformative’ critique of EU law. While negative dialectics enables critical engagement even in the absence of any positive theory-building, a dialectical critique of EU law cannot close its eyes to the question of what comes after critique in EU legal studies. To that end, it is good to bear in mind that fundamental, even rejectionist, critique can also be ‘redemptive’ in the sense that it sheds light on the ‘unrealized promises’ of what is critiqued.Footnote 219
6. Conclusion
Although the EU’s multifaceted crises reinforce the need for critical research, the methodology of critique has received relatively little attention in critical EU law scholarship. This article made a distinct contribution to the critical study of EU law from a methodological perspective. First, it showed how both the revisionist and the rejectionist strands of critique bypass a whole set of relevant methodological questions about the critique of EU law. Second, the article explored what EU law scholars could learn from the methodological commitments of critical social theory and how the principles of metacritique, critique’s immanence, contingency, and negativity can inform the critique of EU law. This analysis gained additional weight from the observation that a purely unmasking critique of EU law is vulnerable both to epistemological authoritarianism and uncritical sociological positivism. It was concluded on this basis that the turn to empirical research cannot alone fill the perceived methodological gaps in critical EU law scholarship. Since both critique and the critic are always socially embedded, the critical method becomes central to the accountability of the critical project. These findings highlighted the importance of social-theoretic approaches in the study of EU law.
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to the ELO editors and the anonymous reviewers for thoughtful comments during the review process. I also warmly thank those current and former colleagues in Durham, Helsinki, and Berlin who have discussed this topic with me.
Funding
This work was supported by the Academy of Finland, the Research Council for Culture and Society (postdoctoral grant number 309207).
Conflicts of interest
The author has no conflicts of interest to declare.