Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T01:45:49.169Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scientific Man vs. Power Politics: A Pamphlet and Its Author between Two Academic Cultures

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 March 2016

Extract

Hans Morgenthau's Scientific Man vs. Power Politics appeared in 1946, one year after he received tenure at the University of Chicago. Thus, the monograph demarcates the beginning of Morgenthau's career in the United States, to which he had emigrated nine years earlier. Three main aspects seem important for understanding this work. The first is Morgenthau's bewilderment about American political culture and, as he perceived it, its cheerful optimism about the betterment of politics, society, and humanity in general. The second aspect is the nature of the argument: Scientific Man is a dogmatic tract, an attempt to hammer home certain philosophical positions—positions that were largely unpopular in the U.S. social sciences in the 1940s (and later)—rather than a reflective scholarly elaboration of certain philosophical commitments. The third is Morgenthau's place between two academic cultures: Morgenthau's language in his American writings partly stems from, but also tries to leave behind, his European academic socialization. The monograph thus reflects the author's peculiar situation, as he inhabits two sometimes crucially different semantic and cultural contexts, but fails to bridge or broker them.

Type
Roundtable: Morgenthau in America
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1 Hans J. Morgenthau, Scientific Man vs. Power Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1946).

2 This terminological and conceptual thoroughness is most explicit in his German-written doctoral thesis and two unpublished manuscripts and his French-written postdoctoral (“Habilitation”) thesis. See Die internationale Rechtspflege, ihr Wesen und ihre Grenzen (Leipzig: Universitätsverlag von Robert Noske, 1929); “Über die Herkunft des Politischen aus dem Wesen des Menschen” (Washington, D.C.: Library of Congress, Manuscript Division, Box 151, 1930, unpublished); La Réalité des Normes. En Particulier des Normes du Droit International. Fondement d'une Théorie des Normes (Paris: Félix Alcan, 1934); and “Über den Sinn der Wissenschaft in dieser Zeit und über die Bestimmung des Menschen” (Washington, D.C.: Library of Congress, Manuscript Division, Box 151, 1934, unpublished).

3 “Postscript to the Transaction Edition: Bernard Johnson's Interview with Hans J. Morgenthau,” in Kenneth W. Thompson and Robert J. Myers, eds., Truth and Tragedy. A Tribute to Hans J. Morgenthau (New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Books, 1984), pp. 333–386, 371.

4 See also Felix Rösch's contribution to this roundtable.

5 Morgenthau, La Réalité des Normes; see also Oliver Jütersonke, Morgenthau, Law and Realism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010).

6 There are comprehensive studies of Morgenthau's intellectual influences. The major influence of European intellectual thought on his work, particularly the writings of Plato, Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas, Friedrich Nietzsche, and Sigmund Freud, is well known. His stark opposition to Carl Schmitt and Hegelianism is also well documented. More immediately, there was Reinhold Niebuhr, whom he met in Chicago in 1944 and with whom he formed a life-long friendship. Max Weber, on the other hand, is prominently absent (there is almost no mention of Weber in his entire oeuvre and none in Scientific Man). Morgenthau was sometimes negligent of bibliographical precision in his references and careless when it came to historical details, as my co-editor, Felix Roesch, and I came to realize when editing his 1933 La notion du “Politique” and preparing the book's first English edition (as The Concept of the Political; see endnote eight for details). On the other hand, Morgenthau was a “paper saver” (Frei, 2001, p. 4), and his surviving private notes and correspondence are a valuable resource for those who seek to reconstruct his political thought.

7 See Hartmut Behr and Felix Rösch, “Introduction,” in Behr and Rösch, eds., Hans J. Morgenthau, The Concept of the Political, Maeva Vidal, trans., foreword by Michael C. Williams (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), esp. pp. 38–42.

8 See Morgenthau's “Concept of the Political,” in Behr and Rösch, Hans J. Morgenthau, The Concept of the Political, where this is strongest; also Fritz Ringer and the problem of the Weimar Mandarins, in The Decline of the German Mandarins: The German Academic Community, 1890–1933 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969). Morgenthau's argument about depoliticization of society and politics shows surprising similarities to the same argument in poststructuralist authors; see, e.g., Jenny Edkins, Poststructuralism and International Relations. Bringing the Political Back in (Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner Publishers, 1999).

9 See most explicitly in Scientific Man, ch. 1, “The Challenge of Fascism,” p. 6 onward.

10 Morgenthau's later oeuvre follows Marcuse with regard to consumerism, modernity, nuclear weapons (the “political-industrial-military complex” more widely), and mass society; see, for example, Hans J. Morgenthau, “Macht und Ohnmacht des Menschen im Technologischen Zeitalter,” in Oskar Schatz, ed., Was wird aus dem Menschen? Der Fortschritt—Analysen und Warnungen bedeutender Denker (Graz: Verlag Styria, 1973), pp. 47–60; Morgenthau, Hans J., “The Pathology of American Power,” International Security 1, no. 3 (1977), pp. 320 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; also “Classical Realism Meets Critical Theory,” research.ncl.ac.uk/classicalrealism.

11 Morgenthau is politically committed to the idea of liberal society and liberalism (see Hall, Ian, “The Triumph of Anti-liberalism? Reconciling Radicalism to Realism in International Relations Theory,” Political Studies Review 9, no. 1 (2011), pp. 4252 Google Scholar), but criticized liberal idealism as an epistemological position. For more on this, see Behr, Hartmut, “‘Common Sense,’ Thomas Reid, and Realist Epistemology in Hans J. Morgenthau,” in International Politics 50, no. 6 (2013)Google Scholar, and Behr and Rösch, “Introduction,” in Hans J. Morgenthau, The Concept of the Political.

12 For example, Morgenthau, Hans J., “Positivism, Functionalism, and International Law,” American Journal of International Law 34, no. 2 (1940)Google Scholar; The Limitations of Science and the Problem of Social Planning,” Ethics 54, no. 3 (1944)Google Scholar; “The Scientific Solution of Social Conflicts,” in Lyman Bryson, Louis Finkelstein, and Robert M. MacIver, eds., Approaches to National Unity: Fifth Symposium of the Conference on Science, Philosophy and Religion (New York: Harper, 1945); Reflections on the State of Political Science,” Review of Politics 17, no. 4 (1955)Google Scholar; and Modern Science and Political Power,” Columbia Law Review 64, no. 8 (1964)Google Scholar.

13 Morgenthau gave the lecture in a series called “Liberalism Today.” In the programme, available through the New School for Social Research online archive, Morgenthau is not listed, but one encounters the name of Professor Erich Hula from the New School itself. Since both Hula and Morgenthau were close to Hans Kelsen, and Morgenthau and Hula maintained correspondence and collaborated on various writings, one can assume that Morgenthau was suggested by Hula as a replacement after Hula cancelled his talk. In any case, Morgenthau certainly utilized this chance, as he did not have tenure at that time, being an assistant professor at the University of Kansas.

14 This is most obvious in Morgenthau's, paper on “The Evil of Politics and the Ethics of Evil,” Ethics 56, no. 1 (1945)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and is elaborated on by Richard Ned Lebow in The Tragic Vision of Politics: Ethics, Interests, and Orders (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003); see also Morgenthau, “Love and Power,” Commentary 33 (March 1962), published by the American Jewish Committee, pp. 247–51.

15 Morgenthau, Scientific Man, p. 14 as well as ch. VIII, “The Tragedy of Scientific Man”; for other writing from Morgenthau in this vein, see “The Evil of Politics and the Ethics of Evil,” pp. 227–28; The Twilight of International Morality,” Ethics 58, no. 2 (1948), pp. 7999 Google Scholar; The Evil of Power. A Critical Study of de Jouvenel's On Power ,” Review of Metaphysics 3, no. 4 (1950), pp. 507–17Google Scholar; and “Morgenthau to Gottfried-Karl Kindermann,” April 5, 1961 (Washington, D.C.: Library of Congress, Box 33). See also Hartmut Behr and Felix Rösch, “Hans J. Morgenthau and the Ethics of Anti-Hubris,” in Jodok Troy, ed., Religion and the Realist Tradition (Abingdon: Routledge, 2013), pp. 111–28.

16 Here it appears that Morgenthau was celebrated (as well as critiqued) by many for the wrong reasons; see Behr and Rösch, “Introduction,” in Hans J. Morgenthau, The Concept of the Political, p. 29–30.

17 See Ashley, Richard, “Political Realism and Human Interests,” International Studies Quarterly 25, no. 2 (1981), pp. 204–36Google Scholar; Behr and Rösch, “Introduction,” in Hans J. Morgenthau, The Concept of the Political, p. 30–32; and Levine, Daniel, “Why Morgenthau Was Not a Critical Theorist,” International Relations 27, no. 1 (2013), pp. 95118 Google Scholar. We find the two notions of power, by many IR theorists rightly attributed to Michel Foucault, earlier in Morgenthau (and others) in a very similar manner.

18 With regard to this, see his letter to Michael Oakeshott of May 22, 1948 (Washington, D.C.: Library of Congress, Manuscript Division, Container 33), as well as Behr, Hartmut and Heath, Amelia, “Misreading in IR Theory and Ideology Critique: Morgenthau, Waltz and Neo-Realism,” Review of International Studies 35, no. 2 (2009), pp. 327–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and A History of International Political Theory: Ontologies of the International (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010).

19 See the recently edited volume by Felix Rösch, Émigré Scholars and the Genesis of International Relations: A European Discipline in America? (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014).

20 Morgenthau's, reading of Machiavelli can indeed be seen in “The Machiavellian Utopia,” Ethics 55, no. 2 (1945), pp. 145–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar; on Machiavelli, see, among others, Behr, A History of International Political Theory, ch. II.2.1.

21 Translated in English as The Concept of the Political (see note eight).

22 Morgenthau utilizes the distinction in his German writings, foremost his PhD thesis, where he writes about “Macht” (in the meaning of “pouvoir”) and “Kraft” (as “puissance”). For an excellent discussion of both concepts of “power,” see Rösch, Felix, “Pouvoir, Puissance, and Politics: Hans Morgenthau's Dualistic Concept of Power?Review of International Studies 40, no. 2 (2014), pp. 349–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar; also Morgenthau, “Love and Power.”

23 Correspondence between the author and Morgenthau's daughter, Susanna, and son, Mathew, in 2010 and 2011 during the preparation of The Concept of the Political.

24 Letter to Michael Oakeshott, May 22, 1948 (Washington, D.C.: Library of Congress, Manuscript Division, Container 33).