Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T02:44:41.423Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Symbolic factors of ${\mathcal S}$-adic subshifts of finite alphabet rank

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 March 2022

BASTIÁN ESPINOZA*
Affiliation:
Departamento de Ingeniería Matemática and Centro de Modelamiento Matemático, Universidad de Chile, Beauchef 851, Santiago, Chile
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper studies several aspects of symbolic (i.e. subshift) factors of $\mathcal {S}$ -adic subshifts of finite alphabet rank. First, we address a problem raised by Donoso et al [Interplay between finite topological rank minimal Cantor systems, S-adic subshifts and their complexity. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 374(5) (2021), 3453–3489] about the topological rank of symbolic factors of $\mathcal {S}$ -adic subshifts and prove that this rank is at most the one of the extension system, improving on the previous results [B. Espinoza. On symbolic factors of S-adic subshifts of finite alphabet rank. Preprint, 2022, arXiv:2008.13689v2; N. Golestani and M. Hosseini. On topological rank of factors of Cantor minimal systems. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. doi:10.1017/etds.2021.62. Published online 8 June 2021]. As a consequence of our methods, we prove that finite topological rank systems are coalescent. Second, we investigate the structure of fibers $\pi ^{-1}(y)$ of factor maps $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,S)$ between minimal ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshifts of finite alphabet rank and show that they have the same finite cardinality for all y in a residual subset of Y. Finally, we prove that the number of symbolic factors (up to conjugacy) of a fixed subshift of finite topological rank is finite, thus extending Durand’s similar theorem on linearly recurrent subshifts [F. Durand. Linearly recurrent subshifts have a finite number of non-periodic subshift factors. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. 20(4) (2000), 1061–1078].

Type
Original Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1 Introduction

An ordered Bratteli diagram is an infinite directed graph $B = (V,E,\leq )$ such that the vertex set V and the edge set E are partitioned into levels $V= V_0\cup V_1\cup \cdots $ , $E = E_0\cup \cdots $ so that $E_n$ are edges from $V_{n+1}$ to $V_n$ , $V_0$ is a singleton, each $V_n$ is finite and $\leq $ is a partial order on E such that two edges are comparable if and only if they start at the same vertex. The order $\leq $ can be extended to the set $X_B$ of all infinite paths in B, and the Vershik action $V_B$ on $X_B$ is defined when B has unique minimal and maximal infinite paths with respect to $\leq $ . We say that $(X_B,V_B)$ is a Bratteli–Vershik (BV) representation of the Cantor system $(X,T)$ if both are conjugate. Bratteli diagrams are a tool coming from $C^*$ -algebras that, at the beginning of the 1990’s, Herman et al [Reference Herman, Putnam and SkauHPS92] used to study minimal Cantor systems. Their success at characterizing the strong and weak orbit equivalence for systems of this kind marked a milestone in the theory that motivated many posterior works. Some of these works focused on using Bratteli diagrams to study specific classes of systems and, as a consequence, many of the classical minimal systems have been characterized as BV systems with a specific structure. Some examples include odometers as those systems that have a BV representation with one vertex per level, substitutive subshifts as stationary BV (all levels are the same) [Reference Durand, Host and SkauDHS99], certain Toeplitz sequences as ‘equal row-sum’ BV [Reference Gjerde and JohansenGJ00], and (codings of) interval exchanges as BV where the diagram codifies a path in a Rauzy graph [Reference Gjerde and JohansenGJ02]. Now, almost all of these examples share certain coarse dynamical behavior: they have finitely many ergodic measures, are not strongly mixing, have zero entropy, are subshifts, and their BV representations have a bounded number of vertices per level, among many others. It turns out that just having a BV representation with a bounded number of vertices per level (or, from now on, having finite topological rank) implies the previous properties (see, for example, [Reference Bezuglyi, Kwiatkowski, Medynets and SolomyakBKMS13, Reference Downarowicz and MaassDM08]). Hence, the finite topological rank class arises as a possible framework for studying minimal subshifts and proving general theorems.

This idea has been exploited in many works: Durand et al, in a series of papers (with [Reference Durand, Frank and MaassDFM19] being the last one), developed techniques from the well-known substitutive case and obtained criteria for any BV of finite topological rank to decide if a given complex number is a continuous or measurable eigenvalue; Bezuglyi et al described in [Reference Bezuglyi, Kwiatkowski, Medynets and SolomyakBKMS13] the simplex of invariant measures together with natural conditions for being uniquely ergodic; Giordano et al bounded the rational rank of the dimension group by the topological rank [Reference Herman, Putnam and SkauHPS92, Reference Giordano, Handelman and HosseiniGHH18], among other works. It is important to remark that these works were inspired by or first proved in the substitutive case.

Now, since Bratteli–Vershik systems with finite topological rank at least two are conjugate to a subshift [Reference Downarowicz and MaassDM08], it is interesting to try to define them directly as a subshift. This can be done by codifying the levels of the Bratteli diagram as substitutions and then iterate them to obtain a sequence of symbols defining a subshift conjugate to the initial BV system. This procedure also makes sense for arbitrary nested sequences of substitutions (called directive sequences), independently from the Bratteli diagram and the various additional properties of its codifying substitutions. Subshifts obtained in this way are called ${\mathcal S}$ -adic (substitution-adic) and may be non-minimal (see, for example, [Reference Berthé, Steiner, Thuswaldner and YassawiBSTY19]).

Although there are some open problems about finite topological rank systems depending directly on the combinatorics of the underlying Bratteli diagrams, others are more naturally stated in the ${\mathcal S}$ -adic setting (e.g. when dealing with endomorphisms, it is useful to have the Curtisâ–Hedlundâ–Lyndon theorem) and, hence, there exists an interplay between ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshifts and finite topological rank systems in which theorems and techniques obtained for one of these classes can sometimes be transferred to the other. The question about which is the exact relation between these classes has been recently addressed in [Reference Donoso, Durand, Maass and PetiteDDMP21] and, in particular, the authors proved the following.

Theorem 1.1. [Reference Donoso, Durand, Maass and PetiteDDMP21]

A minimal subshift $(X,T)$ has topological rank at most K if and only if it is generated by a proper, primitive, and recognizable ${\mathcal S}$ -adic sequence of alphabet rank at most K.

In this context, a fundamental question is the following.

Question 1.2. Are subshift factors of finite topological rank systems of finite topological rank?

Indeed, the topological rank controls various coarse dynamical properties (number of ergodic measures, rational rank of dimension group, among others) which cannot increase after a factor map, and we also know that big subclasses of the finite topological rank class are stable under symbolic factors, such as the linearly recurrent and the non-superlineal complexity classes [Reference Donoso, Durand, Maass and PetiteDDMP21], so it is expected that this question has an affirmative answer. However, when trying to prove this using Theorem 1.1, we realize that the naturally inherited ${\mathcal S}$ -adic structure of finite alphabet rank that a symbolic factor has is never recognizable. Moreover, this last property is crucial for many of the currently known techniques to handle finite topological rank systems (even in the substitutive case, it is a deep and fundamental theorem of Mossé), so it is not clear why it would be always possible to obtain this property while keeping the alphabet rank bounded or why recognizability is not connected with a dynamical property of the system. Thus, an answer to this question seems to be fundamental to the understanding of the finite topological rank class.

This question has been recently addressed, first in [Reference EspinozaEsp20] by purely combinatorial methods, and then also in [Reference Golestani and HosseiniGH21] in the BV formulation by using an abstract construction from [Reference Amini, Elliott and GolestaniAEG15]. In this work, we refine both approaches and obtain, as a first consequence, the optimal answer to Question 1.2 in a more general, non-minimal context.

Theorem 1.3. Let $(X,T)$ be an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing and proper directive sequence of alphabet rank equal to K, and $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,S)$ be an aperiodic subshift factor. Then, $(Y,S)$ is an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing, proper, and recognizable directive sequence of alphabet rank at most K.

Here, a directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ is everywhere growing if $\lim _{n\to \infty }\min _{a\in {\mathcal A}_n}|\sigma _0\ldots \sigma _{n-1}(a)| = \infty $ , and a system $(X,T)$ is aperiodic if every orbit $\{T^nx:n\in {\mathbb Z}\}$ is infinite. Theorem 1.3 implies that the topological rank cannot increase after a factor map (Corollary 4.8). Theorem 1.3 implies the following sufficient condition for a system to be of finite topological rank.

Corollary 1.4. Let $(X,T)$ be an aperiodic minimal ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing directive sequence of finite alphabet rank. Then, the topological rank of $(X,T)$ is finite.

An interesting corollary of the underlying construction of the proof of Theorem 1.3 is the coalescence property for this kind of system, in the following stronger form.

Corollary 1.5. Let $(X,T)$ be an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing and proper directive sequence of alphabet rank equal to K, and $(X,T) \overset {\pi _1}{\to } (X_1,T_1)\overset {\pi _2}{\to }\ldots \overset {\pi _L}{\to }(X_L,T_L)$ be a chain of aperiodic subshift factors. If $L> \log _2K$ , then at least one $\pi _j$ is a conjugacy.

One of the results in [Reference DurandDur00] is that factor maps between aperiodic linearly recurrent subshifts are finite-to-one. In particular, they are almost k-to-1 for some finite k. For finite topological rank subshifts, we prove the following.

Theorem 1.6. Let $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,S)$ be a factor map between aperiodic minimal subshifts. Suppose that $(X,T)$ has topological rank equal to K. Then $\pi $ is almost k-to-1 for some $k \leq K$ .

We use this theorem, in Corollary 4.12, to prove that Cantor factors of finite topological rank subshifts are either odometers or subshifts.

In [Reference DurandDur00], the author proved that linearly recurrent subshifts have finite topological rank, and that this kind of system has finitely many aperiodic subshift factors up to conjugacy. Inspired by this result, we use ideas from the proof of Theorem 1.3 to obtain the following.

Theorem 1.7. Let $(X,T)$ be a minimal subshift of topological rank K. Then, $(X,T)$ has at most $(3K)^{32K}$ aperiodic subshift factors up to conjugacy.

Altogether, these results give a rough picture of the set of totally disconnected factors of a given finite topological rank system: they are either equicontinuous or subshifts satisfying the properties in Theorems 1.3, 1.5, 1.7, and 1.6. Now, in a topological sense, totally disconnected factors of a given system $(X,T)$ are ‘maximal,’ so, the natural next step in the study of finite topological rank systems is asking about the connected factors. As we have seen, the finite topological rank condition is a rigidity condition. By this reason, we think that the following question has an affirmative answer.

Question 1.8. Let $(X,T)$ be a minimal system of finite topological rank and $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,S)$ be a factor map. Suppose that Y is connected. Is $(Y,S)$ an equicontinuous system?

We remark that the finite topological rank class contains all minimal subshifts of non-superlinear complexity [Reference Donoso, Durand, Maass and PetiteDDMP21], but even for the much smaller class of linear complexity subshifts, the author is not aware of results concerning Question 1.8.

1.1 Organization

In the next section, we give the basic background in topological and symbolic dynamics needed in this article. Section 3 is devoted to prove some combinatorial lemmas. The main results about the topological rank of factors are stated and proved in §4. Next, in §5, we prove Theorem 1.6, which is mainly a consequence of the so-called critical factorization theorem. Finally, in §6, we study the problem about the number of symbolic factors and prove Theorem 1.7.

2 Preliminaries

For us, the set of natural numbers starts with zero, i.e. ${\mathbb N}=\{0,1,2,\ldots \}$ .

2.1 Basics in topological dynamics

A topological dynamical system (or just a system) is a pair $(X,T)$ , where X is a compact metric space and $T\colon X \to X$ is a homeomorphism of X. We denote by $\text {Orb}_T(x)$ the orbit $\{T^nx : n\in {\mathbb Z}\}$ of $x \in X$ . A point $x\in X$ is p-periodic if $T^px=x$ , periodic if it is p-periodic for some $p\geq 1$ , and aperiodic otherwise. A topological dynamical system is aperiodic if any point $x\in X$ is aperiodic, is minimal if the orbit of every point is dense in X, and is Cantor if X is a Cantor space (i.e. X is totally disconnected and does not have isolated points). We use the letter T to denote the action of a topological dynamical system independently of the base set X. The hyperspace of $(X,T)$ is the system $(2^X,T)$ , where $2^X$ is the set of all closed subsets of X with the topology generated by the Hausdorff metric $d_H(A,B) = \max (\sup _{x\in A}d(x,A),\ \sup _{y\in B}d(y,A))$ , and T the action $A\mapsto T(A)$ .

A factor between the topological dynamical systems $(X,T)$ and $(Y,T)$ is a continuous function $\pi $ from X onto Y such that $\pi \circ T=T\circ \pi $ . We use the notation $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,T)$ to indicate the factor. A factor map $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Y,T)$ is almost K-to-1 if $\#\pi ^{-1}(y) = K$ for all y in a residual subset of Y. We say that $\pi $ is distal if whenever $\pi (x) = \pi (x')$ and $x\not =x'$ , we have $\inf _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}\mathrm {dist}(T^kx,T^kx')> 0$ .

Given a system $(X,T)$ , the Ellis semigroup $E(X,T)$ associated with $(X,T)$ is defined as the closure of $\{x\mapsto T^nx:n\in {\mathbb Z}\} \subseteq X^X$ in the product topology, where the semi-group operation is given by the composition of functions. On X, we may consider the $E(X,T)$ -action given by $x\mapsto ux$ . Then, the closure of the orbit under T of a point $x\in X$ is equal to the orbit of x under $E(X,T)$ . If $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Y,T)$ is a factor between minimal systems, then $\pi $ induces a surjective map $\pi ^*\colon E(X,T) \to E(Y,T)$ , which is characterized by the formula

$$ \begin{align*} \pi(ux) = \pi^*(u)\pi(x)\quad \text{for all}\ u \in E(X,T)\ \text{and}\ x\in X. \end{align*} $$

If the context is clear, we will not distinguish between u and $\pi ^*(u)$ . When $u \in E(2^X,T)$ , we write $u\circ A$ instead of $uA$ , the last symbol being reserved to mean $uA = \{ux : x \in A\}$ . We can describe more explicitly $u\circ A$ as follows: it is the set of all $x\in X$ for which we can find nets $x_\unicode{x3bb} \in A$ and $m_\unicode{x3bb} \in {\mathbb Z}$ such that $\lim _\unicode{x3bb} T^{m_\unicode{x3bb} } x_\unicode{x3bb} = x$ and $\lim _\unicode{x3bb} T^{m_\unicode{x3bb} } = u$ . Finally, we identify X with $\{\{x\} \subseteq 2^X : x\in X\}$ , so that the restriction map $E(2^X,T) \to E(X,T)$ , which sends $u\in E(2^X,T)$ to the restriction $u|_X\colon X\to X$ , is an onto morphism of semigroups. As above, we will not distinguish between $u\in 2^X$ and $u|_X$ .

2.2 Basics in symbolic dynamics

2.2.1 Words and subshifts

Let ${\mathcal A}$ be an alphabet i.e. a finite set. Elements in ${\mathcal A}$ are called letters and concatenations $w = a_1\ldots a_\ell $ of them are called words. The number $\ell $ is the length of w and it is denoted by $|w|$ , the set of all words in ${\mathcal A}$ of length $\ell $ is ${\mathcal A}^\ell $ , and ${\mathcal A}^+ = \bigcup _{\ell \geq 1}{\mathcal A}^\ell $ . The word $w\in {\mathcal A}^+$ is $|u|$ -periodic, with $u\in {\mathcal A}^+$ , if w occurs in a word of the form $uu\ldots u$ . We define ${\mathrm {per}}(w)$ as the smallest p for which w is p-periodic. We will use notation analogous to that introduced in this paragraph when dealing with infinite words $x \in {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb N}$ and bi-infinite words $x \in {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ . The set ${\mathcal A}^+$ equipped with the operation of concatenation can be viewed as the free semigroup on ${\mathcal A}$ . It is convenient to introduce the empty word $1$ , which has length $0$ and is a neutral element for the concatenation. In particular, ${\mathcal A}^+\cup \{1\}$ is the free monoid in ${\mathcal A}$ . Finally, for ${\mathcal W}\subseteq {\mathcal A}^+$ , we write $\langle {\mathcal W}\rangle := \min _{w\in {\mathcal W}}|w|$ and $|W| := \max _{w\in {\mathcal W}}|w|$ .

The shift map $T \colon {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z} \to {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ is defined by $T ((x_n)_{n\in \mathbb {Z}}) = (x_{n+1})_{n\in \mathbb {Z}}$ . For $x \in {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ and integers $i < j$ , we denote by $x_{[i,j)}$ the word $x_ix_{i+1}\ldots x_j$ . Analogous notation will be used when dealing with intervals of the form $[i,\infty )$ , $(i,\infty )$ , $(-\infty ,i]$ , and $(-\infty ,i)$ . A subshift is a topological dynamical system $(X,T)$ , where X is a closed and T-invariant subset of ${\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ (we consider the product topology in ${\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ ) and T is the shift map. Classically one identifies $(X,T)$ with X, so one says that X itself is a subshift. When we say that a sequence in a subshift is periodic (respectively aperiodic), we implicitly mean that this sequence is periodic (respectively aperiodic) for the action of the shift. Therefore, if $x\in {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ is periodic, then ${\mathrm {per}}(x)$ is equal to the size of the orbit of x. The language of a subshift $X\subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ is the set ${\mathcal L}(X)$ of all words $w\in {\mathcal A}^+$ that occur in some $x\in X$ .

The pair $(x,\tilde {x}) \in {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}\times {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ is right asymptotic if there exist $k \in {\mathbb Z}$ satisfying $x_{(k,\infty )} = \tilde {x}_{(k,\infty )}$ and $x_k\not =\tilde {x}_k$ . If moreover $k=0$ , $(x,\tilde {x})$ is a centered right asymptotic. A right asymptotic tail is an element $x_{(0,\infty )}$ , where $(x,\tilde {x})$ is a centered right asymptotic pair. We make similar definitions for left asymptotic pairs and tails.

2.2.2 Morphisms and substitutions

Let ${\mathcal A}$ and ${\mathcal B}$ be finite alphabets and $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}^+ \to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism between the free semigroups that they define. Then, $\tau $ extends naturally to maps from ${\mathcal A}^{\mathbb {N}}$ to itself and from ${\mathcal A}^{\mathbb {Z}}$ to itself in the obvious way by concatenation (in the case of a two-sided sequence, we apply $\tau $ to positive and negative coordinates separately and we concatenate the results at coordinate zero). We say that $\tau $ is positive if for every $a\in {\mathcal A}$ , all letters $b \in {\mathcal B}$ occur in $\tau (a)$ , is r-proper, with $r\geq 1$ , if there exist $u,v \in {\mathcal B}^r$ such that $\tau (a)$ starts with u and ends with v for any $a \in {\mathcal A}$ , is proper when is $1$ -proper, and is letter-onto if for every $b \in {\mathcal B}$ there exists $a \in {\mathcal A}$ such that b occurs in a. The minimum and maximum lengths of $\tau $ are respectively the numbers $\langle \tau \rangle := \langle \tau ({\mathcal A})\rangle = \min _{a\in {\mathcal A}}|\tau (a)|$ and $|\tau | := |\tau ({\mathcal A})| = \max _{a\in {\mathcal A}}|\tau (a)|$ .

We observe that any map $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}\to {\mathcal B}^+$ can be naturally extended to a morphism (that we also denote by $\tau $ ) from ${\mathcal A}^+$ to ${\mathcal B}^+$ by concatenation, and any morphism $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ is uniquely determined by its restriction to ${\mathcal A}$ . From now on, we will use the same notation for denoting a map $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}\to {\mathcal B}^+$ and its extension to a morphism $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ .

Definition 2.1. Let $X\subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ be a subshift and $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism. We say that $(k,x) \in {\mathbb Z}\times X$ is a $\sigma $ -factorization of $y \in {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z}$ in X if $y = T^k\sigma (x)$ . If moreover $k\in [0,|\sigma (x_0)|)$ , then $(k,x)$ is a centered $\sigma $ -factorization in X.

The pair $(X,\sigma )$ is recognizable if every point $y \in {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z} $ has at most one centered $\sigma $ -factorization in X, and recognizable with constant $r \in {\mathbb N}$ if whenever $y_{[-r,r]} = y^{\prime }_{[-r,r]}$ and $(k,x)$ , $(k',x')$ are centered $\sigma $ -factorizations of $y, y' \in {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z}$ in X, respectively, we have $(k,x_0) = (k',x^{\prime }_0)$ .

The cuts of $(k,x)$ are defined by

$$ \begin{align*} c_{\sigma,j}(k,x) = \begin{cases} -k + |\sigma(x_{[0,j)})| &\text{if }j \geq 0, \\ -k - |\sigma(x_{[j,0)})| &\text{if }j < 0. \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

We write $C_\sigma (k,x) = \{c_{\sigma ,j}(k,x) : j \in {\mathbb Z}\}$ .

Remark 2.2. In the context of the previous definition we have the following.

  1. (i) The point $y \in {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z}$ has a (centered) $\sigma $ -factorization in X if and only if y belongs to the subshift $Y := \bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb Z}}T^n\sigma (X)$ . Hence, $(X,\sigma )$ is recognizable if and only if every $y\in Y$ has a exactly one centered $\sigma $ -factorization in X.

  2. (ii) If $(k,x)$ is a $\sigma $ -factorization of $y \in {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z}$ in X, then $(c_{\sigma ,j}(k,x), T^j x)$ is a $\sigma $ -factorization of y in X for any $j \in {\mathbb Z}$ . There is exactly one factorization in this class that is centered.

  3. (iii) If $(X,\sigma )$ is recognizable, then it is recognizable with constant r for some $r \in {\mathbb N}$ [Reference Donoso, Durand, Maass and PetiteDDMP21].

The behavior of recognizability under composition of morphisms is given by the following lemma.

Lemma 2.3. [Reference Berthé, Steiner, Thuswaldner and YassawiBSTY19, Lemma 3.5]

Let $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ and $\tau \colon {\mathcal B}^+\to {\mathcal C}^+$ be morphisms, $X\subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ be a subshift, and $Y = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma (X)$ . Then, $(X, \tau \sigma )$ is recognizable if and only if $(X,\sigma )$ and $(Y,\tau )$ are recognizable.

Let $X \subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ and $Z \subseteq {\mathcal C}^{\mathbb Z}$ be subshifts and $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Z,T)$ a factor map. The classic Curtisâ–Hedlundâ–Lyndon theorem asserts that $\pi $ has a local code, this is, a function $\psi \colon {\mathcal A}^{2r+1}\to {\mathcal C}$ , where $r\in {\mathbb N}$ , such that $\pi (x) = (\psi (x_{[i-r,i+r]}))_{i\in {\mathbb Z}}$ for all $x \in X$ . The integer r is called the a radius of $\pi $ . The following lemma relates the local code of a factor map to proper morphisms.

Lemma 2.4. Let $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism, $X \subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ and $Z\subseteq {\mathcal C}^{\mathbb Z}$ be subshifts, and $Y = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma (X)$ . Suppose that $\pi \colon (Y,T)\to (Z,T)$ is a factor map of radius r and that $\sigma $ is r-proper. Then, there exists a proper morphism $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal C}^+$ such that $|\tau (a)| = |\sigma (a)|$ for any $a \in {\mathcal A}$ , $Z = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau (X)$ and the following diagram commutes:

(1)

Proof. Let $\psi \colon {\mathcal A}^{2r+1}\to {\mathcal B}$ be a local code of radius r for $\pi $ and $u,v \in {\mathcal B}^r$ be such that $\sigma (a)$ starts with u and ends with v for all $a \in {\mathcal A}$ . We define $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}\to {\mathcal C}^+$ by $\tau (a) = \psi (v\sigma (a)u)$ . Then, since $\sigma $ is r-proper, $\tau $ is proper and we have $\pi (\sigma (x)) = \tau (x)$ for all $x \in X$ (that is, Diagram (1) commutes). In particular,

$$ \begin{align*} \bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau(X) = \bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\pi(\sigma(X)) = \pi(Y) = Z.\\[-46pt] \end{align*} $$

2.2.3 ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshifts

We recall the definition of an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift as stated in [Reference Berthé, Steiner, Thuswaldner and YassawiBSTY19]. A directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n \colon \mathcal {A}_{n+1}^+\to \mathcal {A}_n^+)_{n \in {\mathbb N}}$ is a sequence of morphisms. For $0\leq n<N$ , we denote by $\sigma _{[n,N)}$ the morphism $\sigma _n \circ \sigma _{n+1} \circ \cdots \circ \sigma _{N-1}$ . We say that $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is everywhere growing if

(2) $$ \begin{align} \lim_{N\to +\infty}\langle\sigma_{[0,N)}\rangle = +\infty, \end{align} $$

and primitive if for any $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , there exists $N>n$ such that $\sigma _{[n,N)}$ is positive. We remark that this notion is slightly different from the usual one used in the context of substitutional dynamical systems. Observe that $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is everywhere growing if $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is primitive. Let ${\mathcal P}$ be a property for morphisms (e.g. proper, letter-onto, etc). We say that $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ has property ${\mathcal P}$ if $\sigma _n$ has property ${\mathcal P}$ for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ .

For $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , we define

$$ \begin{align*} X^{(n)}_{\boldsymbol{\sigma}} = \{x \in \mathcal{A}_n^{\mathbb Z} :\text{ for all } \ell\in{\mathbb N}, x_{[-\ell,\ell]}\ \text{occurs in}\ \sigma_{[n,N)}(a)\ \text{for some}\ N>n, a \in\mathcal{A}_N\}. \end{align*} $$

This set clearly defines a subshift that we call the nth level of the ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ . We set $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }} = X^{(0)}_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ and simply call it the ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ . If $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is everywhere growing, then every $X^{(n)}_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ , $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , is non-empty; if $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is primitive, then $X^{(n)}_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ is minimal for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ . There are non-everywhere growing directive sequences that generate minimal subshifts.

The relation between levels of an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift is given by the following lemma.

Lemma 2.5. [Reference Berthé, Steiner, Thuswaldner and YassawiBSTY19, Lemma 4.2]

Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n \colon \mathcal {A}_{n+1}^+\to \mathcal {A}_n^+)_{n \in {\mathbb N}}$ be a directive sequence of morphisms. If $0\leq n < N$ and $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}$ , then there exists a (centered) $\sigma _{[n,N)}$ -factorization in $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(N)}$ . In particular, $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma _{[n,N)}(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(N)})$ .

The levels $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}$ can be described in an alternative way if $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ satisfies the correct hypothesis.

Lemma 2.6. Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ be an everywhere growing and proper directive sequence. Then, for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ ,

(3) $$ \begin{align} X_{\boldsymbol{\sigma}}^{(n)} = \bigcap_{N>n}\bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma_{[n,N)}({\mathcal A}_N^{\mathbb Z}). \end{align} $$

Proof. Let Z be the set in the right-hand side of (3). Since, by Lemma 2.5, $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma _{[n,N)}(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(N)})$ for any $N> n$ , we have that $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}$ included in Z.

Conversely, let $x\in Z$ and $\ell \in {\mathbb N}$ . We have to show that $x_{[-\ell ,\ell )}$ occurs in $\sigma _{[n,N)}(a)$ for some $N>n$ and $a \in {\mathcal A}_N$ . Let $N>n$ be big enough so that $\sigma _{[n,N)}$ is $\ell $ -proper. Then, by the definition of Z, there exists $y \in {\mathcal A}_N^{\mathbb Z}$ such that $x_{[-\ell ,\ell )}$ occurs in $\sigma _{[n,N)}(y)$ . Since $\langle \sigma _{[n,N)}\rangle \geq \ell $ (as $\sigma _{[n,N)}$ is $\ell $ -proper), we deduce that

(4) $$ \begin{align} x_{[-\ell,\ell)}\ \text{occurs in}\ \sigma_{[n,N)}(ab)\ \text{for some word}\ ab\ \text{of length 2 occurring in}\ y. \end{align} $$

Hence, by denoting by u and v the suffix and prefix of length $\ell $ of $\tau _{[n,N)}(a)$ and $\tau _{[n,N)}(b)$ , respectively, we have that $x_{[-\ell ,\ell )}$ occurs in $\sigma _{[n,N)}(a)$ , in $\tau _{[n,N)}(b)$ , or in $uv$ . In the first two cases, we are done. In the last case, we observe that since $\sigma _{[n,N)}$ is $\ell $ -proper, the following is true: for every $M>N$ such that $\langle \sigma _{[N,M)}\rangle \geq 2$ , $vu\sqsubseteq \sigma _{[n,M)}(c)$ for any $c \in {\mathcal A}_M$ . In particular, $x_{[-\ell ,\ell )}\sqsubseteq \tau _{[n,M)}(c)$ for such M and c. We have proved that $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}$ .

We define the alphabet rank of a directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ as

$$\begin{align*}AR(\boldsymbol{\tau}) = \liminf_{n\to +\infty} \#{\mathcal A}_n.\end{align*}$$

A contraction of $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is a sequence $\tilde {\boldsymbol {\tau }} = (\tau _{[n_k,n_{k+1})}\colon {\mathcal A}_{n_{k+1}}^+\to {\mathcal A}_{n_k}^+)_{k\in {\mathbb N}}$ , where $0 = n_0 < n_1 < n_2 < \ldots $ . Observe that any contraction of $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ generates the same ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}$ . When the context is clear, we will use the same notation to refer to $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ and its contractions. If $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ has finite alphabet rank, then there exists a contraction $\tilde {\boldsymbol {\tau }} = (\tau _{[n_k,n_{k+1})}\colon {\mathcal A}_{n_{k+1}}^+\to {\mathcal A}_{n_k}^+)_{k\in {\mathbb N}}$ of $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ in which ${\mathcal A}_{n_k}$ has cardinality $AR(\boldsymbol {\tau })$ for every $k\geq 1$ .

Finite alphabet rank ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshifts are eventually recognizable.

Theorem 2.7. [Reference Donoso, Durand, Maass and PetiteDDMP21, Theorem 3.7]

Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ be an everywhere growing directive sequence of alphabet rank equal to K. Suppose that $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ is aperiodic. Then, at most $\log _2 K$ levels $(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)},\sigma _n)$ are not recognizable.

We will also need the following property.

Theorem 2.8. [Reference Espinoza and MaassEM21, Theorem 3.3]

Let $(X,T)$ be an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing directive sequence of alphabet rank K. Then, X has at most $144K^7$ right (respectively left) asymptotic tails.

Proof. In the proof of theorem 3.3 in [Reference Espinoza and MaassEM21], the authors show the following: the set consisting of pairs $(x,y) \in X \times X$ such that $x_{(-\infty ,0)} = y_{(-\infty ,0)}$ and $x_0\not =y_0$ has at most $144K^7$ elements. In our language, this is equivalent to saying that X has at most $144K^7$ left asymptotic tails. Since this is valid for any ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing directive sequence of alphabet rank K, $144K^7$ is also an upper bound for right asymptotic tails.

3 Combinatorics on words lemmas

In this section, we present several combinatorial lemmas that will be used throughout the article.

3.1 Lowering the rank

Let $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism. Following ideas from [Reference Rozenberg and SalomaaRS97], we define the rank of $\sigma $ as the least cardinality of a set of words ${\mathcal D} \subseteq {\mathcal B}^+$ such that $\sigma ({\mathcal A}^+) \subseteq {\mathcal D}^+$ . Equivalently, the rank is the minimum cardinality of an alphabet ${\mathcal C}$ in a decomposition into morphisms ${\mathcal A}^+ \overset {q}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal C}^+ \overset {p}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal B}^+$ such that $\sigma = pq$ . In this subsection, we prove Lemma 3.6, which states that in certain technical situations, the rank of the morphism $\sigma $ under consideration is small and its decomposition $\sigma = pq$ satisfies additional properties.

We start by defining some morphisms that will be used in the proofs of this subsection. If $a\not =b \in {\mathcal A}$ are different letters and $\tilde {a}$ is a letter not in ${\mathcal A}$ , then we define $\phi _{a,b}\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to ({\mathcal A}\setminus \{b\})^+$ , $\psi _{a,b}\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal A}^+$ , and $\theta _{a, \tilde {a}}\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to ({\mathcal A}\cup \{\tilde {a}\})^+$ by

$$ \begin{align*} \phi_{a,b}(c) = \begin{cases} c & \text{if}\ c\not=b, \\ a & \text{if}\ c=b. \end{cases} \qquad \psi_{a,b}(c) = \begin{cases} c & \text{if}\ c\not=b, \\ ab & \text{if}\ c=b. \end{cases} \qquad \theta_{a,\tilde{a}}(c) = \begin{cases} c & \text{if}\ c\not=a, \\ \tilde{a}a & \text{if}\ c=a. \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

Observe that these morphisms are letter-onto. Before stating the basic properties of these morphisms, we need one more set of definitions.

For a morphism $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ , we define $|\sigma |_1 = \sum _{a\in {\mathcal A}}|\sigma (a)|$ . When $u,v,w\in {\mathcal A}^+$ satisfy $w = uv$ , we say that u is a prefix of w and that v a suffix of w. Recall that $1$ stands for the empty word.

Lemma 3.1. Let $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism.

  1. (i) If $\sigma (a) = \sigma (b)$ for some $a\not =b\in {\mathcal A}$ , then $\sigma = \sigma '\phi _{a,b}$ , where $\sigma '\colon ({\mathcal A}\setminus \{b\})^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ is the restriction of $\sigma $ to $({\mathcal A}\setminus \{b\})^+$ .

  2. (ii) If $\sigma (a)$ is a prefix of $\sigma (b)$ and $\sigma (b) = \sigma (a)t$ for some non-empty $t\in {\mathcal B}^+$ , then $\sigma = \sigma '\psi _{a,b}$ , where $\sigma '\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ is defined by

    (5) $$ \begin{align} \sigma'(c) = \begin{cases} \sigma(c) & \text{if}\ c\not=b, \\ t & \text{if}\ c=b. \end{cases} \end{align} $$
  3. (iii) If $\sigma (a) = st$ for some $s,t\in {\mathcal B}^+$ and $a\in {\mathcal A}$ , then $\sigma = \sigma '\theta _{a,\tilde {a}}$ , where $\sigma '\colon ({\mathcal A}\cup \{\tilde {a}\})^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ is defined by

    (6) $$ \begin{align} \sigma'(c) = \begin{cases} \sigma(c) & \text{if}\ c\not=a,\tilde{a}, \\ s & \text{if}\ c=\tilde{a}, \\ t & \text{if}\ c=a. \end{cases} \end{align} $$

Proof. The lemma follows from unraveling the definitions. For instance, in case (ii), we have $\sigma '(\psi _{a,b}(a)) = \sigma '(a) = \sigma (a)$ , $\sigma '(\psi _{a,b}(b)) = \sigma '(ab) = \sigma (a)t = \sigma (b)$ , and $\sigma '(\psi _{a,b}(c)) = \sigma '(c) = \sigma (c)$ for all $c \not = a,b$ , which shows that $\sigma '\psi _{a,b} = \sigma $ .

Lemma 3.2. Let $\{\sigma _j\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}_j^+\}_{j\in J}$ be a set of morphisms such that

(7) $$ \begin{align} \text{for every fixed}\ a \in {\mathcal A}, \ell_a := |\sigma_j(a)|\ \text{is constant for any chosen}\ j \in J, \end{align} $$

and $u,v \in {\mathcal A}^+$ , with u of length at least $\ell := \sum _{a\in {\mathcal A}}\ell _a$ . Assume that u and v start with different letters and that $\sigma _j(u)$ is a prefix of $\sigma _j(v)$ for every $j \in J$ .

Then, there exists a letter-onto morphism $q\colon {\mathcal A}^+ \to {\mathcal C}^+$ , with $\#{\mathcal C} < \#{\mathcal A}$ , and morphisms $\{p_j\colon {\mathcal C}^+\to {\mathcal B}_j^+\}_{j\in J}$ satisfying a condition analogous to (7) and such that $\sigma _j = p_jq$ .

Remark 3.3. If in the previous lemma we change the last hypothesis to ‘u and v end with different letters and $\sigma _j(u)$ is a suffix of $\sigma _j(v)$ for every $j \in J$ ’, then the same conclusion holds. This observation will be used in the proof of Lemma 6.7.

Proof of Lemma 3.2

By contradiction, we assume that u, v, and $\{\sigma _j\}_{j \in J}$ are counterexamples for the lemma. Moreover, we suppose that $\ell $ is as small as possible.

Let us write $u = au'$ and $v=bv'$ , where $a,b \in {\mathcal A}$ . Since $\sigma _j(u)$ is a prefix of $\sigma _j(v)$ , we have that for every $j \in J$ ,

(8) $$ \begin{align} \text{one of the words in}\ \{\sigma_j(a), \sigma_j(b)\}\ \text{is a prefix of the other.} \end{align} $$

We consider two cases. First, we suppose that $\ell _a = \ell _b$ . In this case, (8) implies that $\sigma _j(a) = \sigma _j(b)$ for every $j\in J$ . Hence, we can use (i) of Lemma 3.1 to decompose each $\sigma _j$ as $\sigma _j'\phi _{a,b}$ , where $\sigma ^{\prime }_j$ is the restriction of $\sigma _j$ to $({\mathcal A}\setminus \{b\})^+$ . Since $\phi _{a,b}$ is letter-onto and $\ell _c = |\sigma ^{\prime }_j(c)|$ for every $j \in J$ , $c\in {\mathcal A}\setminus \{b\}$ , the conclusion of the lemma holds, contrary to our assumptions.

This leaves to consider the case in which $\ell _a \not = \ell _b$ . We only do the case $\ell _a < \ell _b$ as the other is similar. Then, by (8), for every $j \in J$ , there exists a non-empty word $t_j \in {\mathcal B}_j^{\ell _b-\ell _a}$ of length $\ell _b-\ell _a$ such that $\sigma _j(b) = \sigma _j(a)t_j$ . Thus, we can use (ii) of Lemma 3.1 to write, for any $j \in J$ , $\sigma _j = \sigma ^{\prime }_j\psi _{a,b}$ , where $\sigma ^{\prime }_j$ is defined as in (5).

Let $\tilde {u} = \psi _{a,b}(u')$ and $\tilde {v} = b\psi _{a,b}(v')$ . We want now to prove that $\tilde {u}$ , $\tilde {v}$ , and $\{\sigma ^{\prime }_j : j \in J\}$ satisfy the hypothesis of the lemma. First, we observe that for every $j \in J$ ,

(9) $$ \begin{align} \text{if }c\not=b, \text{ then } |\sigma^{\prime}_j(c)| = \ell_c, \text{ and } |\sigma^{\prime}_j(b)| = |t_j| = \ell_b-\ell_a. \end{align} $$

Therefore, $\{\sigma ^{\prime }_j\}_{j\in J}$ satisfy (7). Also, since $\psi _{a,b}(c)$ never starts with b, we have that

(10) $$ \begin{align} \tilde{u}, \tilde{v}\ \text{start with different letters.} \end{align} $$

Furthermore, by using the symbol $\leq _p$ to denote the prefix relation, we can compute:

$$ \begin{align*} \sigma_j(a)\sigma^{\prime}_j(\tilde{u}) &= \sigma_j(a)\sigma_j(u') = \sigma_j(u) \leq_p \sigma_j(v) = \sigma^{\prime}_j(\psi_{a,b}(v)) = \sigma^{\prime}_j(a)\sigma^{\prime}_j(\tilde{v}). \end{align*} $$

This and the fact that $\sigma _j(a)$ is equal to $\sigma ^{\prime }_j(a)$ imply that

(11) $$ \begin{align} \sigma^{\prime}_j(\tilde{u}) \text{ is a prefix of } \sigma^{\prime}_j(\tilde{v}) \text{ for every } j \in J. \end{align} $$

Finally, we note

(12) $$ \begin{align} |\tilde{u}| \geq |u|-1 \geq \sum_{c\in{\mathcal A}}\ell_c - \ell_a =: \ell'. \end{align} $$

We conclude from (9), (10), (11), and (12) that $\tilde {u}$ , $\tilde {v}$ , and $\{\sigma ^{\prime }_j : j \in J\}$ satisfy the hypothesis of this lemma. Since $\ell ' < \ell $ , the minimality of $\ell $ implies that there exist a letter-onto morphism $q'\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal C}^+$ , with $\#{\mathcal C} < \#{\mathcal A}$ , and morphisms $\{p_j\colon {\mathcal C}^+\to {\mathcal B}_j^+\}_{j\in J}$ satisfying $\sigma ^{\prime }_j=p_jq'$ and a property analogous to (7). However, then $q := q'\psi _{a,b}$ is also letter-onto and the morphisms $\{p_j\}_{j\in J}$ satisfy $\sigma _j = p_jq$ and a property analogous to (7). Thus, the conclusion of the lemma holds for $\{\sigma _j\}_{j\in J}$ , contrary to our assumptions.

Lemma 3.4. Let $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism, $u,v \in {\mathcal A}^+$ , $a,b$ be the first letters of $u,v$ respectively, and $\sigma (a) = st$ be a decomposition of $\sigma (a)$ in which t is non-empty. Assume that $\sigma (u)$ is a prefix of $s\sigma (v)$ , $|u| \geq |\sigma |_1+|s|$ , and either that $s = 1$ and $a\not =b$ or that $s \not = 1$ .

Then, there exist morphisms $q\colon {\mathcal A}^+ \to {\mathcal C}^+$ and $p\colon {\mathcal C}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ such that $\#{\mathcal C} \leq \#{\mathcal A}$ , q is letter-onto, $|p|_1 < |\sigma |_1$ , and $\sigma = pq$ .

Remark 3.5. As in Lemma 3.2, there are symmetric hypotheses for the previous lemma that involve suffixes instead of prefixes and which give the same conclusion. We will use this in the proof of Lemma 3.6.

Proof of Lemma 3.4

Let us write $u = au'$ and $v = bv'$ . We first consider the case in which $s=1$ . In this situation, u and v start with different letters, so Lemma 3.2 can be applied (with the index set J chosen as a singleton) to obtain a decomposition ${\mathcal A}^+ \overset {q}{\to } {\mathcal C}^+ \overset {p}{\to } {\mathcal B}^+$ such that q is letter-onto, $\#{\mathcal C} < \#{\mathcal A}$ , and $\sigma = pq$ . Since ${\mathcal C}$ has strictly fewer elements than ${\mathcal A}$ , we have $|p|_1 < |\sigma |_1$ . Hence, the conclusion of the lemma holds in this case.

We now assume that $s\not =1$ . In this case, t and s are non-empty, so we can use (iii) of Lemma 3.1 to factorize $\sigma = \sigma '\theta _{a, \tilde {a}}$ , where $\tilde {a}$ is a letter not in ${\mathcal A}$ and $\sigma '$ is defined as in (6). We set $\tilde {u} = a\theta _{a,\tilde {a}}(u')$ and $\tilde {v} = \theta _{a,\tilde {a}}(v)$ . Our plan is to use Lemma 3.2 with $\tilde {u}$ , $\tilde {v}$ and $\sigma '$ .

Observe that $\theta _{a,\tilde {a}}(c)$ never starts with a, so

(13) $$ \begin{align} \tilde{u}, \tilde{v}\ \text{start with different letters.} \end{align} $$

Also, by using, as in the previous proof, the symbol $\leq _p$ to denote the prefix relation,

$$ \begin{align*} s\sigma'(\tilde{u}) = s\sigma'(a) \sigma'(\theta_{a,\tilde{a}}(u')) = st\sigma(u') = \sigma(u) \leq_p s\sigma(v) = s\sigma'(\theta_{a,\tilde{a}}(v)) = s\sigma'(\tilde{v}), \end{align*} $$

which implies that

(14) $$ \begin{align} \sigma'(\tilde{u})\ \text{is a prefix of}\ \sigma'(\tilde{v}). \end{align} $$

Finally, we use (6) to compute:

(15) $$ \begin{align} |\tilde{u}| \geq |u|-1 \geq |\sigma|_1 +|s|-1 \geq |\sigma|_1 = |\sigma'|_1. \end{align} $$

We conclude, by (13), (14), and (15) that Lemma 3.2 can be applied with $\tilde {u}$ , $\tilde {v}$ , and $\sigma '$ (and J as a singleton). Thus, there exist morphisms $q'\colon ({\mathcal A}\cup \{\tilde {a}\})^+\to {\mathcal C}^+$ and $p\colon {\mathcal C}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ such that $\#{\mathcal C} < \#({\mathcal A}\cup \{\tilde {a}\})$ , $q'$ is letter-onto, and $\sigma '=pq'$ . Then, $\#{\mathcal C} \leq \#{\mathcal A}$ , $q := q'\theta _{a, \tilde {a}}$ is letter-onto, and $\sigma = p q'\theta _{a, \tilde {a}} = pq$ . Moreover, since $\theta _{a, \tilde {a}}$ is not the identity function, we have $|p|_1 < |\sigma |_1$ .

The next lemma is the main result of this subsection. To state it, we introduce additional notation. For an alphabet ${\mathcal A}$ , let ${\mathcal A}^{++}$ be the set of words $w \in {\mathcal A}^+$ in which all letters occur. Observe that $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ is letter-onto if and only if $\sigma ({\mathcal A}^{++}) \subseteq {\mathcal B}^{++}$ .

Lemma 3.6. Let $\phi \colon {\mathcal A}^+ \to {\mathcal C}^+$ , $\tau \colon {\mathcal B}^+\to {\mathcal C}^+$ be morphisms such that $\tau $ is $\ell $ -proper, with $\ell \geq |\phi |_1^4$ , and $\phi ({\mathcal A}^+) \cap \tau ({\mathcal B}^{++}) \not = \emptyset $ . Then, there exist ${\mathcal B}^+ \overset {q}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal D}^+ \overset {p}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal C}^+$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \text{(i)}\ \#{\mathcal D} \leq \#{\mathcal A},\quad \text{(ii)}\ \tau = pq,\quad \text{(iii)}\ q\ \text{is letter-onto and proper.} \end{align*} $$

Proof. By contradiction, we suppose that the lemma does not hold for $\phi $ and $\tau $ and, moreover, that $|\phi |_1$ as small as possible.

That $\phi ({\mathcal A})^+ \cap \tau ({\mathcal B}^{++})$ is non-empty means that there exist $u = u_1\ldots u_n \in {\mathcal A}^+$ and $w = w_1\ldots w_m \in {\mathcal B}^{++}$ with $\phi (u) = \tau (w)$ . If $m = 1$ , then, since $w \in {\mathcal B}^{++}$ , we have $\#{\mathcal B} = \{v_1\}$ and the conclusion of the lemma trivially holds for ${\mathcal D} = \{a\in {\mathcal C}:a\ \text {occurs in}\ \tau (w_1)\}$ , $q\colon {\mathcal B}^+\to {\mathcal D}^+$ , $w_1\mapsto \tau (w_1)$ , and $p\colon {\mathcal D}^+\to {\mathcal C}^+$ the inclusion map, contradicting our initial assumption. Therefore, $m \geq 2$ and $\{1,\ldots ,m-1\}$ is non-empty.

Let $k \in \{1,\ldots ,m-1\}$ . We define $i_k$ as the smallest number in $\{1,\ldots ,n\}$ for which $|\tau (w_1\ldots w_k)| < |\phi (u_1\ldots u_{i_k})|$ holds. Since $|\phi (u_1)| \leq |\phi |_1 \leq \ell \leq |\tau (w_1\ldots w_k)|$ , $i_k$ is at least $2$ and, thus, $|\phi (u_1\ldots u_{i_k-1})| \leq |\tau (w_1\ldots w_k)|$ by minimality of $i_k$ . Hence, there exists a decomposition $\phi (u_{i_k}) = s_kt_k$ such that $t_k$ is non-empty and

(16) $$ \begin{align} t_k\phi(u_{i_k+1}\ldots u_n) = \tau(w_{k+1}\ldots w_m). \end{align} $$

Our next objective is to use Lemma 3.4 to prove that $s_k$ and $u_k$ have a very particular form.

Claim 3.6.1. For every $k\in \{1,\ldots ,m-1\}$ , $s_k = 1$ and $u_1 = u_{i_k}$ .

Proof. To prove this, we suppose that it is not true, that is, there exists $k\in \{1,\ldots ,m-1\}$ such that

(17) $$ \begin{align} s_k \not= 1 \quad \text{or}\quad u_1 \not= u_{i_k}. \end{align} $$

Let $\tilde {u} := u_{i_k}\ldots u_{i_k+|\phi |^2_1-1}$ and $\tilde {v} := u_1\ldots u_{|\phi |^3_1}$ . We are going to check the hypothesis of Lemma 3.4 for $\tilde {u}$ , $\tilde {v}$ and $\phi $ .

First, we observe that, since $\phi (u)=\tau (v)$ , we have that $\phi (\tilde {v})$ is a prefix of $\tau (v)$ . Moreover, given that $|\phi (\tilde {v})| \leq |\phi |_1^4 \leq \ell $ and that $\tau $ is $\ell $ -proper, $\phi (\tilde {v})$ is a prefix of $\tau (b)$ for every $b \in {\mathcal B}$ . In particular,

(18) $$ \begin{align} \phi(\tilde{v})\ \text{is a prefix of}\ \tau(w_k). \end{align} $$

Second, from (16) and the inequalities $|t_k\phi (u_{i_k+1}\ldots u_{i_k+|\phi |^2_1-1})| \leq |\phi |_1^3 \leq \ell \leq |\tau (w_k)|$ , we deduce that $t_k\phi (u_{i_k+1}\ldots u_{i_k+|\phi |^2_1-1})$ is a prefix of $\tau (w_k)$ . Therefore,

(19) $$ \begin{align} \phi(\tilde{u}) = s_kt_k\phi(u_{i_k+1}\ldots u_{i_k+|\phi|^2_1-1})\ \text{is a prefix of}\ s_k\tau(w_k). \end{align} $$

We conclude from (18), (19), and the inequality $|\phi (\tilde {u})| \leq |\phi |_1^3 = |\tilde {v}| \leq |s_k\phi (\tilde {v})|$ that

$$ \begin{align*} \phi(\tilde{u})\ \text{is a prefix of}\ s_k\phi(\tilde{v}). \end{align*} $$

This, the inequality $|\tilde {u}| \geq |\phi |_1+|s_k|$ and (17) allow us to use Lemma 3.4 with $\tilde {u}$ , $\tilde {v}$ , and $\phi $ and obtain morphisms ${\mathcal A}^+ \overset {\tilde {q}}{\longrightarrow } \tilde {{\mathcal A}}^+ \overset {\tilde {\phi }}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal C}^+$ such that $\#\tilde {{\mathcal A}} \leq \#{\mathcal A}$ , $\phi = \tilde {\phi }\tilde {q}$ and $|\tilde {\phi }|_1 < |\phi |_1$ . Then, $\ell \geq |\phi |_1^4> |\tilde {\phi }|_1^4$ and $\tilde {\phi }(\tilde {{\mathcal A}}^+) \cap \tau ({\mathcal B}^{++})$ contains the element $\tilde {\phi }(\tilde {q}(u)) = \tau (w)$ , and so $\tau $ and $\tilde {\phi }$ satisfy the hypothesis of this lemma. Therefore, by the minimality of $|\phi |_1$ , there exists a decomposition ${\mathcal B}^+ \overset {q}{\to } {\mathcal D}^+ \overset {p}{\to } {\mathcal C}^+$ of $\tau $ satisfying conditions (i)–(iii) of this lemma, contrary to our assumptions.

An argument similar to the one used in the proof of the previous claim gives us that

(20) $$ \begin{align} u_n = u_{i_k-1}\quad \text{for every}\ k\in\{1,\ldots,m-1\}. \end{align} $$

We refer the reader to Remark 3.5 for further details.

Now we can finish the proof. First, from (16) and the first part of the claim, we get that $\tau (w_k) = \phi (u_{i_{k-1}}\ldots u_{i_k-1})$ for $k \in \{2,\ldots ,m-1\}$ , $\tau (w_1) = \phi (u_1\ldots u_{i_1-1})$ and $\tau (w_m) = \phi (u_{i_{m-1}}\ldots u_n)$ . Being $w \in {\mathcal B}^{++}$ , these equations imply that each $\tau (b)$ , $b \in {\mathcal B}$ , can be written as a concatenation $x_1\ldots x_N$ , with $x_j \in \phi ({\mathcal A})$ . Moreover, by the second part of the claim and (20), we can choose this decomposition so that $x_1 = u_1$ and $x_N = u_n$ . This defines (maybe non-unique) morphisms ${\mathcal B}^+ \overset {q}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal D}_1^+ \overset {p_1}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal C}^+$ such that $\tau = p_1q$ , $\#{\mathcal D}_1 \leq \#\{\phi (u_1),\ldots ,\phi (u_n)\} \leq \#{\mathcal A}$ , and q is proper. If we define ${\mathcal D}$ as the set of letters $d \in {\mathcal D}_1$ that occur in some $w \in q({\mathcal B})$ , and p as the restriction of $p_1$ to ${\mathcal D}$ , then we obtain a decomposition ${\mathcal B}^+ \overset {q}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal D}^+ \overset {p}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal C}^+$ that still satisfies the previous properties, but in which q is letter-onto. Hence, p and q met conditions (i), (ii), and (iii).

3.2 Periodicity lemmas

We will also need classic results from combinatorics on words. We follow the presentation of [Reference Rozenberg and SalomaaRS97, Ch. 6].

Let $w\in {\mathcal A}^*$ be a non-empty word. We say that p is a local period of w at the position $|u|$ if $w=uv$ , with $u,v\not =1$ , and there exists a word z, with $|z|=p$ , such that one of the following conditions holds for some words $u'$ and $v'$ :

(21) $$ \begin{align} \begin{cases} \mathrm{(i)}\quad & u=u'z \ \text{and}\ v=zv';\\ \mathrm{(ii)}\quad & z =u'u \ \text{and}\ v=zv';\\ \mathrm{(iii)}\quad &u =u'z \ \text{and}\ z=vv';\\ \mathrm{(iv)}\quad & z =u'u = vv'.\end{cases} \end{align} $$

Further, the local period of w at the position $|u|$ , in symbols ${\mathrm {per}}(w,u)$ , is defined as the smallest local period of w at the position u (see Fig. 1). It follows directly from (21) that ${\mathrm {per}}(w,u) \leq {\mathrm {per}}(w)$ .

Figure 1 Illustration of a local period.

The following result is known as the critical factorization theorem.

Theorem 3.7. (Theorem 6.2 and Ch. 6, [Reference Rozenberg and SalomaaRS97])

Each non-empty word $w \in {\mathcal A}^*$ , with $|w|\geq 2$ , possesses at least one factorization $w = uv$ , with $u,v\not =1$ , which is critical, i.e. ${\mathrm {per}}(w) = {\mathrm {per}}(w,u)$ .

4 Rank of symbolic factors

In this section, we prove Theorem 1.3. We start by introducing the concept of factor between directive sequences and, in Proposition 4.4, its relation with factor maps between ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshifts. These ideas are the ${\mathcal S}$ -adic analogs of the concept of premorphism between ordered Bratteli diagrams from [Reference Amini, Elliott and GolestaniAEG15] and their proposition 4.6. Although Proposition 4.4 can be deduced from proposition 4.6 in [Reference Amini, Elliott and GolestaniAEG15] by passing from directive sequences to ordered Bratteli diagrams and backwards, we consider this a little bit artificial since it is possible to provide a direct combinatorial proof; this is done in the Appendix. It is interesting to note that our proof is constructive (in contrast of the existential proof in [Reference Amini, Elliott and GolestaniAEG15]) and shows some additional features that are a consequence of the combinatorics on words analysis made.

Next, we use ideas from [Reference EspinozaEsp20, Reference Golestani and HosseiniGH21] to prove Theorem 1.3. In particular, this improves the previous bounds in [Reference EspinozaEsp20, Reference Golestani and HosseiniGH21] to the best possible one. We apply these results, in Corollary 4.8, to answer affirmatively Question 1.2 and, in Theorem 1.5, to prove a strong coalescence property for the class of systems considered in Theorem 1.3. It is worth noting that this last result is only possible due to the bound in Theorem 1.3 being optimal. We end this section by proving that Cantor factors of finite topological rank systems are either subshifts or odometers.

4.1 Rank of factors of directive sequences

The following is the ${\mathcal S}$ -adic analog of the notion of premorphism between ordered Bratteli diagrams in [Reference Amini, Elliott and GolestaniAEG15].

Definition 4.1. Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = ({\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ , $\boldsymbol {\tau } = ({\mathcal B}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal B}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ be directive sequences. A factor $\boldsymbol {\phi }\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma }\to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ is a sequence of morphisms $\boldsymbol {\phi } = (\phi _n)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ , where $\phi _0\colon {\mathcal A}_1^+\to {\mathcal B}_0^+$ and $\phi _n\colon {\mathcal A}_n^+\to {\mathcal B}_n^+$ for $n \geq 1$ , such that $\phi _0 = \tau _0\phi _1$ and $\phi _n\sigma _n = \tau _n\phi _{n+1}$ for every $n \geq 1$ .

We say that $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ is proper (respectively letter-onto) if $\phi _n$ is proper (respectively letter-onto) for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ .

Remark 4.2. Factors are not affected by contractions. More precisely, if $0=n_0<n_1<n_2<\ldots $ , then $\boldsymbol {\phi '} = (\phi _{n_k})_{k\in {\mathbb N}}$ is a factor from $\boldsymbol {\sigma '} = (\sigma _{[n_k,n_{k+1})})_{k\in {\mathbb N}}$ to $\boldsymbol {\tau '} = (\tau _{[n_k,n_{k+1})})_{k\in {\mathbb N}}$ .

The next lemma will be needed at the end of this section.

Lemma 4.3. Let $\boldsymbol {\phi } = (\phi _n)_{n\geq 1}\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma }\to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ be a factor. Assume that $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ and $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ are everywhere growing and proper and that $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ is letter-onto. Then, $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi _0(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(1)})$ and $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi _n(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)})$ for every $n \geq 1$ .

Proof. We start by proving that $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)} \subseteq \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi _n(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)})$ . Let $y \in X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ and $\ell \in {\mathbb N}$ . There exist $N>n$ and $b \in {\mathcal B}_n$ such that $y_{[-\ell ,\ell ]}$ occurs in $\tau _{[n,N)}(b)$ . In addition, since $\phi _N$ is letter-onto, there exists $a \in {\mathcal A}_N$ for which b occurs in $\phi _N(a)$ . Then, $y_{[-\ell ,\ell ]}$ occurs in $\tau _{[n,N)}\phi _N(b)$ and, consequently, also in $\phi _n\sigma _{[n,N)}(b)$ as $\tau _{[n,N)}\phi _N = \phi _n\sigma _{[n,N)}$ . Hence, by taking the limit $\ell \to \infty $ , we can find $(k',x) \in {\mathbb Z}\times X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}$ such that $y = T^{k'}\phi _n(x)$ . Therefore, $y \in \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi _n(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)})$ . To prove the other inclusion, we use Lemma 2.6 to compute:

$$ \begin{align*} \phi_n(X_{\boldsymbol{\sigma}}^{(n)}) &= \bigcap_{N>n}\bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi_n\sigma_{[n,N)}({\mathcal A}_N^{\mathbb Z}) = \bigcap_{N>n}\bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau_{[n,N)}\phi_N({\mathcal A}_N^{\mathbb Z}) \\&\subseteq \bigcap_{N>n}\bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau_{[n,N)}({\mathcal B}_N^{\mathbb Z}) = X_{\boldsymbol{\tau}}^{(n)}.\\[-46pt] \end{align*} $$

As we mentioned before, the following proposition is a consequence of the main result in [Reference Amini, Elliott and GolestaniAEG15]. We provide a combinatorial proof in the Appendix.

Proposition 4.4. Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ be a letter-onto, everywhere growing, and proper directive sequence. Suppose that $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ is aperiodic. Then, there exist a contraction $\boldsymbol {\sigma }' = (\sigma ^{\prime }_n)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ , a letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper and recognizable $\boldsymbol {\tau } = (\tau _n)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ generating $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ , and a letter-onto factor $\boldsymbol {\phi }\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma }' \to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ , $\boldsymbol {\phi } = (\phi _n)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ , such that $\phi _0 = \sigma ^{\prime }_0$ .

The next proposition is the main technical result of this section. To state it, it is convenient to introduce the following concept. The directive sequences $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ and $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ are equivalent if $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = \boldsymbol {\nu }'$ , $\boldsymbol {\tau } = \boldsymbol {\nu }''$ for some contractions $\boldsymbol {\nu }'$ , $\boldsymbol {\nu }''$ of a directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ . Observe that equivalent directive sequences generate the same ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift.

Proposition 4.5. Let $\boldsymbol {\phi }\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma } \to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ be a letter-onto factor between the everywhere growing and proper directive sequences. Then, there exist a letter-onto and proper factor $\boldsymbol {\psi }\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma }'\to \boldsymbol {\nu }$ , where:

  1. (1) $\boldsymbol {\sigma }'$ is a contraction of $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ ;

  2. (2) $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ is letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, equivalent to $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ , $\mathrm {AR}(\boldsymbol {\nu }) \leq \mathrm {AR}(\boldsymbol {\sigma })$ , and the first coordinate of $\boldsymbol {\psi }$ and $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ coincide;

  3. (3) if $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is recognizable, then $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ is recognizable.

Proof. Let us write $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = ({\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ and $\boldsymbol {\tau } = ({\mathcal B}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal B}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ . Up to contractions, we can suppose that for every $n \geq 1$ , $\#{\mathcal A}_n = \mathrm {AR}(\boldsymbol {\sigma })$ and that $\tau _n$ is $|\phi _n|^4_1$ -proper (for the last property, we used that $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is everywhere growing and proper).

Using that $\phi _{n+1}$ is letter-onto, we can compute:

$$ \begin{align*} \tau_n({\mathcal B}_{n+1}^{++}) \supseteq \tau_n(\phi_{n+1}({\mathcal A}_{n+1}^{++})) = \phi_n(\sigma_n({\mathcal A}_{n+1}^{++})) \subseteq \phi_n({\mathcal A}_n^+), \end{align*} $$

where in the middle step, we used the commutativity property of $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ . We deduce that

$$ \begin{align*} \tau_n({\mathcal B}_{n+1}^{++}) \cap \phi_n({\mathcal A}_n^+) \not= \emptyset\quad \text{for every}\ n \in {\mathbb N}. \end{align*} $$

This and the fact that $\tau _n$ is a $|\phi _n|^4_1$ -proper morphism allow us to use Lemma 3.6 to find morphisms ${\mathcal B}_{n+1}^+ \overset {q_{n+1}}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal D}_{n+1}^+ \overset {p_n}{\longrightarrow } {\mathcal B}_n^+$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \text{(i)}\ \#{\mathcal D}_{n+1} \leq \#{\mathcal A}_n,\quad \text{(ii)}\ \tau_n = p_nq_{n+1},\quad \text{(iii)}\ q_{n+1}\ \text{is letter-onto and proper.} \end{align*} $$

We define $\nu _0 := p_0$ , the morphisms $\nu _n := q_np_n \colon {\mathcal D}_{n+1}^+ \to {\mathcal D}_n^+$ and $\psi _n := q_n\phi _n\colon {\mathcal A}_n^+\to {\mathcal D}_n^+$ , $n \geq 1$ , and the sequences $\boldsymbol {\nu } = (\nu _n)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ and $\boldsymbol {\psi } = (\psi _n)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ , where $\psi _0 := \phi _0$ . We are going to show that these objects satisfy the conclusion of the proposition.

We start by observing that it follows from the definitions that the diagram below commutes for all $n\geq 1$ :

In particular, $\nu _n\nu _{n+1} = q_n\tau _np_{n+1}$ , so $\langle \nu _{[n,n+1]} \rangle \geq \langle \tau _n\rangle $ . Being $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ everywhere growing, this implies that $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ has the same property. We also observe that condition (iii) implies that $\nu _n = q_np_n$ is letter-onto and proper. Altogether, these arguments prove that, up to contracting the first levels, $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ is everywhere growing and proper.

Next, we note that $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ and $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ are equivalent as both are contractions of $(p_0, q_1, p_1, q_2, \ldots )$ . This implies, by Lemma 2.3, that $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ is recognizable if $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is recognizable. Further, by condition (i), $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ has alphabet rank at most $\mathrm {AR}(\boldsymbol {\sigma })$ .

It is only left to prove that $\boldsymbol {\psi }$ is a letter-onto and proper factor. By unraveling the definitions we can compute:

$$ \begin{align*} \psi_0 = \phi_0 = \tau_0\phi_1 = p_0q_1\phi_1 = \nu_0\psi_1, \end{align*} $$

and from the diagram, we have $\sigma _n\psi _n = \psi _{n+1}\tau _n$ for all $n\geq 1$ . Therefore, $\boldsymbol {\psi }$ is a factor. Finally, since $q_n$ is letter-onto and proper by condition (iii) and $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ was assumed to be letter-onto, $\psi _n = q_n\phi _n$ is letter-onto and proper.

4.2 Rank of factors of ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshifts

In this section, we will prove Theorem 1.3 and its consequences. We start with a technical lemma.

The next lemma will allow us to assume without loss of generality that our directive sequences are letter-onto.

Lemma 4.6. Let $\boldsymbol {\tau } = (\tau _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ be an everywhere growing and proper directive sequence. If $\tilde {{\mathcal A}}_n = {\mathcal A}_n \cap {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)})$ , $\tilde {\tau }_n$ is the restriction of $\tau _n$ to $\tilde {{\mathcal A}}_{n+1}$ and $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }} = (\tilde {\tau }_0,\tilde {\tau }_1,\ldots )$ , then $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}$ is letter-onto and $X_{\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}}^{(n)} = X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ . Conversely, if $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is letter-onto, then ${\mathcal A}_n \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)})$ for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ .

Proof. By Lemma 2.5, $\tilde {\tau }_n$ is letter-onto mapping $\tilde {{\mathcal A}}_{n+1}^+$ into $\tilde {{\mathcal A}}_n$ . Moreover, that lemma also gives that for every $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ and $N>n$ , there exists a $\tau _{[n,N)}$ -factorization $(k',x')$ of x in $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(N)}$ . This together with the inclusion $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(N)} \subseteq \tilde {{\mathcal A}}_N^{\mathbb Z}$ imply that

$$ \begin{align*} Z := \bigcap_{N>n}\bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau_{[n,N)}(\tilde{{\mathcal A}}_N^{\mathbb Z}) \supseteq X_{\boldsymbol{\tau}}^{(n)}. \end{align*} $$

Now, $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}$ is everywhere growing and proper, so we can apply Lemma 2.6 to obtain that $X_{\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}}^{(n)} = Z \supseteq X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ . Since it is clear that $X_{\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}}^{(n)}\subseteq X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ as $\tilde {{\mathcal A}}_N \subseteq {\mathcal A}_N$ for every N, we conclude that $X_{\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}}^{(n)} = X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ .

If $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is letter-onto, then ${\mathcal A}_n \subseteq {\mathcal L}(\bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau _{[n,N)}({\mathcal A}_N^{\mathbb Z}))$ for every $N>n$ , and hence, by the formula in Lemma 2.6, ${\mathcal A}_n \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)})$ .

Now we are ready to prove Theorem 1.3. We re-state it in a more precise way.

Theorem 1.3. Let $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Y,T)$ be a factor map between aperiodic subshifts. Suppose that X is generated by the everywhere growing and proper directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ of alphabet rank K. Then, Y is generated by a letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, and recognizable directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ of alphabet rank at most K.

Moreover, if $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is letter-onto, then, up to contracting the sequences, there exists a proper factor $\boldsymbol {\phi }\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma }\to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ such that $\pi (\sigma _0(x)) = \phi _0(x)$ for all $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(1)}$ and $|\sigma _0(a)| = |\phi _0(a)|$ for all $a \in {\mathcal A}_{1}$ .

Proof. Thanks to Lemma 4.6, we can assume without loss of generality that $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is letter-onto. Moreover, in this case,

(22) $$ \begin{align} {\mathcal A}_n \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol{\sigma}}^{(n)})\quad \text{for every}\ n \in {\mathbb N}. \end{align} $$

Let us write $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ . By contracting $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ , we can further assume that $\sigma _0$ is r-proper and $\pi $ has radius r. Then, Lemma 2.4 gives us a proper morphism $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}_1^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ , where ${\mathcal B}$ is the alphabet of Y, such that

(23) $$ \begin{align} \pi(\sigma_0(x)) = \tau(x)\ \text{for all}\ x \in X_{\boldsymbol{\sigma}}^{(1)}\quad \text{and}\quad |\sigma_0(a)| = |\tau(a)|\ \text{for every}\ a \in {\mathcal A}_1. \end{align} $$

In particular, $\pi (\sigma _{[0,n)}(x)) = \tau \sigma _{[1,n)}(x)$ and $|\sigma _{[0,n)}(a)| = |\tau \sigma _{[1,n)}(a)|$ for all $n \in {\mathbb N}$ , $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}$ , and $a \in {\mathcal A}_n$ , so (23) holds for any contraction of $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ .

We define $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\sigma }} = (\tau , \sigma _1, \sigma _2, \ldots )$ and observe this is a letter-onto, everywhere growing and proper sequence generating Y. This and that Y is aperiodic allow us to use Proposition 4.4 and obtain, after a contraction, a letter-onto factor $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\phi }}\colon \boldsymbol {\tilde {\sigma }}\to \boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}$ , where $\tilde {\phi }_0 = \tilde {\sigma }_0 = \tau $ and $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}$ is a letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, and recognizable directive sequence generating Y. The sequence $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\tau }}$ has all the properties required by the theorem but having alphabet rank bounded by K. To overcome this, we use Proposition 4.5 with $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\phi }}$ and do more contractions to obtain a letter-onto and proper factor $\boldsymbol {\phi }\colon \boldsymbol {\tilde {\sigma }} \to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ such that $\phi _0 = \tilde {\phi }_0 = \tau $ and $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is a letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, and recognizable directive sequence generating Y and satisfying $\mathrm {AR}(\boldsymbol {\tau }) \leq \mathrm {AR}(\tilde {\boldsymbol {\sigma }}) = \mathrm {AR}(\boldsymbol {\sigma })$ .

It is left to prove the last part of the theorem. Observe that since $\boldsymbol {\tilde {\sigma }}$ and $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ differ only at their first coordinate, $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ is also a factor from $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ to $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ . Further, by (23) and the fact that $\phi _0 = \tau $ , we have $\pi (\sigma _0(x)) = \tau (x) = \phi _0(x)$ and $|\sigma _0(a)| = |\phi _0(a)|$ for every $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(1)}$ and $a \in {\mathcal A}_1$ .

Corollary 4.7. Let $(X,T)$ be an aperiodic minimal subshift generated by an everywhere growing and proper directive sequence of alphabet rank K. Then, the topological rank of X is at most K.

Proof. We can use Theorem 1.3 to obtain an everywhere growing, proper, and recognizable directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\tau } = (\tau _n\colon {\mathcal B}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal B}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ generating X and having alphabet rank at most K. Due to Lemma 4.6, we can assume that $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is letter-onto. In particular, ${\mathcal B}_n \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)})$ for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ .

We claim that $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ is minimal. Indeed, if $Y \subseteq X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ is a subshift, then $\tau _{[0,n)}(Y)$ is closed (as $\tau _{[0,n)}\colon X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}\to X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}$ is continuous), so $\bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau _{[0,n)}(Y) = \bigcup _{|k|\leq |\tau _{[0,n)}|}T^k\tau _{[0,n)}(Y)$ is a subshift in $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}$ which, by minimality, is equal to it. Thus, any point $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ has a $\tau _{[0,n)}$ -factorization $(k,z)$ with $z \in Y$ . The recognizability property of $(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)},\tau _{[0,n)})$ then implies that $Y = X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ .

Now, we prove that for any $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , there exists $N>n$ such that $\tau _{[n,N)}$ is positive. This would imply that the topological rank of X is at most K and hence would complete the proof. Let $n \in {\mathbb N}$ and R be a constant of recognizability for $(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)},\tau _{[0,n)})$ . Since $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ is minimal, there exists a constant $L\geq 1$ such that two consecutive occurrences of a word $w \in {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)})\cap {\mathcal B}_n^{2R+1}$ in a point $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ are separated by at most L. Let $N> n$ be big enough so that $\langle \tau _{[0,N)}\rangle \geq L+2R$ . Then, for all $a \in {\mathcal B}_N \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(N)})$ and $w \in {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)})\cap {\mathcal B}_n^{2R+1}$ , w occurs at a position $i \in \{R,R+1,\ldots ,|\tau _{[0,N)}(a)|-R\}$ of $\tau _{[0,N)}(a)$ . Since R is a recognizability constant for $(X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)},\tau _{[0,n)})$ , we deduce that for all $a \in {\mathcal B}_N$ and $b \in {\mathcal B}_n$ , b occurs in $\tau _{[n,N)}(a)$ . Thus, $\tau _{[n,N)}$ is positive.

We can now prove Corollary 1.4.

Corollary 1.4. Let $(X,T)$ be an aperiodic minimal subshift generated by an everywhere growing directive sequence of finite alphabet rank. Then, the topological rank of $(X,T)$ is finite.

Proof. We are going to prove that X is generated by an everywhere growing and proper directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ of finite alphabet rank. This would imply, by Corollary 4.7, that the topological rank of X is finite. Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ be an everywhere growing directive sequence of finite alphabet rank generating X. We contract $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ in a way such that $\#{\mathcal A}_n \leq K$ for every $n\geq 1$ .

We are going to inductively define subshifts $X_n$ , $n\in {\mathbb N}$ . We start with $X_0 := X$ . We now assume that $X_n$ is defined for some $n \in {\mathbb N}$ . Then the set $X^{\prime }_{n+1} = \{x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n+1}: \sigma _n(x) \in X_n\}$ is a subshift. We define $X_{n+1}$ as any minimal subshift contained in $X^{\prime }_{n+1}$ . It follows from the definition of $X_{n+1}$ that $\bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma _n(X_{n+1}) \subseteq X_n$ . Being $X_n$ minimal,

(24) $$ \begin{align} \bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma_n(X_{n+1}) = X_n. \end{align} $$

Let $\tilde {{\mathcal A}}_n = {\mathcal A}_n \cap {\mathcal L}(X_n)$ . Equation (24) and the fact that $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is everywhere growing allow us to assume without loss of generality that, after a contraction of $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ , the following holds for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ :

(25) $$ \begin{align} \text{if}\ a\in\tilde{{\mathcal A}}_{n+1}\ \text{and}\ w \in {\mathcal L}(X_n)\ \text{has length}\ 3, \text{then}\ w\ \text{occurs twice in}\ \sigma_n(a). \end{align} $$

Let us fix a word $w_n = a_nb_nc_b \in {\mathcal L}(X_n)$ of length $3$ . Then, by (25), we can decompose $\sigma _n(a) = u_n(a)v_n(a)$ in a way such that

(26) $$ \begin{align} u_n(a)\ \text{ends with}\ a_n, v_n(a)\ \text{starts with}\ b_nc_n, \text{and}\ |v_n(a)| \geq 2. \end{align} $$

To define $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ , we need to introduce additional notation first. Let ${\mathcal B}_n$ be the alphabet consisting of tuples ${a\brack b}$ such that $ab \in {\mathcal L}(X_n)$ . Also, if $w = w_1\ldots w_{|w|} \in {\mathcal L}(X_n)$ has length $|w|\geq 2$ , then $\chi _n(w) := {w_1\brack w_2} {w_2\brack w_3}\ldots {w_{|w|-1}\brack w_{|w|}} \in {\mathcal B}_n^+$ , and if $w' = {w_1\brack w_2}\ldots {w_{|w|-1}\brack w_{|w|}} \in {\mathcal B}_0^+$ , then $\eta (w') := w_1\ldots w_{|w|-1} \in {\mathcal A}_0^+$ . Observe that $\eta \colon {\mathcal B}_0^+\to {\mathcal A}_0^+$ is a morphism.

We now define $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ . Let $\tau _n\colon {\mathcal B}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal B}_n^+$ be the unique morphism such that $\tau _n({a\brack b}) = \chi _n(v_n(a)u_n(a)b_n)$ for every ${a\brack b} \in {\mathcal B}_{n+1}$ . Observe that since $v_n(a)u_n(a)b_n \in {\mathcal L}(X_n)$ , it is indeed the case that $\tau _n({a\brack b})\in {\mathcal B}_n^+$ . We set $\boldsymbol {\tau } = (\eta \tau _0,\tau _1,\tau _2,\ldots )$ .

It follows from (26) that for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ and ${a\brack b} \in {\mathcal B}_{n+1}$ , $\tau _n({a\brack b})$ starts with ${b_n\brack c_n}$ and ends with ${a_n \brack b_n}$ . Thus, $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is proper. Moreover, since $|v_n(a)| \geq 2$ , we have $|v_n(a)u_n(a)b_n| \geq 3$ and thus $|\tau _n({a\brack b})| \geq 2$ . Therefore, $\langle \tau _n\rangle \geq 2$ and $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is everywhere growing. Also, $\#{\mathcal B}_n \leq \#{\mathcal A}_n^2 \leq K^2$ for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ , so the alphabet rank of $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is finite.

It remains to prove that $X = X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}$ . By minimality, it is enough to prove that $X \supseteq X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}$ . Observe that since $\tau _n\chi _{n+1}(ab) = \chi _n(v_n(a)u_n(b)b_n)$ , the word $\tau _n\chi _{n+1}(ab)$ occurs in $\chi _n\sigma _n(ab)$ . Moreover, for every $w = w_1\ldots w_{|w|} \in {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)})$ , $\tau _n\chi _{n+1}(w)$ occurs in $\chi _n\sigma _n(w)$ . Then, by using the symbol $\sqsubseteq $ to denote the ‘subword’ relation, we can write for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ and $ab \in {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)})$ :

$$ \begin{align*} \tau_{[0,n)}\chi_n(ab) &\sqsubseteq \tau_{[0,n-1)}\chi_{n-1}\sigma_{n-1}(ab) \\[3pt] &\sqsubseteq \tau_{[0,n-2)}\chi_{n-2}\sigma_{[n-2,n)}(ab) \sqsubseteq \cdots \sqsubseteq \chi_0\sigma_{[0,n)}(ab). \end{align*} $$

Hence, $\eta \tau _{[0,n)}({a\brack b}) \sqsubseteq \eta \chi _0\sigma _{[0,n)}(ab) \sqsubseteq \sigma _{[0,n)}(ab)$ . We conclude that $X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }} \subseteq X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }} = X$ .

Corollary 4.8. Let $(X,T)$ be a minimal subshift of topological rank K and $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,T)$ a factor map, where Y is an aperiodic subshift. Then, the topological rank of Y is at most K.

Proof. By Theorem 1.1, $(X,T)$ is generated by a proper and primitive directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ of alphabet rank equal to K. In particular, $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is everywhere growing and proper, so we can use Theorem 1.3 to obtain an everywhere growing, proper, and recognizable directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\tau } = (\tau _n\colon {\mathcal B}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal B}_n^+)_{n\geq 0}$ generating $(Y,T)$ and having alphabet rank at most K. Then, the hypothesis of Corollary 4.7 holds for $(Y,T)$ , and thus the topological rank of $(Y,T)$ is at most K.

The following notion will be used in the proof of the theorem below: $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n)_{n\geq 0}$ has exact alphabet rank at most K if $\#{\mathcal A}_n\leq K$ for all $n\geq 1$ .

Corollary 1.5. Let $(X,T)$ be an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing and proper sequence of alphabet rank K, and $\pi _j\colon (X_{j+1},T) \to (X_j,T)$ , $j=0,\ldots ,L$ be a chain of aperiodic symbolic factors, with $X_L = X$ . Suppose that $L> \log _2(K)$ . Then $\pi _j$ is a conjugacy for some j.

Proof. We start by using Theorem 1.3 with the identity function $\mathrm {id}\colon (X,T)\to (X,T)$ to obtain a letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, and recognizable directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\sigma _L}$ of alphabet rank at most K generating X. By doing a contraction, we can assume that $\boldsymbol {\sigma _L}$ has exact alphabet rank at most K.

By Theorem 1.3 applied to $\pi _{L-1}$ and $\boldsymbol {\sigma _L}$ , there exists, after a contraction of $\boldsymbol {\sigma _L}$ , a letter-onto factor $\boldsymbol {\phi _{L-1}}\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma _L}\to \boldsymbol {\sigma _{L-1}}$ , where $\boldsymbol {\sigma _{L-1}}$ is letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, recognizable, has alphabet rank at most K, generates $X_{L-1}$ , and, if $\phi _{L-1,0}$ and $\sigma _{L,0}$ are the first coordinates of $\boldsymbol {\phi _{L-1}}$ and $\boldsymbol {\sigma _{L}}$ , respectively, then $\pi _{L-1}(\sigma _{L,0}(x)) = \phi _{L-1,0}(x)$ for every $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma _L}}^{(1)}$ and $|\sigma _{L,0}(a)| = |\phi _{L-1,0}(a)|$ for every letter a in the domain of $\sigma _{L,0}$ . By contracting these sequences, we can also suppose that $\boldsymbol {\sigma _{L-1}}$ has exact alphabet rank at most K. The same procedure applies to $\pi _{L-2}$ and $\boldsymbol {\sigma _{L-1}}$ . Thus, by continuing in this way, we obtain for every $j=0,\ldots ,L-1$ a letter-onto factor $\boldsymbol {\phi _j}\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma _{j+1}}\to \boldsymbol {\sigma _j}$ such that the following holds.

  • $\boldsymbol {\sigma _j}$ is letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, recognizable, has exact alphabet rank at most K, generates $X_j$ , $\pi _{j}(\sigma _{j+1,0}(x)) = \phi _{j,0}(x)$ for every $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma _{j+1}}}^{(1)}$ , and $|\sigma _{j+1,0}(a)| = |\phi _{j,0}(a)|$ for every $a \in {\mathcal A}_{j+1,1}$ .

Here, we are using the notation $\boldsymbol {\sigma _j} = (\sigma _{j,n}\colon {\mathcal A}_{j,n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_{j,n}^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ , $\boldsymbol {\phi _j} = (\phi _{j,n}\colon {\mathcal A}_{j+1,n}^+\to {\mathcal A}_{j,n}^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ and $X_j^{(n)} = X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma _j}}^{(n)}$ . We note that:

  1. (△1 ) for every $x \in X_{j+1}^{(1)}$ , $\pi _j(\sigma _{j+1,0}(x)) = \phi _{j,0}(x) = \sigma _{j,0}\phi _{j,1}(x)$ since $\phi _{j,0} = \sigma _{j,0}\phi _{j,1}$ ;

  2. (△2 ) $X_j^{(1)} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi _{j,1}(X_{j+1}^{(1)})$ by Lemma 4.3.

Hence, the following diagram commutes:

Claim 4.8.1. If $(X_{j+1}^{(1)}, \phi _{j,1})$ is recognizable, then $\pi _j$ is a conjugacy.

Proof. Let us assume that $(X_{j+1}^{(1)}, \phi _{j,1})$ is recognizable, and let, for $i=0,1$ , $x^i \in X_{j+1}^{(1)}$ such that $y = \pi _j(x^0) = \pi _j(x^1)$ . We have to show that $x^0 = x^1$ . First, we use Lemma 2.5 to find a centered $\sigma _{j+1,0}$ -factorization $(k^i,z^i)$ of $x^i$ in $X_{j+1}^{(1)}$ . Then, equation $\triangle _1$ allows us to compute:

$$ \begin{align*} T^{k^0}\sigma_{j,0}\phi_{j,1}(z^0) = T^{k^0}\pi_j(\sigma_{j+1,0}(z^0)) = \pi_j(x^0) = \pi_j(x^1) = T^{k^1}\sigma_{j,0}\phi_{j,1}(z^1). \end{align*} $$

This implies that $(k^i,z^i)$ is a $\sigma _{j,0}\phi _{j,1}$ -factorization of y in $X_{j+1}^{(1)}$ for $i=0,1$ . Moreover, these are centered factorizations as, by $\bullet $ , $|\sigma _{j,0}\phi _{j,1}(a)| = |\sigma _{j+1,0}(a)|$ for all $a \in {\mathcal A}_{j+1,1}$ . Now, being $(X_j^{(1)},\sigma _{0,j})$ and $(X_{j+1}^{(1)}, \phi _{j,1})$ recognizable, Lemma 2.3 gives that $(X_{j+1}^{(1)},\sigma _{j,1}\phi _{j,1})$ is recognizable, and thus we have that $(k^0,z^0) = (k^1,z^1)$ . Therefore, $x^0 = x^1$ and $\pi $ is a conjugacy.

Now we can finish the proof. We assume, by contradiction, that $\pi _j$ is not a conjugacy for all j. Then, by the claim,

(27) $$ \begin{align} (X_j^{(1)},\phi_{1,j})\ \text{is not recognizable for every}\ j \in \{0,\ldots,L-1\}. \end{align} $$

Let

$$ \begin{align*} \boldsymbol{\nu} = (\phi_{0,1}, \phi_{1,1}, \phi_{2,1}, \ldots,\phi_{L-1,1},\sigma_{L,1}, \sigma_{L,2}, \sigma_{L,3}, \ldots). \end{align*} $$

The idea is to use Theorem 2.7 with $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ to obtain a contradiction. To do so, we first note that, since $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ and $\boldsymbol {\sigma }^{(L)}$ have the same ‘tail’, $X_{\boldsymbol {\nu }}^{(m+L)} = X_{L}^{(m+1)}$ for all $m \in {\mathbb N}$ . Moreover, $\triangle _2$ and the previous relation imply that

$$ \begin{align*} X_{\boldsymbol{\nu}}^{(j)} &= \bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}} T^k\phi_{j,1}(X_{\boldsymbol{\nu}}^{(j+1)}) = \cdots = \bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}} T^k\phi_{j,1}\ldots\phi_{L-1,1}(X_{\boldsymbol{\nu}}^{(L)}) \\[3pt] &= \bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}} T^k\phi_{j,1}\ldots\phi_{L-1,1}(X_{L}^{(1)}) = \bigcup_{k\in{\mathbb Z}} T^k\phi_{j,1}\ldots\phi_{L-2,1}(X_{L-1}^{(1)}) = \cdots = X_j^{(1)}. \end{align*} $$

This and (27) imply that for every $j \in \{1,\ldots ,L-1\}$ , the level $(X_{\boldsymbol {\nu }}^{(j)}, \phi _{j,1})$ of $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ is not recognizable. Being $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ everywhere growing as $\boldsymbol {\sigma _L}$ has this property, we conclude that Theorem 2.7 can be applied and, therefore, that $X_0^{(1)} = X_{\boldsymbol {\nu }}$ is periodic. However, then $X_0 = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma _{0,0}(X_0^{(1)})$ is periodic, contrary to our assumptions.

A system $(X,T)$ is coalescent if every endomorphism $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (X,T)$ is an automorphism. This notion has been relevant in the context of topological dynamics; see for example [Reference DownarowiczDow97].

Corollary 4.9. Let $(X,T)$ be an ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshift generated by an everywhere growing and proper directive sequence of finite alphabet rank. Then, $(X,T)$ is coalescent.

Remark 4.10. A linearly recurrent subshift of constant C is generated by a primitive and proper directive sequence of alphabet rank at most $C(C+1)^2$ [Reference DurandDur00, Proposition 6]. In [Reference Durand, Host and SkauDHS99], the authors proved the following.

Theorem 4.11. [Reference Durand, Host and SkauDHS99, Theorem 3]

For a linearly recurrent subshift X of constant C, in any chain of factors $\pi _j\colon (X_j,T)\to (X_{j+1},T)$ , $j=0,\ldots ,L$ , with $X_0 = X$ and $L \geq (2C(2C+1)^2)^{4C^3(2C+1)^2}$ , there is at least one $\pi _j$ which is a conjugacy.

Thus, Theorem 1.5 is not only a generalization of this result to a much larger class of systems, but also improves the previous super-exponential constant to a logarithmic one.

In Proposition 28 of [Reference Durand, Host and SkauDHS99], the authors proved that Cantor factors of linearly recurrent systems are either subshifts or odometers. Their proof only uses that this kind of system satisfies the strong coalescence property that we proved in Corollary 4.9 for finite topological rank systems. Therefore, by the same proof, we have the following.

Corollary 4.12. Let $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Y,T)$ be a factor map between minimal systems. Assume that $(X,T)$ has finite topological rank and that $(Y,T)$ is a Cantor system. Then, $(Y,T)$ is either a subshift or a odometer.

Proof. We sketch the proof from [Reference Durand, Host and SkauDHS99] that we mentioned above.

Let $({\mathcal P}_n)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ be a sequence of clopen partitions of Y such that ${\mathcal P}_{n+1}$ is finer than ${\mathcal P}_n$ and their union generates the topology of Y. Also, let $Y_n$ be the subshift obtained by codifying the orbits of $(Y,T)$ by using the atoms of ${\mathcal P}_n$ . Then, the fact that ${\mathcal P}_n$ is a clopen partition induces a factor map $\pi _n\colon (Y,T) \to (Y_n,T)$ . Moreover, since ${\mathcal P}_{n+1}$ is finer than ${\mathcal P}_n$ , there exists a factor map $\xi _n\colon (Y_{n+1},T)\to (Y_n,T)$ such that $\xi _n\pi _{n+1} = \pi _n$ . Hence, we have the following chain of factors:

$$ \begin{align*} (X,T) \overset{\pi}{\longrightarrow} (Y,T) \overset{\pi_n}{\longrightarrow} (Y_n,T) \overset{\xi_{n-1}}{\longrightarrow} (Y_{n-1},T) \overset{\xi_{n-2}}{\longrightarrow} \cdots \overset{\xi_{1}}{\longrightarrow} (Y_0,T). \end{align*} $$

We conclude, by also using the fact that the partitions ${\mathcal P}_n$ generate the topology of Y, that $(Y,T)$ is conjugate to the inverse limit $\overleftarrow {\lim }_{n\to \infty }(Y_n;\xi _n)$ .

Now we consider two cases. If $Y_n$ is periodic for every $n \in {\mathbb N}$ , then Y is the inverse limit of periodic system, and hence an odometer. In the other case, we have, by Corollary 1.5, that $\xi _n$ is a conjugacy for all big enough $n \in {\mathbb N}$ , and thus that $(Y,T)$ is conjugate to one of the subshifts $Y_n$ .

5 Fibers of symbolic factors

The objective of this section is to prove Theorem 1.6, which states that factor maps $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,T)$ between ${\mathcal S}$ -adic subshifts of finite topological rank are always almost k-to- $1$ for some k bounded by the topological rank of X. We start with some lemmas from topological dynamics.

Lemma 5.1. [Reference AuslanderAus88]

Let $\pi \colon X \to Y $ be a continuous map between compact metric spaces. Then $\pi ^{-1}\colon Y \to 2^X$ is continuous at every point of a residual subset of Y.

The next lemma gives a sufficient condition for a factor map $\pi $ to be almost k-to-1. Recall that $E(X,T)$ stands for the Ellis semigroup of $(X,T)$ .

Lemma 5.2. Let $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Y,T)$ be a factor map between topological dynamical systems, with $(Y,T)$ minimal and $K\geq 1$ an integer. Suppose that for every $y \in Y$ , there exists $u \in E(2^X,T)$ such that $\#u\circ \pi ^{-1}(y) \leq K$ . Then, $\pi $ is almost k-to-1 for some $k\leq K$ .

Proof. First, we observe that by the description of $u\circ A$ in terms of nets at the end of §2.1, we have

(28) $$ \begin{align} \# u\circ A \leq \#A,\quad\text{for all } u\in E(2^X,T),\ A\in 2^X. \end{align} $$

Now, by the previous lemma, there exists a residual set $\tilde {Y} \subseteq Y$ of continuity points for $\pi ^{-1}$ . Let $y,y'\in \tilde {Y}$ be arbitrary. Since Y is minimal, there exists a sequence $(n_\ell )_\ell $ such that $\lim _\ell T^{n_\ell }y = y'$ . If $w \in E(2^X,T)$ is the limit of a convergent subnet of $(T^{n_\ell })_\ell $ , then $wy = y'$ . By the continuity of $\pi ^{-1}$ at $y'$ and (28), we have

$$ \begin{align*} \#\pi^{-1}(y') = \#\pi^{-1}(wy) =\#w\circ \pi^{-1}(y) \leq \#\pi^{-1}(y). \end{align*} $$

We deduce, by symmetry, that $\#\pi ^{-1}(y') = \#\pi ^{-1}(y)$ . Hence, $k:= \pi ^{-1}(y)$ does not depend on the chosen $y\in \tilde {Y}$ . To end the proof, we have to show that $k\leq K$ . We fix $y \in \tilde {Y}$ and take, using the hypothesis, $u \in E(2^X,T)$ such that $\#u\circ \pi ^{-1}(y) \leq K$ . As above, by minimality, there exists $v\in E(2^X,T)$ such that $vuy = y$ . Then, by the continuity of $\pi ^{-1}$ at y,

$$ \begin{align*} \pi^{-1}(y) = \pi^{-1}(vuy) = (vu)\circ\pi^{-1}(y) = v\circ (u\circ\pi^{-1}(y)). \end{align*} $$

This and (28) imply that $k = \#\pi ^{-1}(y) \leq \#u\circ \pi ^{-1}(y) \leq K$ .

Let $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism, $(k,x)$ a centered $\sigma $ -factorization of $y \in {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z}$ in ${\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ , and $\ell \in {\mathbb Z}$ . Note that there exists a unique $j \in {\mathbb Z}$ such that $\ell \in [c_{\sigma ,j}(k,x), c_{\sigma ,j+1}(k,x))$ (recall the notion of cut from Definition 2.1). In this context, we say that $(c_{\sigma ,j}(k,x),x_j)$ is the symbol of $(k,x)$ covering position $\ell $ of y.

Theorem 1.6. Let $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Y,T)$ be a factor between subshifts, with $(Y,T)$ minimal and aperiodic. Suppose that X is generated by a proper and everywhere growing directive sequence $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ of alphabet rank K. Then, $\pi $ is almost k-to-1 for some $k\leq K$ .

Proof. Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}\to {\mathcal A}_n)_{n\geq 0}$ be a proper and everywhere growing directive sequence of alphabet rank at most K generating X. Due the possibility of contracting $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ , we can assume without loss of generality that $\#{\mathcal A}_{n} \leq K$ for every $n\geq 1$ and that $\sigma _0$ is r-proper, where r is the radius of $\pi $ . Then, by Lemma 2.4, Y is generated by an everywhere growing directive sequence of the form $\boldsymbol {\tau } = (\tau ,\sigma _1,\sigma _2,\ldots )$ , where $\tau \colon {\mathcal A}_1^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ is such that $\tau (x) = \pi (\sigma _0(x))$ for every $x\in X_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(1)} = X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(1)}$ . We will use the notation $\tau _{[0,n)} = \tau \sigma _{[1,n)}$ . Further, for $y \in Y$ and $n\geq 1$ , we write $F_n(y)$ to denote the set of $\tau _{[0,n)}$ -factorizations of y in $Y_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ .

Before continuing, we prove the following claim.

Claim 5.2.1. There exist $\ell _n\in {\mathbb Z}$ and $G_n \subseteq {\mathbb Z}\times {\mathcal B}_{n+1}$ with at most K elements such that if $(k,x)\in F_n(y)$ , then the symbol of $(k,x)$ covering position $\ell _n$ of y is in $G_n$ .

Proof. First, since Y is aperiodic, there exists $L \in {\mathbb N}$ such that

(29) $$ \begin{align} \text{all words}\ w \in {\mathcal L}(Y)\ \text{of length}\ \geq L\ \text{have at least period greater than}\ |\tau_{[0,n)}|. \end{align} $$

We assume, by contradiction, that the claim does not hold. In particular, for every $\ell \in [0,L)$ , there exist $K+1 \tau _{[0,n)}$ -factorizations $(x,k)$ of y in $Y_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ such that their symbols covering position $\ell $ of y are all different. Now, since $\#\tau _{[0,n)}({\mathcal A}_{n+1}) \leq K$ , we can use the pigeonhole principle to find two of such factorizations, say $(k,x)$ and $(k',x')$ , such that if $(c,a)$ and $(c',a')$ are their symbols covering position $\ell $ of y, then $a = a'$ and $c<c'$ . Then,

$$ \begin{align*} y_{(c,c+|\tau_{[0,n)}(a)|]} = \tau_{[0,n)}(a) = y_{(c',c'+|\tau_{[0,n)}(a)|]} \end{align*} $$

and, thus, $y_{(c,c'+|\tau _{[0,n)}(a)|]}$ is $(c'-c)$ -periodic. Being $\ell \in (c',c+|\tau _{[0,n)}(a)|)$ , we deduce that the local period of $y_{[0,L)}$ at $\ell $ is at most $c'-c \leq |\tau _{[0,n)}|$ . Since this is true for every $\ell \in [0,L)$ and since, by Theorem 3.7, ${\mathrm {per}}(y_{[0,L)}) = {\mathrm {per}}(y_{[0,L)}, y_{[0,\ell )})$ for some $\ell \in [0,L)$ , we conclude that ${\mathrm {per}}(y_{[0,L)}) \leq |\tau _{[0,n)}|$ . This contradicts (29) and proves thereby the claim.

Now we prove the theorem. It is enough to show that the hypothesis of Lemma 5.2 holds. Let $y \in Y$ and $\tilde {F}_n(y) \subseteq F_n(y)$ be such that $\#\tilde {F}_n(y) = \#G_n$ and the set consisting of all the symbols of factorizations $(k,x) \in \tilde {F}_n(y)$ covering position $\ell _n$ of y is equal to $G_n$ . Let $z \in \pi ^{-1}(y)$ and $(k,x)$ be a $\sigma _{[0,n)}$ -factorization of z in $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}$ . Then, $T^k\tau _{[0,n)}(x) = T^k\pi (\sigma _{[0,n)}(x)) = \pi (z) = y$ and $(k,x)$ is a $\tau _{[0,n)}$ -factorization of y in $Y_{\boldsymbol {\tau }}^{(n)}$ . Thus, we can find $(k',x') \in \tilde {F}_n(y)$ such that the symbols of $(k,x)$ and $(k',x')$ covering position $\ell _n$ of y are the same; let $(m,a)$ be this common symbol. Since $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is proper, we have

$$ \begin{align*} z_{[m-\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle,m+|\sigma_{[0,n)}(a)|+\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle]} = z^{\prime}_{[m-\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle,m+|\sigma_{[0,n)}(a)|+\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle]}, \end{align*} $$

where $z' = T^{k'}\sigma _{[0,n)}(x') \in X$ is the point that $(k',x')$ factorizes in $(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)}, \sigma _{[0,n)})$ . Then, as $\ell _n \in (m, m+|\sigma _{[0,n)}(a)|]$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} z_{(\ell_n-\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle, \ell_n+\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle]} = z^{\prime}_{(\ell_n-\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle, \ell_n+\langle\sigma_{[0,n-1)}\rangle]}. \end{align*} $$

Thus, $\mathrm {dist}(T^{\ell _n}z, T^{\ell _n}P_n(y)) \leq \exp (-\langle \sigma _{[0,n-1)}\rangle )$ , where $P_n(y)\subseteq \pi ^{-1}(y)$ is the set of all points $T^{k''}\sigma _{[0,n)}(x'') \in X$ such that $(k'',x'') \in \tilde {F}_n(y)$ . Since this holds for every $n \geq 1$ , we obtain that $d_{\mathrm {H}}(T^{\ell _n}\pi ^{-1}(y),T^{\ell _n} P_n(y))$ converges to zero as n goes to infinity (where, we recall, $d_{\mathrm {H}}$ is the Hausdorff distance). By taking an appropriate convergent subnet $u \in E(2^X,T)$ of $(T^{\ell _n})_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ , we obtain $\# u\circ \pi ^{-1}(y) \leq \sup _{n\in {\mathbb N}}\#P_n = \sup _{n\in {\mathbb N}}\#G_n \leq K$ . This proves that the hypothesis of Lemma 5.2 holds. Therefore, $\pi $ is almost k-to-1 for some $k\leq K$ .

6 Number of symbolic factors

In this section, we prove Theorem 1.7. To do this, we split the proof into three subsections. First, in Lemma 6.3 of §6.1, we deal with the case of Theorem 1.7 in which the factor maps are distal. Next, we show in Lemma 6.7 from §6.2 that in certain technical situation—which will arise when we consider non-distal factor maps—it is possible to reduce the problem to a similar one, but where the alphabet is smaller. Then, we prove Theorem 1.7 in §6.3 by a repeated application of the previous lemmas.

6.1 Distal factor maps

We start with some definitions. If $(X,T)$ is a system, then we always give $X^k$ the diagonal action $T^{[k]} := T\times \cdots \times T$ . If $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,T)$ is a factor map and $k \geq 1$ , then we define $R_\pi ^k = \{(x^1,\ldots ,x^k)\in X^k : \pi (x^1) = \cdots =\pi (x^k)\}$ . Observe that $R_\pi ^k$ is a closed $T^{[k]}$ -invariant subset of $X^k$ .

The next lemma follows from classical ideas from topological dynamics. See, for example, theorem 6 in ch. 10 of [Reference AuslanderAus88].

Lemma 6.1. Let $\pi \colon (X,T)\to (Y,T)$ be a distal almost k-to-1 factor between minimal systems, $z = (z^1,\ldots ,z^k) \in R_\pi ^k$ and $Z = \overline {\mathrm {orb}}_{T^{[k]}}(z)$ . Then, $\pi $ is k-to-1 and Z is minimal.

We will also need the following lemma.

Lemma 6.2. [Reference DurandDur00, Lemma 21]

Let $\pi _i\colon (X,T) \to (Y_i,T)$ , $i=0,1$ , be two factors between aperiodic minimal systems. Suppose that $\pi _0$ is finite-to-one. If $x,y\in X$ are such that $\pi _0(x) = \pi _0(y)$ and $\pi _1(x) = T^p\pi _1(y)$ , then $p=0$ .

Lemma 6.3. Let $(X,T)$ be an infinite minimal subshift of topological rank K and J an index set of cardinality $\#J> K(144K^7)^K$ . Suppose that for every $j \in J$ there exists a distal symbolic factor $\pi _j\colon (X,T)\to (Y_j,T)$ . Then, there are $i\not =j \in J$ such that $(Y_i,T)$ is conjugate to $(Y_j,T)$ .

Proof. We start by introducing the necessary objects for the proof and doing some general observations about them. First, thanks to Theorem 1.6, we know that $\pi _j$ is almost $k_j$ -to-1 for some $k_j \leq K$ , so, by the pigeonhole principle, there exist $J_1 \subseteq J$ and $k \leq K$ such that $\#J_1 \geq \#J/K> (144K^7)^K$ and $k_j = k$ for every $j \in J_1$ . For $j \in J_1$ , we fix $z^j = (z_1^j, \ldots , z_k^j) \in R_{\pi _j}^k$ with $z_n^j \not = z_m^j$ for all $n\not =m$ . Let $Z_j = \overline {\mathrm {orb}}_{T^{[k]}}(z^j)$ and $\rho \colon X^k\to X$ be the factor map that projects onto the first coordinate. By Lemma 6.1, $\pi _j$ is k-to-1 and $Z_j$ minimal. This implies that if $x = (x_1,\ldots ,x_k) \in Z_j$ , then

(30) $$ \begin{align} \{x_1,\ldots,x_k\} &= \pi_j^{-1}(\pi_j(x_n)) \quad\text{for all}\ n\in \{1,\ldots,k\}, \end{align} $$
(31) $$ \begin{align} x_n &\not= x_m \quad\text{for all}\ n,m \in \{1,\ldots,k\}. \end{align} $$

Indeed, since $Z_j$ is minimal, $(T^{[k]})^{n_\ell }z \to x$ for some sequence $(n_\ell )_\ell $ , so,

$$\begin{align*}\inf_{n\not=m}\mathrm{dist}(x_n,x_m) \geq \inf_{n\not=m, l\in{\mathbb Z}}\mathrm{dist}(T^lz_n,T^lz_m)> 0,\end{align*}$$

where in the last step is due to the fact that $\pi _j$ is distal. This gives (31). For (30), we first note that $\{x_1,\ldots ,x_k\} \subseteq \pi _j^{-1}(\pi _j(x_n))$ as $x \in R_{\pi _j}$ , and then that the equality must hold since $\#\pi _j^{-1}(\pi _j(x_n)) = k = \#\{x_1,\ldots ,x_k\}$ by (31).

The next step is to prove that asymptotic pairs in $Z_j$ are well-behaved.

Claim 6.3.1. Let $j \in J_1$ and $(x^j = (x_1^j,\ldots ,x_k^j)$ , $\tilde {x}^j = (\tilde {x}_1^j,\ldots ,\tilde {x}_k^j))$ be a right asymptotic pair in $Z_j$ , this is,

(32) $$ \begin{align} \lim_{n\to-\infty}\mathrm{dist}((T^{[k]})^nx^j, T^{[k]}\tilde{x}^j) = 0\quad\text{and}\quad x^j \not= \tilde{x}^j. \end{align} $$

Then, $(x_n^j,\tilde {x}_n^j)$ is right asymptotic for every $n \in \{1,\ldots ,k\}$ .

Proof. Suppose, with the aim to obtain a contradiction, that $(x_n^j, \tilde {x}_n^j)$ is not right asymptotic for some $n \in \{1,\ldots ,k\}$ . Observe that (32) implies that

(33) $$ \begin{align} \text{for every}\ m \in \{1,\ldots,k\}, \text{either}\ (x_m^j,\tilde{x}_m^j)\ \text{is right asymptotic or}\ x_n^j = \tilde{x}_n^j. \end{align} $$

Therefore, $x_n^j = \tilde {x}_n^j$ . Using this and that $x^j,\tilde {x}^j \in R_{\pi _j}^k$ , we can compute:

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_j(x_m^j) = \pi_j(x_n^j) = \pi_j(\tilde{x}_n^j) = \pi_j(\tilde{x}_l^j) \quad\text{for all } m,l\in\{1,\ldots,k\}, \end{align*} $$

and thus, by (30),

$$ \begin{align*} \{x_1^j,\ldots,x_k^j\} = \pi_j^{-1}(\pi_j(x_n^j)) = \pi_j^{-1}(\pi_j(\tilde{x}_n^j)) = \{\tilde{x}_1^j,\ldots,\tilde{x}_k^j\}. \end{align*} $$

The last equation, (31), and that $x^j\not =\tilde {x}^j$ imply that there exist $m\not =l \in \{1,\ldots ,k\}$ such that $\tilde {x}_{l}^j = x_m^j$ . This last equality and (33) tell us that $x^j_m$ and $x^j_l$ are either asymptotic or equal. However, in both cases a contradiction occurs: in the first one with the distality of $\pi $ and in the second one with (31).

Let $j \in J_1$ . Since $Y_j$ is infinite, $Z_j$ is a infinite subshift. It is a well-known fact from symbolic dynamics that this implies that there exists a right asymptotic pair $(x^j = (x_1^j,\ldots ,x_k^j)$ , $\tilde {x}^j = (\tilde {x}_1^j,\ldots ,\tilde {x}_k^j))$ in $Z_j$ . We are now going to use Theorem 2.8 to prove the following.

Claim 6.3.2. There exists $i,j \in J_1$ , $i\not =j$ , such that $Z_i = Z_j$ .

Proof. On one hand, by the previous claim, $(x_n^j, \tilde {x}_n^j) \in X^2$ is right asymptotic for every $n \in \{1,\ldots , k\}$ and $j \in J_1$ . Let $p_n^j \in {\mathbb Z}$ be such that $(T^{p_n^j}x_n^j, T^{p_n^j}\tilde {x}_n^j)$ is centered right asymptotic. On the other hand, Theorem 2.8 asserts that the set

$$ \begin{align*} \{ x_{(0,\infty)} : (x,\tilde{x}) \text{ is centered right asymptotic in }X\} \end{align*} $$

has at most $144K^7$ elements. Since $\#J_1> (144K^7)^K$ , we conclude, by the pigeonhole principle, that there exist $i,j \in J_1$ , $i\not =j$ , such that

(34) $$ \begin{align} T^{p_n^i}x_n^i \text{ and } T^{p_n^j}x_n^j \text{ agree on }(0,\infty) \text{ for every }n \in \{1,\ldots,k\}. \end{align} $$

We are going to show that $Z_i = Z_j$ .

Using (34), we can find $u \in E(X,T)$ such that $uT^{p_n^i}x_n^i = uT^{p_n^j}x_n^j$ for every n. Then, by putting $y_n^i = ux_n^i$ , $y_n^j = ux_n^j$ and $q_n = p_n^j-p_n^i$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} y^i := (y_1^i,\ldots,y_k^i) \in Z_i, y^j := (y_1^j,\ldots,y_k^j) \in Z_j\text{ and } y_n^i = T^{q_n}y_n^j. \end{align*} $$

Hence, $\pi (y_n^i) = T^{q_n}\pi (y_n^j)$ and Lemma 6.2 can be applied to deduce that $q := q_n$ has the same value for every n. We conclude that $y^i = T^qy^j \in T^qZ_j = Z_j$ , that $Z_i \cap Z_j$ is not empty, and, therefore, that $Z_i = Z_j$ as these are minimal systems.

We can now finish the proof. Let $i\not =j\in J_1$ be the elements given by the previous claim, so that $Z := Z_i = Z_j$ . Let $y \in Y_i$ and $x = (x_1,\ldots ,x_k) \in \rho ^{-1}\pi _i^{-1}(y)\cap Z$ . Then, by (30), $\pi _i^{-1}(y) = \{x_1,\ldots ,x_k\} = \pi _j^{-1}(\pi _j(x_1))$ , and so $\pi _j\pi _i^{-1}(y)$ contains exactly one element, which is $\pi _j(x_1)$ . We define $\psi \colon Y_i\to Y_j$ by $\psi (y) = \pi _j(x_1)$ .

Observe that $\pi _i^{-1}\colon Y_i\to 2^X$ is continuous (as $\pi _i$ is distal and hence open) and commutes with T. Being $\pi _j$ a factor map, $\psi $ is continuous and commutes with T. Therefore, $\psi \colon (Y_i,T)\to (Y_j,T)$ is a factor map. A similar construction gives a factor map $\phi \colon Y_j\to Y_i$ which is the inverse function of $\psi $ . We conclude that $\psi $ is a conjugacy and, thus, that $Y_i$ and $Y_j$ are conjugate.

6.2 Non-distal factor maps and asymptotic pairs lying in fibers

To deal with non-factor maps, we study asymptotic pairs belonging to fibers of this kind of factor. The starting point is the following lemma.

Lemma 6.4. Let $\pi \colon (X,T) \to (Y,T)$ be a factor between minimal subshifts. Then, either $\pi $ is distal or there exists a fiber $\pi ^{-1}(y)$ containing a pair of right or left asymptotic points.

Proof. Assume that $\pi $ is not distal. Then, we can find a fiber $\pi ^{-1}(y)$ and proximal points $x,x' \in \pi ^{-1}(y)$ , with $x\not =x'$ . This implies that for every $k \in {\mathbb N}$ , there exist a (may be infinite) interval $I_k = (a_k,b_k) \subseteq {\mathbb Z}$ , with $b_k-a_k\geq k$ , for which x and $x'$ coincide on I, and $I_k$ is maximal (with respect to the inclusion) with this property. Since $x\not =x'$ , then $a_k> -\infty $ or $b_k < \infty $ . Hence, there exists an infinite set $E \subseteq {\mathbb N}$ such that $a_k> -\infty $ for every $k \in E$ or $b_k < \infty $ for every $k \in E$ . In the first case, we have that $(T^{b_k}(x,x'))_{k\in E}$ has a left asymptotic pair $(z,z')$ as an accumulation point, while in the second case, it is a right asymptotic pair $(z,z')$ which is an accumulation point of $(T^{a_k}(x,x'))_{k\in E}$ . In both cases we have that $(z,z') \in R_\pi ^2$ since $(T^{b_k}(x,x'))_{k\in E}$ and $(T^{a_k}(x,x'))_{k\in E}$ are contained in $R_\pi ^2$ and $R_\pi ^2$ is closed. Therefore, the fiber $\pi ^{-1}(\pi (z))$ contains a pair $z,z'$ of asymptotic points.

The next lemma allows us to pass from morphisms $\sigma \colon X\to Y$ to factors $\pi \colon X'\to Y$ in such a way that $X'$ is defined on the same alphabet as X and has the ‘same’ asymptotic pairs. We remark that its proof is simple, but tedious.

Lemma 6.5. Let $X \subseteq {\mathcal A}^+$ be an aperiodic subshift, $\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism, and $Y = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\sigma (X)$ . Define the morphism $i_\sigma \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal A}^+$ by $i_\sigma (a) = a^{|\sigma (a)|}$ , $a \in {\mathcal A}$ , and $X' = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^ki_\sigma (X)$ . Then, centered asymptotic pairs in $X'$ are of the form $(i_\sigma (x),i_\sigma (\tilde {x}))$ , where $(x,\tilde {x})$ is a centered asymptotic pair in X, and there exists a factor map $\pi \colon (X',T)\to (Y,T)$ such that $\pi (i_\sigma (x)) = \tau (x)$ for all $x \in X$ .

Proof. Our first objective is to prove that $(X,i_\sigma )$ is recognizable. We start by observing that

(35) $$ \begin{align} \text{if}\ (k,x), (\tilde{k},\tilde{x})\ \text{are centered}\ i_\sigma\text{-factorizations of}\ y \in X',\quad \text{then}\ x_0 = \tilde{x}_0. \end{align} $$

Indeed, since the factorizations are centered, we have $x_0 = i_\sigma (x_0)_k = y_0 = i_\sigma (\tilde {x}_0)_{\tilde {k}} = \tilde {x}_0$ .

Let $\Lambda $ be the set of tuples $(k,x,\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ such that $(k,x),(\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ are centered $i_\sigma $ -factorizations of the same point. Moreover, for ${\mathcal R} \in \{=,>\}$ , let $\Lambda _{\mathcal R}$ be the set of those $(k,x,\tilde {k},\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda $ satisfying $k\ {\mathcal R}\ \tilde {k}$ .

Claim 6.5.1. If $(k,x,\tilde {k},\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _=$ , then $(0,Tx,0,T\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _=$ , and if $(k,x,\tilde {k},\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _>$ , then $(|i_\sigma (x_0)|-k+\tilde {k},\tilde {x},0,Tx) \in \Lambda _>$ .

Proof. If $(k,x,\tilde {k},\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _=$ , then, since $x_0 = \tilde {x}_0$ by (35), we can write $i_\sigma (Tx) = T^ki_\sigma (x) = T^{\tilde {k}}i_\sigma (\tilde {x}) = i_\sigma (T\tilde {x})$ . Thus, $(0,Tx,0,T\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _=$ . Let now $(k,x,\tilde {k},\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _>$ and $y := T^ki_\sigma (x) = T^{\tilde {k}}i_\sigma (\tilde {x})$ . We note that

$$ \begin{align*} T^{|i_\sigma(x_0)|-k+\tilde{k}}i_\sigma(\tilde{x}) = T^{|i_\sigma(x_0)|-k}y = T^{|i_\sigma(x_0)|}i_\sigma(x) = i_\sigma(Tx), \end{align*} $$

so $(|i_\sigma (x_0)|-k+\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ and $(0,Tx)$ are $i_\sigma $ -factorizations of the same point. Now, since $x_0 = \tilde {x}_0$ (by (35)) and $(k,x),(\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ are centered, we have $k,\tilde {k}\in [0,|i_\sigma (x_0)|)$ . This and the fact that $k>\tilde {k}$ imply that $k-\tilde {k}\in (0,|i_\sigma (x_0)|)$ . Therefore, $|i_\sigma (x_0)|-k+\tilde {k} \in (0,|i_\sigma (x_0)|)$ and, consequently, $(|i_\sigma (x_0)|-k+\tilde {k},\tilde {x},0,Tx) \in \Lambda _>$ .

We prove now that $(X,i_\sigma )$ is recognizable. Let $(k,x,\tilde {k},\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda $ . We have to show that $(k,x) = (\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ . First, we consider the case in which $k = \tilde {k}$ . In this situation, the previous claim implies that $(0,Tx,0,T\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _=$ . We use again the claim, but with $(0,Tx,0,T\tilde {x})$ , to obtain that $(0,T^2x,0,T^2\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _=$ . By continuing in this way, we get $(0,T^nx,0,T^n\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _=$ for any $n\geq 0$ . Then, (35) implies that $x_n = \tilde {x}_n$ for all $n\geq 0$ . A similar argument shows that $x_n = \tilde {x}_n$ for any $n\leq 0$ , and so $(k,x) = (\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ . We now do the case $k> \tilde {k}$ . Another application of the claim gives us $(p_1,\tilde {x},0,Tx) \in \Lambda _>$ for some $p_1 \in {\mathbb Z}$ . As before, we iterate this procedure to obtain that $(p_2,Tx,0,T\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda _>$ , $(p_3,T\tilde {x},0,T^2x) \in \Lambda _>$ , and so on. From these relations and (35), we deduce that $x_0 = \tilde {x}_0$ , $\tilde {x}_0 = (Tx)_0 = x_1$ , $x_1 = (Tx)_0 = (T\tilde {x})_0 = \tilde {x}_1$ , $\tilde {x}_1 = (T\tilde {x})_0 = (T^2x)_0 = x_2$ , etc. We conclude that $x_n = \tilde {x}_n = x_0$ for any $n \geq 0$ . Then, by compacity, the periodic point $\cdots x_0.x_0x_0\cdots $ belongs to X, contrary to our aperiodicity hypothesis on X. Thus, the case $k> \tilde {k}$ does not occur. This proves that $(X,i_\sigma )$ is recognizable.

Using the property we just proved, we can define the factor map $\pi \colon X'\to Y$ as follows: if $x' \in X'$ , then we set $\pi (x') = T^k\tau (x) \in Y$ , where $(k,x)$ is the unique centered $i_\sigma $ -factorization of $x'$ in X. To show that $\pi $ is indeed a factor map, we first observe that since

(36) $$ \begin{align} |\tau(a)| = |i_\sigma(a)| \quad\text{for all }a \in {\mathcal A}, \end{align} $$

$\pi $ commutes with T. Moreover, thanks to condition (iii) in Remark 2.2, $\pi $ is continuous. Finally, if $y \in Y$ , then by the definition of Y, there exist a centered $(k,x) \tau $ -factorization of y in X. Thus, by (36), $(k,x)$ is a centered $i_\sigma $ factorization of $x' := T^ki_\sigma (x)$ . Therefore, $\pi (x') = y$ and $\pi $ is onto. Altogether, these arguments show that $\pi $ is a factor map. That $\pi (i_\sigma (x)) = \tau (x)$ for every $x \in X$ follows directly from the definition of $\pi $ .

It is left to prove the property about the asymptotic pairs. We only prove it for left asymptotic pairs since the other case is similar. We will use the following notation: if Z is a subshift, then $A(Z)$ denotes the set of centered left asymptotic pairs. To start, we observe that $(i_\sigma (x),i_\sigma (x')) \in A(X')$ for every $(x,\tilde {x}) \in A(X)$ . Let now $(z,\tilde {z}) \in A(X')$ , and $(k,x)$ and $(\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ be the unique centered $i_\sigma $ -factorizations of z and $\tilde {z}$ in X, respectively. We have to show that $k = \tilde {k} = 0$ and that $(x,\tilde {x}) \in A(X)$ . Due to condition (iii) in Remark 2.2, $(X,i_\sigma )$ has a recognizability constant. This and the fact that $(z,\tilde {z})$ is centered left asymptotic imply that $(k,x)$ and $(\tilde {k},\tilde {x})$ have a common cut in $(-\infty ,0]$ , this is, that there exist $p,q \leq 0$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} m := -k-|i_\sigma(x_{[p,0)})| = -\tilde{k}-|i_\sigma(\tilde{x}_{[q,0)})| \in (-\infty, 0]. \end{align*} $$

We take m as big as possible with this property. Then, $x_p \not = \tilde {x}_q$ . Moreover, being $z_{m} = x_p$ and $\tilde {z}_{m} = \tilde {x}_p$ by the definition of $i_\sigma $ , we have that $z_m \not = \tilde {z}_m$ and consequently, by also using that $(z,\tilde {z})$ is centered left asymptotic, that $m \geq 0$ . We conclude that $m = 0$ , i.e. that $k+|i_\sigma (x_{[p,0)})| = \tilde {k}+|i_\sigma (\tilde {x}_{[q,0)})| = 0$ . Hence, $k =\tilde {k}=p=q=0$ . Now, it is clear that $x_{(-\infty ,p]} = \tilde {x}_{(-\infty ,q]}$ , so from the last equations, we obtain that $(x,\tilde {x}) \in A(X)$ . This completes the proof.

We will also need the following lemma to slightly strengthen Proposition 2.8.

Lemma 6.6. Let $X \subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ be an aperiodic subshift with L asymptotic tails. Then, $(X,T)$ has at most $2L^2\cdot \#{\mathcal A}^2$ centered asymptotic pairs.

Proof. Let ${\mathcal P}_r$ be the set of centered right asymptotic pairs in X and ${\mathcal T}_r = \{x_{(0,\infty )} : (x,\tilde {x}) \in \Lambda \} \subseteq {\mathcal A}^{{\mathbb N}_{\geq 1}}$ be the set of right asymptotic tails, where ${\mathbb N}_{\geq 1} = \{1,2,\ldots \}$ . We are going to prove that

(37) $$ \begin{align} \#{\mathcal P}_r \leq \#{\mathcal T}_r^2\cdot \#{\mathcal A}^2. \end{align} $$

Once this is done, we will have by symmetry the same relation for the centered left asymptotic pairs ${\mathcal P}_l$ , and thus we are going to be able to conclude that the number of centered asymptotic pairs in X is at most $(\#{\mathcal T}_r^2+\#{\mathcal T}_l^2)\cdot \#{\mathcal A}^2 \leq 2L^2\cdot \#{\mathcal A}^2$ , completing the proof.

Let $(x,\tilde {x}) \in {\mathcal P}_r$ and ${\mathcal R}_x = \{k\leq 0 : x_{(k,\infty )} \in {\mathcal T}_r\}$ . We claim that $\#{\mathcal R}_x \leq \#{\mathcal T}_r$ . Indeed, if this is not the case, then, by the pigeonhole principle, we can find $k' < k$ and $w \in {\mathcal T}_r$ such that $w = x_{(k,\infty )} = x_{(k',\infty )}$ . However, this implies that w has period $k-k'$ , and so X contains a point of period $k-k'$ , contrary to the aperiodicity hypothesis. Thus, ${\mathcal R}_x$ is finite and, since ${\mathcal R}_x$ is non-empty as it contains $x_{(0,\infty )}$ , $k_x := \min {\mathcal R}_x$ is a well-defined non-positive integer.

Let now $\phi \colon {\mathcal P}_r \to {\mathcal T}_r^2\times {\mathcal A}^2$ be the function defined by

$$ \begin{align*} \phi(x,\tilde{x}) = (x_{(k_x, \infty)}, \tilde{x}_{(k_{\tilde{x}},\infty)}, x_{k_x}, \tilde{x}_{k_{\tilde{x}}}). \end{align*} $$

If $\phi $ is injective, then (37) follows. Let us then prove that $\phi $ is injective.

We argue by contradiction and assume that there exist $(x,\tilde {x})\not =(y,\tilde {y})$ such that $\phi (x,\tilde {x}) = \phi (y,\tilde {y}) = (z,\tilde {z},a,\tilde {a})$ . Without loss of generality, we may assume that $x \not = y$ . Then, $x_{(k_x,\infty )} = z = y_{(k_y,\infty )}$ and $x_{k_x} = a = y_{k_y}$ . Being $x \not = y$ , this implies that $(x,y)$ is asymptotic. Furthermore, it implies that there exist $p < k$ and $q < \ell $ such that $(T^px, T^qy)$ is centered right asymptotic. In particular, $x_{(p,\infty )} \in {\mathcal T}_r$ and $p < k_x$ , contrary to the definition of $k_x$ . We conclude that $\phi $ is injective and thereby complete the proof of the lemma.

Lemma 6.7. Let $X \subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ be a subshift of topological rank K, J be an index set, and, for $j \in J$ , let $\tau _j\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal B}_j^+$ be a morphism. Suppose that for every $j \in J$ :

  1. (I) $Y_j = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau _j(X)$ is aperiodic;

  2. (II) for every fixed $a \in {\mathcal A}$ , $|\tau _j(a)|$ is equal to a constant $\ell _a$ independent of $j \in J$ .

Then, one of the following situations occur.

  1. (1) There exist $i,j\in J$ , $i\not =j$ , such that $(Y_i,T)$ is conjugate to $(Y_j,T)$ .

  2. (2) There exist $\phi \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal A}_1^+$ with $\#{\mathcal A}_1 < \#{\mathcal A}$ , a set $J_1 \subseteq J$ having at least $\#J / 2\#{\mathcal A}^2(144K^7)^2 - K(144K^7)^K$ elements, and morphisms $\tau ^{\prime }_j\colon {\mathcal C}_1^+\to {\mathcal B}_j$ , $j \in J_1$ , such that $\tau _j = \tau ^{\prime }_j\phi $ . In particular, the hypothesis of this lemma holds for $X_1 := \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi (X)$ and $\tau ^{\prime }_j$ , $j \in J_1$ .

Proof. Let $\mathfrak {i}\colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal A}^+$ be the morphism defined by $\mathfrak {i}(a) = a^{\ell _a}$ , $a \in {\mathcal A}$ , and $X' = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\mathfrak {i}(X)$ . We use Lemma 6.5 with X and $\tau _j$ to obtain a factor map $\pi _j\colon (X',T) \to (Y_j,T)$ such that

(38) $$ \begin{align} \pi(\mathfrak{i}(x)) = \tau_j(x)\quad \text{for every}\ x \in X. \end{align} $$

If $\pi _j$ is distal for $K(144K^7)^K+1$ different values of $j \in J$ , then by Lemma 6.3, we can find $i,j$ such that $(Y_i,T)$ is conjugate to $(Y_j,T)$ . Therefore, we can suppose that there exists $J' \subseteq J$ such that

(39) $$ \begin{align} \#J' \geq \#J-K(144K^7)^K\quad \text{and}\quad\pi_j\ \text{is not distal for every}\ j \in J'. \end{align} $$

From this and Lemma 6.4, we obtain, for every $j \in J'$ , a centered asymptotic pair $(x^{(j)},\tilde {x}^{(j)})$ in $X'$ such that $\pi _j(x^{(j)}) = \pi _j(\tilde {x}^{(j)})$ . This and (38) imply that

(40) $$ \begin{align} \tau_j(x^{(j)}) = \pi_j(x^{(j)}) = \pi_j(\tilde{x}^{(j)}) = \tau_j(\tilde{x}^{(j)}). \end{align} $$

Now, by Lemma 6.6, X has at most $2\#{\mathcal A}^2(144K^7)^2$ centered asymptotic pairs and thus, thanks to Lemma 6.5, the same bound holds for $X'$ . Therefore, by the pigeonhole principle, there exist $J_1 \subseteq J$ satisfying $\#J_1 \geq \#J'/2\#{\mathcal A}^2(144K^7)^2 \geq \#J / 2\#{\mathcal A}^2(144K^7)^2 - K(144K^7)^K$ and a centered asymptotic pair $(x,\tilde {x})$ in $X'$ such that $(x,\tilde {x}) = (x^{(j)},\tilde {x}^{(j)})$ for every $j \in J_1$ .

We assume that $(x,\tilde {x})$ is right asymptotic as the other case is similar. Then, (40) implies that if $\ell = \sum _{a\in {\mathcal A}}\ell _a$ , then, for every $j \in J_1$ ,

(41) $$ \begin{align} \text{one of the words in}\ \{\tau_j(x_{[0,\ell)}), \tau_j(\tilde{x}_{[0,\ell)})\}\ \text{is a prefix of the other.} \end{align} $$

This, hypothesis (II), and the fact that, since $(x,\tilde {x})$ is a centered asymptotic pair, $x_0 \not = \tilde {x}_0$ allows us to use Lemma 3.2 with $u := x_{[0,\ell )}$ , $v := \tilde {x}_{[0,\ell )}$ , $J := J_1$ , and $w^j := \tau _j(x_{[0,\infty )})_{[0,\ell )}$ , and obtain morphisms $\phi \colon {\mathcal A}^+\to {\mathcal A}_1^+$ and $\tau ^{\prime }_j\colon {\mathcal A}_1^+\to {\mathcal B}_j^+$ , $j \in J_1$ , such that $\#{\mathcal A}_1 < \#{\mathcal A}$ , $\tau _j = \tau ^{\prime }_j\phi $ , and

(42) $$ \begin{align} \text{for every}\ a \in {\mathcal A}_1, \ell^{\prime}_a := |\tau^{\prime}_j(c)|\ \text{does not depend on the chosen}\ j \in J. \end{align} $$

Finally, we observe that $X_1$ and $\tau ^{\prime }_j$ , $j \in J_1$ , satisfy the hypothesis of the lemma: condition (I) holds since, by the relation $\tau _j = \tau ^{\prime }_j\phi $ , the subshift $X_1 := \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi (X)$ satisfies that $\bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau ^{\prime }_j(X_1) = Y_j$ is aperiodic; condition (II) is given by (42).

6.3 Proof of main result

We now prove Theorem 1.7. We restate it for convenience.

Theorem 1.7. Let $(X,T)$ be an minimal subshift of topological rank K. Then, $(X,T)$ has at most $(3K)^{32K}$ aperiodic symbolic factors up to conjugacy.

Proof. We set $R = (3K)^{32K}$ . We prove the theorem by contradiction: assume that there exist $X \subseteq {\mathcal A}^{\mathbb Z}$ of topological rank K and, for $j \in \{0,\ldots ,R\}$ , factor maps $\pi _j\colon (X,T) \to (Y_j,T)$ such that $(Y_i,T)$ is not conjugate to $(Y_j,T)$ for every $i\not =j \in \{0,\ldots ,R\}$ . We remark that X must be infinite as, otherwise, it would not have any aperiodic factor.

To start, we build ${\mathcal S}$ -representations for the subshifts X and $Y_j$ . Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal A}_n^+)_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ be the primitive and proper directive sequence of alphabet rank K generating X given by Theorem 1.1. Let $r \in {\mathbb N}$ be such that every $\pi _j$ has a radius r and let ${\mathcal B}_j$ be the alphabet of $Y_j$ . By contracting $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ , we can assume that $\sigma _0$ is r-proper and $\#{\mathcal A}_n = K$ for all $n\geq 1$ . Then, we can use Lemma 2.4 to find morphisms $\tau _{j} \colon {\mathcal A}_1^+\to {\mathcal B}_j^+$ such that

(43) $$ \begin{align} \pi_j(\sigma_1(x)) = \tau_j(x)\quad \text{for all}\ x \in X_{\boldsymbol{\sigma}}^{(1)}\quad \text{and}\quad |\tau_{j}(a)| = |\sigma_0(a)|\quad \text{for all}\ a \in {\mathcal A}_1. \end{align} $$

Next, we inductively define subshifts $X_n \subseteq {\mathcal C}_n^{\mathbb Z}$ and morphisms $\{\tau _{n,j}\colon {\mathcal C}_n^+\to {\mathcal B}_j : j\in J_n\}$ such that:

  1. (i) $X_n$ has topological rank at most K;

  2. (ii) $Y_j = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}} \tau _{n,j}(X_n)$ ;

  3. (iii) for every $c \in {\mathcal C}_n$ , $\ell _{n,a} := |\tau _{n,j}(c)|$ does not depend on the chosen $j \in J_n$ .

First, we set $X_0 = X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(1)}$ , ${\mathcal C}_0 = {\mathcal A}_1$ , $J_0 = J$ , and, for $j\in J_0$ , $\tau _{0,j} = \tau _{j}$ , and note that by the hypothesis and (43), they satisfy conditions (i), (ii), and (iii). Let now $n \geq 0$ and suppose that $X_n \subseteq {\mathcal C}_n^{\mathbb Z}$ and $\tau _{n,j}$ , $j\in J_n$ , has been defined in a way such that conditions (i), (ii), and (iii) hold. If $\#J_n / 2\#{\mathcal A}^2(144K^7)^2 - K(144K^7)^K \leq 1$ , then the procedure stops. Otherwise, we define step $n+1$ as follows. Thanks to conditions (i), (ii), and (iii), we can use Lemma 6.7, and since there are no two conjugate $(Y_i,T)$ , this lemma gives us a morphism $\phi \colon {\mathcal C}_n^+\to {\mathcal C}_{n+1}^+$ , a set $J_{n+1} \subseteq J_n$ , and morphisms $\{\tau _{n+1,j}\colon {\mathcal C}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal B}_j^+ : j\in J_{n+1}\}$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \#{\mathcal C}_{n+1} < \#{\mathcal C}_n, \#J_{n+1} \geq \#J_n / 2\#{\mathcal C}_n^2(144K^7)^2 - K(144K^7)^K\quad \text{and}\quad\tau_{n,j} = \tau_{n+1,j}\phi_n. \end{align*} $$

Furthermore, $X_{n+1} := \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi _n(X_n)$ and $\tau _{n+1,j}$ satisfy the hypothesis of that lemma, that is, conditions (ii) and (iii) above. Since $(\phi _n\ldots \phi _0\sigma _1,\sigma _2,\sigma _3,\ldots )$ is a primitive and proper sequence of alphabet rank K generating $X_{n+1}$ , Theorem 1.3 implies that condition (i) is met as well.

Since $\#{\mathcal C}_0> \#{\mathcal C}_1 > \ldots $ , there is a last ${\mathcal C}_N$ defined. Our next objective is to prove that $N \geq K$ . Observe that $\#{\mathcal C}_n \leq K$ , so

$$ \begin{align*} \#J_{n+1} \geq \#J_n / 2K^2(144K^7)^2 - K(144K^7)^K\quad \text{for any}\ n \in \{0,\ldots,N-1\}. \end{align*} $$

Using this recurrence and the inequalities $\#J_0> (3K)^{32K}$ and $K\geq 2$ , it is routine to verify that the following bound holds for every $n \in \{0,\ldots ,K-1\}$ such that the nth step is defined:

$$ \begin{align*} \#J_n / 2\#{\mathcal C}_n^2(144K^7)^2 - K(144K^7)^K> 1. \end{align*} $$

Therefore, $N \geq K$ . We conclude that $\#{\mathcal C}_N \leq \#{\mathcal C}_0-K = 0$ , which is a contradiction.

Remark 6.8. In theorem 1 of [Reference DurandDur00], the author proved that linearly recurrent subshifts have finitely many aperiodic symbolic factors up to conjugacy. Since this kind of systems have finite topological rank (see Remark 4.10), Theorem 1.7 generalizes the theorem of [Reference DurandDur00] to the much larger class of minimal finite topological rank subshifts.

Acknowledgements

This research was partially supported by grant ANID-AFB 170001. The first author thanks Doctoral Fellowship CONICYT-PFCHA/Doctorado Nacional/2020-21202229.

A Appendix

To prove Proposition 4.4, we start with some lemmas concerning how to construct recognizable pairs $(Z,\tau )$ for a fixed subshift $Y = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau (Z)$ .

A.1 Codings of subshifts

If $Y \subseteq {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z}$ is a subshift, $U \subseteq Y$ and $y\in Y$ , we denote by ${\mathcal R}_U(y)$ the set of return times of y to U, this is, ${\mathcal R}_U(y) = \{k\in {\mathbb Z} : T^ky \in U\}$ . We recall that the set $C_\tau (k,z)$ in the lemma below corresponds to the cuts of $(k,z)$ (see Definition 2.1 for further details).

Lemma A.1. Let $Y \subseteq {\mathcal B}^{\mathbb Z}$ be an aperiodic subshift, with ${\mathcal B} \subseteq {\mathcal L}(Y)$ . Suppose that $U \subseteq Y$ is:

  1. (I) d-syndetic, for every $y \in Y$ there exists $k \in [0,d-1]$ with $T^ky\in U$ ;

  2. (II) of radius r, $U \subseteq \bigcup _{u\in {\mathcal A}^r,v\in {\mathcal A}^{r+1}}[u.v]$ ;

  3. (III) $\ell $ -proper, $U \subseteq [u.v]$ for some $u,v\in {\mathcal A}^\ell $ ;

  4. (IV) $\rho $ -separated, $U,TU,\ldots ,T^{\rho -1}U$ are disjoint.

Then, there exist a letter-onto morphism $\tau \colon {\mathcal C}^+ \to {\mathcal B}^+$ and a subshift $Z \subseteq {\mathcal C}^{\mathbb Z}$ such that:

  1. (1) $Y = \bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb Z}}T^n\tau (Z)$ and ${\mathcal C} \subseteq {\mathcal L}(Y)$ ;

  2. (2) $(Z,\tau )$ is recognizable with constant $r+d$ ;

  3. (3) $|\tau | \leq d$ , $\langle \tau \rangle \geq \rho $ and $\tau $ is $\min (\rho ,\ell )$ -proper;

  4. (4) $C_\tau (k,z) = {\mathcal R}_U(y)$ for all $y \in Y$ and $\tau $ -factorization $(k,z)$ of y in Z.

Remark A.2. If $U \subseteq Y$ satisfies condition (III), then U is $\rho := \min {\mathrm {per}}({\mathcal L}_{\ell }(Y))$ -separated. Indeed, if $U\cap T^k U\not =\emptyset $ for some $k> 0$ , then $[v]\cap T^k[v]\not =\emptyset $ , where $v \in {\mathcal A}^\ell $ is such that $U \subseteq [v]$ . Hence, v is k periodic and $k \geq \rho $ .

Proof. Let $y \in Y$ . By condition (I), the sets ${\mathcal R}_U(y)\cap [0,\infty )$ , ${\mathcal R}_U(y)\cap (-\infty ,0]$ are infinite. Thus, we can write ${\mathcal R}_U(y) = \{\cdots k_{-1}(y) < k_0(y) < k_1(y) \cdots \}$ , with $\min \{i\in {\mathbb Z}:k_i(y)> 0\}=1$ . Let ${\mathcal W} = \{y_{[k_i(y), k_{i+1}(y))} : y\in Y,\ i\in {\mathbb Z}\} \subseteq {\mathcal B}^+$ . By condition (I), ${\mathcal W}$ is finite, so we can write ${\mathcal C} := \{1,\ldots , \#{\mathcal W}\}$ and choose a bijection $\phi \colon {\mathcal C} \to {\mathcal W}$ . Then, $\phi $ extends to a morphism $\tau \colon {\mathcal C}^+ \to {\mathcal B}^+$ . As ${\mathcal B} \subseteq {\mathcal L}(Y)$ , $\phi $ is letter-onto. We define $\psi \colon Y \to {\mathcal C}^{\mathbb Z}$ by $\psi (y) = (\phi ^{-1}(y_{[k_i(y), k_{i+1}(y))}))_{i\in {\mathbb Z}}$ and set $Z = \psi (Y)$ . We are going to prove that $\tau $ and Z satisfy items (1–4).

Claim A.2.1.

  1. (i) If $y_{[-d-r,d+r]} = y^{\prime }_{[-d-r,d+r]}$ , then $\psi (y)_0 = \psi (y')_0$ .

  2. (ii) $\tau (\psi (y)) = T^{k_0(y)}y$ .

  3. (iii) $T^j\psi (y) = \psi (T^ky)$ for $j\in {\mathbb Z}$ and $k \in [k_j(y),k_{j+1}(y))$ .

Proof. Let $y,y' \in Y$ such that $y_{[-d-r,d+r]} = y^{\prime }_{[-d-r,d+r]}$ . By condition (I), we have $k_{i+1}(y)-k_i(y) \leq d$ for all $i \in {\mathbb Z}$ and, thus, $|k_0(y)|, |k_1(y)| \leq d$ . Since U has radius r and $y_{[-d-r,d+r]} = y^{\prime }_{[-d-r,d+r]}$ , we deduce that $k_0(y) = k_0(y')$ and $k_1(y) = k_0(y')$ . Hence, $\psi (y)_0 = \phi ^{-1}(y_{[k_0(y), k_1(y))}) = \phi ^{-1}(y^{\prime }_{[k_0(y'), k_1(y'))}) =\psi (y')_0$ . To prove claim (ii) we compute:

$$ \begin{align*} \tau(\psi(y)) &= \tau(\cdots \phi^{-1}(y_{[k_{-1}(y),k_0(y))}).\phi^{-1}(y_{[k_0(y),k_1(y))})\cdots) \\[3pt] &= \cdots y_{[k_{-1}(y),k_0(y))}.y_{[k_0(y),k_1(y))}\cdots = T^{k_0}y. \end{align*} $$

Finally, for claim (iii) we write, for $k \in [k_j(y),k_{j+1}(y))$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} T^j\psi(y) = \cdots \phi^{-1}(y_{[k_{j-1}(y),k_j(y))}).\phi^{-1}(y_{[k_j(y),k_{j+1}(y))})\cdots = \psi(T^ky). \end{align*} $$

Now we prove the desired properties of $\tau $ and Z.

(1) From claim (i), we see that $\psi $ is continuous and, therefore, Z is closed. By claim (iii), Z is also shift-invariant and, then, a subshift. By claim (ii), $Y = \bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb Z}}T^n\tau (Z)$ . The condition ${\mathcal C} \subseteq {\mathcal L}(Y)$ follows from the definition of ${\mathcal W}$ and $\tau $ .

(2) We claim that the only centered $\tau $ -interpretation in Z of a point $y \in Y$ is $(-k_0(y), \psi (y))$ . Indeed, this pair is a $\tau $ -interpretation in Z by claim (ii), and it is centered because $k_0(y) \leq 0 < k_1(y)$ implies $-k_0(y) \in [0, k_1(y)-k_0(y)) = [0, |\psi (y)_0|)$ . Let $(n,z)$ be another centered $\tau $ -interpretation of y in Z. By the definition of Z, there exists $y' \in Y$ with $z = \psi (y')$ . Then, by claim (ii),

(44) $$ \begin{align} T^{n+k_0(y')}y' = T^n\tau(\psi(y')) = T^n\tau(z) = y. \end{align} $$

Now, on one hand, we have $|\tau (z_0)| = |\tau (\psi (y')_0)| = k_1(y')-k_0(y')$ . On the other hand, that $(n,\psi (y'))$ is centered gives that $n \in [0,|\tau (z_0)|)$ . Therefore, $n +k_0(y')\in (k_0(y'),k_1(y')]$ . We conclude from this, claim (iii), and (44) that $\psi (y') = \psi (y)$ . Hence, $y = T^n\tau \psi (y') = T^n\tau \psi (y) = T^{n+k_0(y)}y$ , which implies that $n = -k_0(y)$ as Y is aperiodic. This proves that $(-k_0(y), \psi (y))$ is the only $\tau $ -interpretation of y in Z. From this and claim (i), we deduce property (2).

(3) Since U is d-syndetic, $|\tau (\psi (y)_i)| = |y_{[k_i(y), k_{i+1}(y))}| = k_{i+1}(y)-k_i(y) \leq d$ for $y\in Y$ and $i\in {\mathbb Z}$ , so $|\tau | \leq d$ . Similarly, we can obtain $\langle \tau \rangle \geq \rho $ using that U is $\rho $ -separated. Let $u,v \in {\mathcal B}^\ell $ satisfying $U \subseteq [u.v]$ . Since $k_i, k_{i+1} \in {\mathcal R}_U(y)$ , we have that $u = y_{[k_i(y), k_i(y)+|u|)}$ , $v = y_{[k_{i+1}(y)-|v|, k_{i+1}(y))}$ and, thus, that $\tau $ is $\min (\ell ,\langle \tau \rangle )$ -proper. In particular, it is $\min (\ell ,\rho )$ -proper.

(4) This follows directly from the definition of $\tau $ and ${\mathcal R}_U(y)$ .

Lemma A.3. For $j\in \{0,1\}$ , let $\sigma _j \colon {\mathcal A}_j^+ \to {\mathcal B}^+$ be a morphism and $X_j \subseteq {\mathcal A}_j^{\mathbb Z}$ be a subshift such that $Y := \bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb Z}}T^n\sigma _j(X_j)$ and ${\mathcal A}_j \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_j)$ for every $j \in \{0,1\}$ . Suppose that:

  1. (1) $(X_0, \sigma _0)$ is recognizable with constant $\ell $ ;

  2. (2) $\sigma _1$ is $\ell $ -proper;

  3. (3) $C_{\sigma _0}(k^0,x^0)(y) \supseteq C_{\sigma _1}(k^1,x^1)(y)$ for all $y \in Y$ and $\sigma _j$ -factorizations $(k^j,x^j)$ of y in $X_j$ , $j=0,1$ .

Then, there exist a letter-onto and proper morphism $\nu \colon {\mathcal A}_1^+\to {\mathcal A}_0^+$ such that $\sigma _1 = \sigma _0\nu $ and $X_0 = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\nu (X_1)$ .

Proof. Since $\sigma _1$ is $\ell $ -proper, we can find $u,v \in {\mathcal B}^\ell $ such that $\sigma _1(a)$ starts with u and ends with v for every $a \in {\mathcal A}_1$ . We define $\nu $ as follows. Let $a\in {\mathcal A}_1$ and $x \in X_1$ such that $a = x_0$ . Since $\sigma _1$ is $\ell $ -proper, the word $v.\sigma _1(a)u$ occurs in $\sigma _1(x) \in Y$ at position $0$ . By item (3), we can find $w \in {\mathcal L}(X_0)$ with $\sigma _1(x_0) = \sigma _0(w)$ . We set $\nu (a) = w$ . Since $(X_0,\sigma _0)$ is recognizable with constant $\ell $ and $u,v$ have length $\ell $ , w uniquely determined by $v.\sigma _1(a)u$ and, therefore, $\nu $ is well defined. Moreover, the recognizability implies that the first letter of $\nu (a)$ depends only on $v.u$ , so $\nu $ is left-proper. A symmetric argument shows that $\nu $ is right-proper and, in conclusion, that it is proper. We also note that $\nu $ is letter-onto as ${\mathcal A}_0 \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_0)$ . It follows from the definition of $\nu $ that $\sigma _1 = \sigma _0\nu $ . Now, let $x \in X_1$ and $(k,x')$ be a centered $\sigma _0$ -factorization of $\sigma _1(x)$ in $X_0$ . By item (3), $k=0$ and $\sigma _1(x_j) = \sigma _0(x^{\prime }_{[k_j,k_{j+1})})$ for some sequence $\cdots < k_{-1} < k_0 < \cdots $ Hence, by the definition of $\nu $ , $\nu (x) = x' \in X_0$ . This argument shows that $X^{\prime }_0 := \bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb Z}}T^n\nu (X_1) \subseteq X_0$ . Then, $\bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb Z}}T^n\sigma _0(X^{\prime }_0) = \bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb Z}}T^n\sigma _0\nu (X_1) = Y$ , where in the last step, we used that $\sigma _0\nu =\sigma _1$ . Since the points in Y have exactly one $\sigma _0$ -factorization, we must have $X^{\prime }_0 = X_0$ . This ends the proof.

A.2 Factors of ${\mathcal S}$ -adic sequences

Now we are ready to prove Proposition 4.4. For convenience, we repeat its statement.

Proposition A.4. Let $\boldsymbol {\sigma } = (\sigma _n\colon {\mathcal A}_n \to {\mathcal A}_{n-1})_{n\geq 0}$ be a letter-onto, everywhere growing, and proper directive sequence. Suppose that $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ is aperiodic. Then, there exists a contraction $\boldsymbol {\sigma }' = (\sigma _{n_k})_{k\in {\mathbb N}}$ and a letter-onto and proper factor $\boldsymbol {\phi }\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma }' \to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ , where $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is letter-onto, everywhere growing, proper, recognizable, and generates $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ .

Proof. We start by observing that from Lemma 4.6, we can get that

(45) $$ \begin{align} {\mathcal A}_n \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol{\sigma}}^{(n)})\quad \text{for every}\ n\in{\mathbb N}. \end{align} $$

Let $p_n = \min \{{\mathrm {per}}(\sigma _{[0,n)}(a)) : a \in {\mathcal A}_n\}$ . Since $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ is everywhere growing and $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ is aperiodic, $\lim _{n\to \infty }p_n = \infty $ . Hence, we can contract $\boldsymbol {\sigma }$ in a way such that, for every $n\geq 2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} (\mathrm{I}_n)\ p_n \geq 3|\sigma_{[0,n-1)}|,\quad (\mathrm{II}_n)\ \sigma_{[0,n)}\ \text{is}\ 3|\sigma_{[0,n-1)}|\text{-proper.} \end{align*} $$

For $n\geq 2$ , let $U_n = \bigcup _{u,v\in {\mathcal A}_n^2}[\sigma _{[0,n)}(u.v)]$ . Observe that $U_n$ is $|\sigma _{[0,n)}|$ -syndetic, has radius $2|\sigma _{[0,n)}|$ , is $3|\sigma _{[0,n-1)}|$ -proper and, by Remark A.2, is $p_n$ -separated. Thus, by $(\mathrm {I}_n)$ , U is $3|\sigma _{[0,n-1)}|$ -separated. We can then use Lemma A.1 with $(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n)},\sigma _{[0,n)})$ to obtain a letter-onto morphism $\nu _n\colon {\mathcal B}_n^+ \to {\mathcal A}_0^+$ and a subshift $Y_n \subseteq {\mathcal B}_n^{\mathbb Z}$ such that:

  1. $(P^1_n)$ $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\nu _n(Y_n)$ and ${\mathcal B}_n \subseteq {\mathcal L}(Y_n)$ ;

  2. $(P^2_n)$ $(Y_n,\nu _n)$ is recognizable with constant $3|\sigma _{[0,n)}|$ ;

  3. $(P^3_n)$ $|\nu _n| \leq |\sigma _{[0,n)}|$ , $\langle \nu _n\rangle \geq 3|\sigma _{[0,n-1)}|$ , and $\nu _n$ is $3|\sigma _{[0,n-1)}|$ -proper;

  4. $(P^4_n)$ $C_{\nu _n}(k,y) = {\mathcal R}_{U_n}(x)$ for all $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ and $\nu _n$ -factorization $(k,y)$ of x in $Y_n$ .

We write $C_{\nu _n}(x) := C_{\nu _n}(k,y)$ if $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ and $(k,y)$ is the unique $\nu _n$ -factorization of x in $Y_n$ . Observe that $U_{n+1} \subseteq U_n$ for $n \geq 2$ . Thus, $C_{\nu _{n+1}}(x) = {\mathcal R}_{U_{n+1}}(x) \subseteq {\mathcal R}_{U_n}(x) = C_{\nu _n}(x)$ for all $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ . This, $(P^2_n)$ and $(P^3_{n+1})$ allow us to use Lemma A.3 with $(Y_{n+1},\nu _{n+1})$ and $(Y_n,\nu _n)$ and find a letter-onto and proper morphism $\tau _n\colon {\mathcal B}_{n+1}^+ \to {\mathcal B}_{n}^+$ such that $\nu _n\tau _n = \nu _{n+1}$ and $Y_{n} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\tau _n(Y_{n+1})$ .

Next, we claim that $C_{\nu _n}(x) \supseteq C_{\sigma _{[0,n+1)}}(k,z)$ for all $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}$ and $\sigma _{[0,n+1)}$ -factorization $(k,z)$ of x in $X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n+1)}$ . Indeed, if $j \in {\mathbb Z}$ , then $T^{c_{\sigma _{[0,n+1)},j}(k,z)}x \in [\sigma _{[0,n+1)}(z_{j-1}.z_jz_{j+1})] \subseteq [\sigma _{[0,n)}(a.bc)] \subseteq U_n$ , where a is the last letter of $\sigma _{n}(z_{j-1})$ and $bc$ the first two letters of $\sigma _{n}(z_jz_{j+1})$ , so $c_{\sigma _{[0,n+1)},j}(k,z) \in {\mathcal R}_{U_n}(x) = C_{\nu _n}(x)$ , as desired.

Thanks to the claim, $(P^2_n)$ , $(\mathrm {I}_{n+1})$ , and (45), we can use Lemma A.3 with $(Y_{n}, \nu _{n})$ and $(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n+1)},\sigma _{[0,n+1)})$ to obtain a proper morphism $\phi _n\colon {\mathcal A}_{n+1}^+\to {\mathcal B}_{n}^+$ such that $\sigma _{[0,n+1)} = \nu _n\phi _n$ and $Y_{n} = \bigcup _{k\in {\mathbb Z}}T^k\phi _n(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n+1)})$ .

Now we can define the morphisms $\tau _1 := \nu _2$ and $\phi _1 := \nu _2\phi _2$ and the sequence:

$$ \begin{align*} \boldsymbol{\phi} = (\phi_n)_{n\geq1}, \boldsymbol{\tau} = (\tau_n)_{n\geq1}\quad \text{and}\quad\boldsymbol{\sigma}' = (\sigma_{[0,2)}, \sigma_2,\sigma_3,\ldots)_{n\geq2}. \end{align*} $$

We are going to prove that $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ , $\boldsymbol {\sigma '}$ , and $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ are the objects that satisfy the conclusion of the proposition.

These sequences are letter-onto as each $\nu _n$ and each $\phi _n$ is letter-onto. Next, we show that $\boldsymbol {\phi }$ is a factor. The relation $\phi _1 = \tau _1\phi _2$ follows from the definitions. To prove the other relations, we observe that from the commutative relations for $\tau _n$ and $\phi _n$ , we have that

(46) $$ \begin{align} \nu_{n}\phi_n\sigma_{n+1} = \sigma_{[0, n+1)}\sigma_{n+1} = \sigma_{[0, n+2)} = \nu_{n+1}\phi_{n+1} = \nu_{n}\tau_n\phi_{n+1}. \end{align} $$

In particular, $\nu _{n}\phi _n\sigma _{n+1}(x) = \nu _{n}\tau _n\phi _{n+1}(x)$ for any $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n+2)}$ . Since $\phi _n\sigma _{n+1}(x)$ and $\tau _n\phi _{n+1}(x)$ are both elements of $Y_{n}$ and $(Y_{n},\nu _{n})$ is recognizable, we deduce that $\phi _n\sigma _{n+1}(x) = \tau _n\phi _{n+1}(x)$ for any $x \in X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n+2)}$ . Thus, one of the words in $\{\phi _n\sigma _{n+1}(x_0)$ , $\tau _n\phi _{n+1}(x_0)\}$ is a prefix of the other. Since ${\mathcal A}_{n+2} \subseteq {\mathcal L}(X_{\boldsymbol {\sigma }}^{(n+2)})$ , we deduce that, for any $a \in {\mathcal A}_{n+2}$ , one of the words in $\{\tau _n\phi _{n+1}(a)$ , $\nu _{n}\phi _n\sigma _{n+1}(a)\}$ is a prefix of the other. However, by (46), the words $\nu _{n}\tau _n\phi _{n+1}(a)$ and $\nu _{n}\phi _n\sigma _{n+1}(a)$ have the same length, so $\phi _n\sigma _{n+1}(a)$ must be equal to $\tau _n\phi _{n+1}(a)$ for every $n\geq 2$ . This proves that $\phi _n\sigma _{n+1} = \tau _n\phi _{n+1}$ for every $n\geq 2$ and that $\boldsymbol {\phi }\colon \boldsymbol {\sigma '}\to \boldsymbol {\tau }$ is a factor.

The following commutative diagram, valid for all $n\geq 2$ , summarizes the construction so far:

As shown in the diagram, we have that $\nu _{n}\tau _n = \nu _{n+1}$ for $n\geq 2$ . Thus, $\tau _1\tau _2\ldots \tau _n = \nu _{n+1}$ , and hence $\langle \tau _1\tau _2\ldots \tau _n \rangle \geq \langle \nu _{n+1} \rangle \geq p_n \to _{n\to \infty } \infty $ . Therefore, $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is everywhere growing. Also, by using Lemma 2.3 with $(Y_{n},\nu _{n}) = (Y_{n},\tau _1\tau _2\ldots \tau _{n-1})$ , we deduce that $(Y_{n},\tau _{n-1})$ is recognizable for every $n\geq 2$ , which implies that $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is recognizable. Finally, as each $\tau _n$ is proper, $\boldsymbol {\tau }$ is proper.

References

Amini, M., Elliott, G. A. and Golestani, N.. The category of Bratteli diagrams. Canad. J. Math. 67(5) (2015), 9901023.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Auslander, J.. Minimal Flows and Their Extensions. Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1988.Google Scholar
Bezuglyi, S., Kwiatkowski, J., Medynets, K. and Solomyak, B.. Finite rank Bratteli diagrams: structure of invariant measures. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 365(5) (2013), 26372679.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berthé, V., Steiner, W., Thuswaldner, J. M. and Yassawi, R.. Recognizability for sequences of morphisms. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. 39(11) (2019), 28962931.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donoso, S., Durand, F., Maass, A. and Petite, S.. Interplay between finite topological rank minimal Cantor systems, $\mathbf{\mathcal{S}}$ -adic subshifts and their complexity. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 374(5) (2021), 34533489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durand, F., Frank, A. and Maass, A.. Eigenvalues of minimal Cantor systems. J. Eur. Math. Soc. (JEMS) 21(3) (2019), 727775.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durand, F., Host, B. and Skau, C.. Substitutional dynamical systems, Bratteli diagrams and dimension groups. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. 19(4) (1999), 953993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downarowicz, T. and Maass, A.. Finite-rank Bratteli–Vershik diagrams are expansive. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. 28(3) (2008), 739747.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downarowicz, T.. The royal couple conceals their mutual relationship: a noncoalescent Toeplitz flow. Israel J. Math. 97 (1997), 239251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durand, F.. Linearly recurrent subshifts have a finite number of non-periodic subshift factors. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. 20(4) (2000), 10611078.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Espinoza, B. and Maass, A.. On the automorphism group of minimal $\mathbf{\mathcal{S}}$ -adic subshifts of finite alphabet rank. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. doi:10.1017/etds.2021.64. Published online 30 June 2021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Espinoza, B.. On symbolic factors of $\mathbf{\mathcal{S}}$ -adic subshifts of finite alphabet rank. Preprint, 2022, arXiv:2008.13689v2 [math.DS].Google Scholar
Golestani, N. and Hosseini, M.. On topological rank of factors of Cantor minimal systems. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. doi:10.1017/etds.2021.62. Published online 8 June 2021.Google Scholar
Giordano, T., Handelman, D. and Hosseini, M.. Orbit equivalence of Cantor minimal systems and their continuous spectra. Math. Z. 289(3–4) (2018), 11991218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gjerde, R. and Johansen, Ø.. Bratteli–Vershik models for Cantor minimal systems: applications to Toeplitz flows. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. 20(6) (2000), 16871710.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gjerde, R. and Johansen, Ø.. Bratteli–Vershik models for Cantor minimal systems associated to interval exchange transformations. Math. Scand. 90(1) (2002), 87100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herman, R. H., Putnam, I. F. and Skau, C. F.. Ordered Bratteli diagrams, dimension groups and topological dynamics. Internat. J. Math. 3(6) (1992), 827864.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rozenberg, G. and Salomaa, A.. Handbook of Formal Languages: Volume 1. Word, Language, Grammar. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1997.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 Illustration of a local period.