Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T21:42:07.797Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Finitely presented left orderable monsters

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 July 2023

FRANCESCO FOURNIER-FACIO*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, ETH Zürich, Zürich, Switzerland
YASH LODHA
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, University of Hawai‘i at Mānoa, Honolulu, USA (e-mail: [email protected])
MATTHEW C. B. ZAREMSKY
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University at Albany (SUNY), Albany, USA (e-mail: [email protected])
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

A left orderable monster is a finitely generated left orderable group all of whose fixed point-free actions on the line are proximal: the action is semiconjugate to a minimal action so that for every bounded interval I and open interval J, there is a group element that sends I into J. In his 2018 ICM address, Navas asked about the existence of left orderable monsters. By now there are several examples, all of which are finitely generated but not finitely presentable. We provide the first examples of left orderable monsters that are finitely presentable, and even of type $F_\infty $. These groups satisfy several additional properties separating them from the previous examples: they are not simple, they act minimally on the circle, and they have an infinite-dimensional space of homogeneous quasimorphisms. Our construction is flexible enough that it produces infinitely many isomorphism classes of finitely presented (and type $F_{\infty }$) left orderable monsters.

Type
Original Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

1 Introduction

A group G is left orderable if it admits a total order which is invariant under left multiplication by any group element. This concept has a remarkable connection with dynamics of group actions on the line: a countable group G is left orderable if and only if it admits a faithful action by orientation-preserving homeomorphisms on the real line.

One of the fundamental questions in the field is to understand the following. Given a left orderable group, what are the possible actions on the line by orientation-preserving homeomorphisms? It is folklore that up to semiconjugacy, every action of a finitely generated left orderable group on the line by orientation-preserving homeomorphisms and without global fixed points is of one of three types [Reference Deroin, Navas and Rivas13, Theorem 3.5.19]:

  1. (1) cyclic or type 1 if there exists an invariant Radon measure on $\mathbb {R}$ , in which case the group surjects onto the integers;

  2. (2) locally proximal or type 2 if it does not preserve a Radon measure on $\mathbb {R}$ , yet it is semiconjugate to a minimal action that commutes with integer translations. Equivalently, such an action descends to a minimal and proximal action on the circle (see Proposition 2.5);

  3. (3) proximal or type 3 if for every bounded interval I and open interval J, there is a group element f such that $I\cdot f\subset J$ .

The above framework has shed light on various algebraic and dynamical properties of left orderable groups, and on the question of when certain groups are left orderable. For example, it was unknown until very recently whether lattices in higher-rank semisimple Lie groups admit actions on the line or not; it turns out that outside some exceptional cases, they do not [Reference Deroin and Hurtado12]. Before this breakthrough solution, given that lattices do not admit actions of type 1 [Reference Kazhdan24] or 2 [Reference Burger and Monod4, Reference Burger and Monod5, Reference Ghys17], it was thought that a promising approach could be to leverage finite generation to also rule out type-3 actions. More succinctly, [Reference Navas32, Question 4] (see also [Reference Deroin, Navas and Rivas13, Question 3.5.11]) asks the following question.

Question 1.1. (Navas ICM $2018$ )

Do there exist finitely generated left orderable groups all of whose fixed point-free actions by homeomorphisms on the line are of type 3?

Definition 1.2. (Navas)

A finitely generated left orderable group G is a left orderable monster if all of its fixed point-free actions by homeomorphisms on the line are of type 3.

Given the negative solution in [Reference Deroin and Hurtado12] to the question concerning higher-rank lattices, it is intriguing that in fact left orderable monsters do exist. This fact was proved independently by Matte Bon and Triestino [Reference Matte Bon and Triestino30], and by Hyde, the second author, Navas, and Rivas [Reference Hyde and Lodha22, Reference Hyde, Lodha, Navas and Rivas23]. In both cases, the examples are families of groups whose construction is non-trivial, and that have a number of stronger properties. First, both families of groups are simple: a property much stronger than the absence of type-1 actions. Second, these groups are uniformly perfect, and even have vanishing second bounded cohomology [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14]; in fact, they admit no fixed point-free action on the circle whatsoever [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14, Reference Matte Bon and Triestino30]—these properties are much stronger than the absence of type-2 actions.

However, the groups in [Reference Hyde and Lodha22, Reference Hyde, Lodha, Navas and Rivas23, Reference Matte Bon and Triestino30] are not finitely presentable since each is a non-trivial limit of markings of a finitely presented group in the space of marked groups. Therefore, one might hope that the above still yields an alternative approach to disprove left orderability of lattices, namely leveraging finite presentability to rule out type-3 actions. In particular, one may hope that this approach works for lattices in products of trees [Reference Burger and Mozes6], whose left orderability is still an open question. Indeed, it follows from their simplicity and from [Reference Burger and Monod5, Corollary 26] that if they are left orderable, then they must be left orderable monsters. One of the key motivations of this article is to show that this modified approach cannot work, that is, there do in fact exist finitely presentable left orderable monsters.

Our examples are very different in nature from those in [Reference Hyde and Lodha22, Reference Matte Bon and Triestino30]. First, as we already mentioned, they are finitely presentable, and even of type $F_\infty $ (finite presentability is equivalent to admitting a classifying space with a finite $2$ -skeleton, and type $F_\infty $ means there is a classifying space with a finite n-skeleton for all n). Second, the absence of type-1 or type-2 actions is shown via a direct dynamical argument, and not via some much stronger property such as simplicity, uniform perfection, or vanishing of second bounded cohomology. Indeed, each of these properties is shown to fail. Lastly, in our construction, the group itself is much more straightforward than in previous examples.

We now describe a concrete instance of our general construction. Let $\overline {T}$ denote the lift of Thompson’s group T to the real line. Let z denote the generator of the center of $\overline {T}$ . Let $\overline {T}_{2,3}$ denote the lift of the Stein–Thompson group $T_{2,3}$ , and let $g\in \overline {T}_{2,3}$ denote a lift of an element with an irrational rotation number in $T_{2,3}$ . Such elements exist, e.g., it was proved in [Reference Liousse25] that $T_{2,3}$ contains elements whose rotation number equals ${\log 2}/{\log 3}$ . We now take the amalgamated product and define

$$ \begin{align*} M := \overline{T} *_{z = g} \overline{T}_{2,3}.\end{align*} $$

Now we can state our main result.

Theorem 1.3. The group M is a left orderable monster.

A number of notable properties can be quickly established for this group. First, the space of homogeneous quasimorphisms of M is infinite-dimensional. In particular, M is not uniformly perfect, and the second bounded cohomology of M is infinite-dimensional. Moreover, M surjects onto Thompson’s group T. In particular, there exists a minimal action of M on the circle, and M is not simple. This showcases the difference with previous examples, which not only do not share these properties, but also were all more complicated to construct and harder to analyze.

To state our more general construction, we define $\mathcal {G}$ to be the class of infinite groups G of orientation-preserving homeomorphisms of the circle that satisfy:

  1. (1) the lift $\overline {G}$ of G to the real line is perfect;

  2. (2) G is simple;

  3. (3) G has a unique proximal action on the circle, up to conjugacy;

  4. (4) G has torsion.

Groups in $\mathcal {G}$ include: Thompson’s group T [Reference Cannon, Floyd and Parry10], the Stein–Thompson groups $T_{2, 3, n_3, \ldots, n_k}$ [Reference Guelman, Liousse and Arnoux21, Reference Stein33] (for example $T_{2, 3}$ ), the commutator subgroup of the golden ratio Thompson group $T_{\tau }$ [Reference Burillo, Nucinkis and Reeves8], and the piecewise projective group S constructed by the second author [Reference Lodha26]. Some of these groups are known to have irrational rotation numbers, e.g., $T_\tau^{\prime}$ [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14], and $T_{n_1,\dots ,n_k}$ if some $n_i$ and $n_j$ are coprime [Reference Liousse25]. A peculiarity of T is that the rotation numbers of all of its elements are rational [Reference Ghys and Sergiescu19]. We do not know whether S contains an element with irrational rotation number.

The following is our main result (with Theorem 1.3 as a special case).

Theorem 1.4. Let $G_1,G_2\in \mathcal {G}$ be groups such that $G_2$ contains an element with an irrational rotation number. Let $\overline {G}_i$ denote the lift of the standard action of $G_i$ , let z denote the generator of the center of $\overline {G}_1$ , and let $g \in \overline {G}_2$ denote the lift of an element with irrational rotation number. Then the following hold.

  1. (1) The group $M := \overline {G}_1*_{z = g}\overline {G}_2$ is a left orderable monster.

  2. (2) If $G_1,G_2$ are finitely presented (respectively of type $F_{\infty }$ ), then M is also finitely presented (respectively of type $F_{\infty }$ .)

  3. (3) The space of homogeneous quasimorphisms of M is infinite-dimensional. In particular, M is not uniformly perfect, and the second bounded cohomology of M is infinite-dimensional.

  4. (4) M admits a unique proximal action on the circle (up to conjugacy), and this coincides with the unique proximal action of the quotient $G_1$ . In particular, $G_1$ is an isomorphism invariant of M.

Using the above, we will conclude the following.

Corollary 1.5. There exist infinitely many isomorphism classes of finitely presentable (and type $F_{\infty }$ ) left orderable monsters.

2 Actions on the line and on the circle

We denote by ${\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {R})$ and ${\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ the groups of orientation-preserving homeomorphisms of the real line and the circle, respectively. Given $f\in {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {R})$ , the support of f, denoted $\mathrm{supp}(f)$ , is the set of points that are moved by f. Note that the support of a homeomorphism is always an open set. Given $G \leq {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {R})$ or ${\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ , we denote by $\mathrm{Fix}(G)$ the set of global fixed points of G, which is closed. We say that an action $\rho $ of a group G is fixed point-free if $\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (G)) = \varnothing $ .

Recall that a group action on a topological space by homeomorphisms is minimal if each orbit is dense. We say that $\Lambda \subset \mathbb {R}$ (or $\Lambda \subset \mathbb {S}^1$ ) is exceptional if $\Lambda $ is perfect and totally disconnected. Let $G\leq {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {M})$ , where $\mathbb {M}\in \{\mathbb {R},\mathbb {S}^1\}$ , and let $\Lambda \subset \mathbb {M}$ be an exceptional set. We say that $\Lambda $ is minimal if it is G-invariant and the action of G on $\Lambda $ is minimal.

The following are some fundamental results concerning actions of groups on the circle and the real line.

Theorem 2.1. [Reference Navas31, Theorem 2.1.1]

If $\Gamma \leq {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ is a countable group, then precisely one of the following holds.

  1. (1) The action admits a finite orbit.

  2. (2) The action is minimal.

  3. (3) There exists a unique, minimal, exceptional subset $\Lambda \subset \mathbb {S}^1$ which is homeomorphic to the Cantor set.

For the case of the line, a similar result holds under the additional assumption of finite generation.

Proposition 2.2. [Reference Navas31, Proposition 2.1.12]

Every fixed point-free action of a finitely generated group G on $\mathbb {R}$ by orientation-preserving homeomorphisms admits a non-empty minimal invariant closed set. This closed set is one of the following.

  1. (1) Discrete, in which case the group surjects onto the integers.

  2. (2) The whole real line, in which case the group action is minimal.

  3. (3) A unique minimal, exceptional set $\Lambda \subset \mathbb {R}$ .

We are particularly interested in the third case of the previous proposition. The following is a fact concerning this case.

Proposition 2.3. [Reference Navas31, §§2.1.1 and 2.1.2]

Let $\mathbb {M}\in \{\mathbb {R},\mathbb {S}^1\}$ . Let $G\leq {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {M})$ be such that G admits a unique, exceptional, minimal set $\Lambda \subset \mathbb {M}$ . Then there is a continuous surjective map $\phi :\mathbb {M}\to \mathbb {M}$ , a group $H\leq {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {M})$ , and a surjective homomorphism $\psi :G\to H$ , such that:

  1. (1) the restriction of $\phi $ to $\Lambda $ is surjective, and every fiber has size at most $2$ ;

  2. (2) for each $g\in G$ , $\phi \circ g=\psi (g)\circ \phi $ ;

  3. (3) the action of H on $\mathbb {M}$ is minimal.

Using the above, we define the following process, which we call the minimalization of an action. We start with the action of a finitely generated group G on $\mathbb {R}$ (or $\mathbb {S}^1$ ) by orientation-preserving homeomorphisms. We assume that this action is not minimal; in the case of $\mathbb {R}$ , we assume that there is no discrete orbit, and in the case of $\mathbb {S}^1$ , we assume that there is no finite orbit. Using the above, we obtain the (possibly non-faithful) action of G on $\mathbb {R}$ (or $\mathbb {S}^1$ ) which is minimal. This new action is called the minimalization of the original action, and is semiconjugate to the original. If the original action was minimal to begin with, then this is the same as the original action.

For actions on the circle, a further property will be relevant for us. An action of a group G on $\mathbb {S}^1$ is said to be proximal if for every non-empty open arc $J \subset \mathbb {S}^1$ and every proper arc $I \subset \mathbb {S}^1$ , there exists $f \in G$ such that $I \cdot f \subset J$ . We warn the reader that in the literature, this property is referred to by various other names, such as strongly proximal, extremely proximal, strongly expansive, or compact-open transitive (some of these properties have well-established and distinct meanings in topological dynamics that happen to coincide for the case of actions on the circle). In this article, we refer to it as proximal.

Theorem 2.4. (Margulis [Reference Margulis29], see also [Reference Ghys18, §5.2])

Let G act faithfully and minimally on the circle. Suppose that G is non-abelian. Then:

  1. (1) if the action is proximal, the centralizer of G in ${\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ is trivial;

  2. (2) otherwise, the centralizer of G in ${\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ is a finite cyclic group $\langle \theta \rangle $ , and the induced action of G on $\mathbb {S}^1 / \langle \theta \rangle \cong \mathbb {S}^1$ is proximal.

Now we can push our minimalization process one step further. Given a minimal action of G on the circle such that the image of G in ${\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ is non-abelian, we obtain a proximal action of G on the circle, which we call the proximalization of the original action. If the original action was proximal to begin with, then this is the same as the original action.

Proximal actions on the circle are especially relevant for type- $2$ actions on the line.

Proposition 2.5. [Reference Malyutin28, Theorem 1]

Let G be a group, and let $\rho $ be a minimal type- $2$ action on $\mathbb {R}$ by orientation-preserving homeomorphisms. Then there exists a fixed point-free homeomorphism $t \in {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {R})$ which commutes with $\rho (G)$ , such that the induced action of G on $\mathbb {R}/\langle t \rangle \cong \mathbb {S}^1$ is proximal.

Finally, we prove a basic fact about rotation numbers of homeomorphisms of the circle, which will be the crucial tool for our proof of Theorem 1.4. Let $g \in {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ , and let $\overline {g}$ be a lift of g to the real line. Then the quantity

$$ \begin{align*}{\operatorname{rot}}(\overline{g}) := \lim\limits_{n \to \infty} \frac{\overline{g}^n(x)}{n} \in \mathbb{R}\end{align*} $$

is independent of the choice of $x \in \mathbb {R}$ , and moreover depends on the choice of lift only up to integers. In particular, the rotation number ${\operatorname {rot}}(g) \in \mathbb {R}/\mathbb {Z}$ is well defined.

Proposition 2.6. Let $\rho : G \to {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ be a group action on the circle. Let $\rho _m$ be the minimalization of $\rho $ , and suppose that $\rho _m(G)$ is non-abelian, so that there exists a proximalization $\rho _p$ . Then there exists an integer $n \geq 1$ such that for all $g \in G$ , we have ${\operatorname {rot}}(\rho _p(g)) = n {\operatorname {rot}}(\rho (g))$ . In particular, the rationality or irrationality of ${\operatorname {rot}}(\rho (g))$ is preserved under proximalization.

Proof. The rotation number of a circle homeomorphism is a semiconjugacy invariant [Reference Ghys18, §5.1]. In particular, if $\rho _m$ is the minimalization of $\rho $ , then for all $g \in G$ , it holds that ${\operatorname {rot}}(\rho _m(g)) = {\operatorname {rot}}(\rho (g))$ .

Now by Proposition 2.4, since $\rho _m(G)$ is non-abelian, there exists a (possibly trivial) finite-order homeomorphism $\theta $ that centralizes $\rho _m(G)$ and such that the proximalization $\rho _p$ is the induced action on the quotient $\mathbb {S}^1 / \langle \theta \rangle $ . Let $n \geq 1$ be the order of $\theta $ . By [Reference Ghys18, Proposition 4.1], up to conjugacy and changing the generator of $\langle \theta \rangle $ , we may assume that $\theta $ is rotation by $1/n$ . It then follows from the definition of rotation numbers that ${\operatorname {rot}}(\rho_p(g)) = n {\operatorname {rot}}(\rho_m(g))$ , and we conclude.

3 Groups in $\mathcal {G}$ and their lifts

In this section, we state and prove various results about the groups $G\in \mathcal {G}$ that play a crucial role in our general construction. Given a group $G \in \mathcal {G}$ , recall that $\overline {G}$ denotes the lift of G to the real line, that is, the group of all homeomorphisms of $\mathbb {R}$ that commute with integer translations and induce elements of G on the quotient $\mathbb {R}/\mathbb {Z}=\mathbb {S}^1$ . We have a central extension

$$ \begin{align*}1 \to \mathbb{Z} \to \overline{G} \to G \to 1.\end{align*} $$

Lemma 3.1. Let $G\in \mathcal {G}$ and let $f\in \overline {G}$ be an element that does not lie in the center. Then f normally generates $\overline {G}$ .

Proof. Let $N=\langle \!\langle f\rangle \!\rangle $ and let $Z=Z(\overline {G})\cong \mathbb {Z}$ . The image of N under the quotient $\overline {G}\to G$ is a normal subgroup of G, and is non-trivial since N is not contained in Z. Since G is simple, this image must equal G. This implies $\overline {G}=NZ$ , so $\overline {G}/N\cong Z/(N\cap Z)$ is abelian. Now the fact that $\overline {G}$ is perfect implies $N=\overline {G}$ .

Lemma 3.2. For $G\in \mathcal {G}$ , every proper normal subgroup of $\overline {G}$ is central. Hence, $\overline {G}$ has no proper non-trivial torsion-free quotients, and no non-trivial finite quotients.

Proof. That every proper normal subgroup is central follows from Lemma 3.1. The center itself corresponds to the quotient G, which has torsion. For any other non-trivial proper normal subgroup, the generator of the center will map to a non-trivial torsion element in the quotient. All non-trivial quotients surject onto G, and thus are infinite.

Next, we want to study the possible dynamics of $\overline {G}$ ( $G\in \mathcal {G}$ ) on the line (see [Reference Matte Bon and Triestino30, Theorem 8.7] for the case of Thompson’s group T).

Lemma 3.3. For $G\in \mathcal {G}$ , every fixed point-free action of $\overline {G}$ by homeomorphisms on the line is semiconjugate to the standard action.

Proof. Let $\rho $ be a fixed point-free action of $\overline {G}$ by orientation-preserving homeomorphisms on the line. Note that $\rho $ cannot fix a Radon measure because $\overline {G}$ is perfect, and hence non-indicable. Therefore, via a semiconjugacy, we pass to a minimal action (Proposition 2.3), which we denote as $\rho^{\prime} $ . We also know from Lemma 3.2 that $\rho^{\prime} $ must be a faithful action of $\overline {G}$ . Since $\overline {G}$ has a cofinal central element, it cannot admit a minimal faithful type- $3$ action [Reference Deroin, Navas and Rivas13, Proposition 3.5.12]. Therefore, $\rho^{\prime}$ is a type- $2$ action. By Proposition 2.5, there exists a fixed point-free homeomorphism t that commutes with $\rho^{\prime}(\overline{G})$ and such that the induced action of $\overline{G}$ on $\mathbb {R}/ \langle t \rangle \cong \mathbb {S}^1$ is proximal.

Now, using our rigidity assumption on proximal actions of groups in $\mathcal {G}$ —together with the fact that the center must act trivially, by Theorem 2.4—this action is even topologically conjugate to the standard action of G. Lifting this conjugacy, we obtain that $\rho^{\prime}$ is conjugate to an action $\rho^{\prime\prime}$ of $\overline {G}$ on the line that sends the center to itself and induces the standard representation on the quotient G. In other words, we can write $\rho^{\prime\prime} (g) = \rho _{st}(g) z^{i_g}$ , where z is the generator of the center and $i_g \in \mathbb {Z}$ . Since z is central, the map $g \mapsto i_g$ is a homomorphism, which must be trivial because $\overline {G}$ is perfect. Therefore, $\rho^{\prime\prime} = \rho _{st}$ and we conclude.

Finally, we consider actions of $\overline {G}$ on the circle.

Proposition 3.4. Let $G \in \mathcal {G}$ . Let $\rho $ be an action of $\overline {G}$ on the circle without global fixed points, and let $\rho _{st}$ be the standard action, that is, the one induced by the unique (up to conjugacy) proximal action of the quotient G. Then, for all $g \in \overline {G}$ , it holds that

$$ \begin{align*} {\operatorname{rot}}(\rho(g)) \in \mathbb{Q} / \mathbb{Z}\! \iff {\operatorname{rot}}(\rho_{st}(g)) \in \mathbb{Q} / \mathbb{Z}.\end{align*} $$

Proof. Let $\rho _m$ be the minimalization of $\rho $ . Since every non-trivial quotient of $\overline {G}$ surjects onto G, $\rho _m(\overline {G})$ is not abelian, so we can produce a proximalization $\rho _p$ . By Theorem 2.4, the centralizer of $\rho _p(\overline {G})$ is trivial, therefore, the whole center of $\overline {G}$ lies in the kernel of $\rho _p$ . It follows that $\rho _p$ induces a proximal action of G, and so by the definition of $\mathcal {G}$ , we deduce that $\rho _p$ is conjugate to $\rho _{st}$ . We conclude by Proposition 2.6 and the fact that rotation numbers are conjugacy-invariant [Reference Ghys18, §5.1].

3.1 Examples

Here we provide some examples of groups in $\mathcal {G}$ . We start with the most well-known example.

Example 3.5. (Thompson)

Our first example is Thompson’s group T, which is the group of orientation-preserving piecewise linear homeomorphisms of the circle $\mathbb {R}/\mathbb {Z}$ stabilizing $\mathbb {Z}[\tfrac 12]$ , with slopes in $2^{\mathbb {Z}}$ and breakpoints in $\mathbb {Z}[\tfrac 12]$ . It is well known that T lies in $\mathcal {G}$ and that it is of type $F_\infty $ ; all necessary facts can be found in [Reference Brown3, Reference Cannon, Floyd and Parry10, Reference Ghys and Sergiescu19]. For the uniqueness of the action on the circle, this is only stated explicitly in [Reference Ghys and Sergiescu19] in a weaker form (uniqueness among $C^2$ actions), however, it can be deduced from their cohomological computations or from the rest of the discussion in this section.

For the remainder of the examples, simplicity and torsion can be found in the literature, and perfection of the lift is easy to check and can sometimes be reduced to the case of T. The uniqueness of the proximal action is less well studied, but can be established via the following general criterion.

Theorem 3.6. [Reference Fournier-Facio, Löh and Moraschini15, Proposition 6.9], [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14, Corollary 4.2]

Let $G \le {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ be either piecewise linear or piecewise projective. Suppose that there exists a dense orbit $Y \subset \mathbb {S}^1$ such that the action of G on positively oriented triples in Y is transitive. Then the given action of G on $\mathbb {S}^1$ is proximal, and it is the unique proximal action of G on the circle, up to conjugacy.

This next example provides an infinite family of groups in $\mathcal {G}$ , which will be used in the proof of Corollary 1.5.

Example 3.7. (Stein–Thompson)

For $n_1,\dots ,n_k\in \mathbb {N}$ ( $n_i\ge 2$ ), let $\unicode{x3bb} := n_1\ldots n_k$ , let $Y := \mathbb {Z}[{1}/{\unicode{x3bb} }]/\mathbb {Z}$ , and let $P := \langle n_1, \ldots , n_k \rangle \leq \mathbb {R}^{\times }$ . The Stein–Thompson group $T_{n_1,\dots ,n_k}$ is the group of orientation-preserving piecewise linear homeomorphisms of the circle $\mathbb {R}/\mathbb {Z}$ , stabilizing Y, with slopes in P and breakpoints in Y; see [Reference Stein33]. When $k=1$ and $n_1=2$ , we recover the classical Thompson’s group T.

We claim that any Stein–Thompson group of the form $G := T_{2,3,n_3,\dots ,n_k}$ is in $\mathcal {G}$ , for example $T_{2,3}$ . All Stein–Thompson groups clearly have torsion, and these particular Stein–Thompson groups are all simple [Reference Guelman, Liousse and Arnoux21]. Since $\overline {T} \leq \overline {G}$ , we deduce that the group of translations is contained in the commutator subgroup of $\overline {G}$ . Together with simplicity of G, this shows that $\overline {G}$ is perfect.

Finally, we claim that Theorem 3.6 applies, with Y as above; in fact, we claim that the action is transitive on positively ordered p-tuples for all $p \geq 1$ . Let $x_1, \ldots , x_p$ and $y_1, \ldots , y_p$ be two positively ordered p-tuples in Y. Then there exists some $q \geq 1$ such that the representatives of all $x_i$ and $y_i$ in $[0, 1)$ are integer multiples of $\unicode{x3bb} ^{-q}$ . Setting $\mathbf {x} = \mathbf {y} = \{ 0, \ldots , 1 - \unicode{x3bb} ^{-q} \}\; \mod \mathbb {Z}$ includes both p-tuples inside larger tuples $\mathbf {x}, \mathbf {y}$ with the additional property that the difference between two consecutive points lies in P. Now, adding the midpoint of two consecutive points to $\mathbf {x}$ or $\mathbf {y}$ keeps the elements of the tuple inside Y, and does not change the property that the difference between two consecutive points in $\mathbf {x}$ or $\mathbf {y}$ lies in P. Therefore, we can add midpoints inductively to $\mathbf {x}$ or $\mathbf {y}$ to ensure that for each $i = 1, \ldots , p$ , the number of points in the arc $\mathbf {x} \cap (x_{i-1}, x_i)$ is the same as the number of points in the arc $\mathbf {y} \cap (y_{i-1}, y_i)$ (where we abuse the notation and interpret $x_0, y_0$ as $x_p, y_p$ ). This ensures that the piecewise linear homeomorphism of $\mathbb {S}^1$ sending $\mathbf {x}$ to $\mathbf {y}$ and interpolating linearly also sends $x_i$ to $y_i$ for each i. Since $\mathbf {x}$ and $\mathbf {y}$ are contained in Y, and the difference between two consecutive points is in the multiplicative group P, the corresponding homeomorphism of the circle is an element of G that sends $x_i$ to $y_i$ for each i, as desired.

This shows that $T_{2,3,n_3,\dots ,n_k}$ is in $\mathcal {G}$ . Also note that all Stein–Thompson groups are of type $F_\infty $ [Reference Stein33], and that any $T_{2,3,n_3,\dots ,n_k}$ has elements with irrational rotation number [Reference Liousse25].

We end with two more exotic examples.

Example 3.8. (Golden ratio Thompson)

Let $\tau := {(\sqrt {5} - 1)}/{2}$ be the small golden ratio. The golden ratio Thompson’s group $T_{\tau }$ is a circle version of Cleary’s golden ratio Thompson’s group $F_{\tau }$ [Reference Burillo, Nucinkis and Reeves7, Reference Cleary11], introduced in [Reference Burillo, Nucinkis and Reeves8]. The commutator subgroup $T_\tau^{\prime}$ has index $2$ and is simple [Reference Burillo, Nucinkis and Reeves8, Theorem 3.2]. Moreover, the action of $T_\tau^{\prime}$ on $\mathbb {Z}[\tau ]$ is transitive on positively oriented n-tuples for all n [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14, Lemmas 5.5 and 5.7], so Theorem 3.6 applies to $T_\tau^{\prime}$ . Moreover, $T_\tau^{\prime}$ is of type $F_\infty $ [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14, Proposition 5.8], and the lift $\overline {T_\tau^{\prime}}$ is perfect [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14, Lemma 5.13]. Thus, $T_\tau^{\prime}\in \mathcal {G}$ . Finally, $T_\tau^{\prime}$ clearly has elements with irrational rotation number, for instance, the rotation by $2 \tau $ (see [Reference Fournier-Facio and Lodha14] for more detail).

Example 3.9. (Piecewise projective)

The group S introduced in [Reference Lodha26] is simple, has torsion, and is of type $F_\infty $ [Reference Lodha and Zaremsky27]. It is a group of piecewise projective homeomorphisms of the circle $\mathbb {R}\cup \{\infty \}$ , which is the real projective line. The action of S preserves $\mathbb {Q}\cup \{\infty \}$ , and it acts transitively on positively oriented triples of this set. (Indeed, the copy of T in S already acts transitively on such triples). Thus, Theorem 3.6 applies to S. Moreover, $\overline {S}$ is perfect with a similar argument as above: its derived subgroup contains $\overline {T}$ , and therefore all of the integer translations. Thus, $S\in \mathcal {G}$ . We do not know whether S has elements with irrational rotation number.

4 Monstrousness and the proof of Theorem 1.4

Now we can prove our main result.

Proof of Theorem 1.4

We recall our hypothesis: $G_1,G_2\in \mathcal {G}$ are groups such that $G_2$ contains an element with an irrational rotation number. For example, for the special case in Theorem 1.3, one can use $G_1=T$ (Example 3.5) and $G_2=T_{2,3}$ (Example 3.7). We denote as usual by $\overline {G}_i$ the lift of the standard action of $G_i$ , we let z denote the generator of the center of $\overline {G}_1$ , and let $g\in \overline {G}_2$ denote a lift of an element of $G_2$ with irrational rotation number.

(1) The left orderability of M follows from the fact that an amalgamated product of two left orderable groups along a cyclic subgroup is left orderable [Reference Bludov and Glass1] (see [Reference Bludov and Glass2] for a more general result).

Being an amalgamated product of two perfect groups, M is perfect, therefore, it has no type-1 action. Now suppose by contradiction that M admits a fixed point-free type- $2$ action $\rho : M \to {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {R})$ , which we may assume to be minimal by Proposition 2.3. This implies the existence of a fixed point-free element $t \in {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {R})$ that commutes with $\rho (M)$ . Up to conjugating our action by a suitable homeomorphism, we may assume for the rest of the proof that $x\cdot t=x+1$ for each $x\in \mathbb {R}$ (this follows, for example, from Hölder’s theorem [Reference Deroin, Navas and Rivas13, Theorem 3.1.2]). Also, we declare $ H_1=\rho (\overline {G}_1)$ and $H_2=\rho (\overline {G}_2)$ .

We first claim that neither $H_1$ nor $H_2$ have global fixed points in $\mathbb {R}$ . Indeed, suppose by contradiction that $H_1$ fixes a point x (the proof for $H_2$ is identical). Since $\rho (M)$ has no global fixed points, $H_2$ does not fix x. Thus, there is an $H_2$ -invariant open interval J containing x on which the restriction of the action of $H_2$ is fixed point-free. Since $\overline {G}_2$ does not have proper non-trivial torsion-free quotients by Lemma 3.2, this action on J is faithful.

By Lemma 3.3, the action of $H_2$ on $J\cong \mathbb {R}$ is semiconjugate to the standard action. In particular, $\rho (g)$ does not fix a point in J: otherwise the rotation number of the image of g in $G_2$ would be $0$ . However, looking at the action of all of M, this contradicts the fact that $\rho (g) = \rho (z) \in H_1$ fixes x. This proves our claim. Moreover, it follows from Lemma 3.3 that $H_1$ and $H_2$ are semiconjugate to their standard actions on the real line.

Now the quotient $\mathbb {R} \to \mathbb {R}/\langle t \rangle \cong \mathbb {S}^1$ induces a homomorphism $\phi :M\to {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ with kernel $\langle t\rangle \cap M$ . The restriction of $\phi $ to each $\overline {G}_i$ is fixed point-free on $\mathbb {S}^1$ . Indeed, if it fixed a point, then this fixed point would lift to a discrete orbit, which would have to be fixed pointwise because $\overline {G}_i$ is perfect (and hence non-indicable). However, we have already shown that the restriction of $\rho $ to $\overline {G}_i$ has no global fixed points.

We can therefore use Proposition 3.4 on $\overline {G}_1$ to obtain ${\operatorname {rot}}(\phi (z)) \in \mathbb {Q}/\mathbb {Z}$ , and then on $\overline {G}_2$ to obtain ${\operatorname {rot}}(\phi (g)) \notin \mathbb {Q}/\mathbb {Z}$ . However, $\phi $ is an action of M, so $\phi (g) = \phi (z)$ , which is a contradiction.

(2) It is a standard fact that an amalgamation of two type $F_\infty $ groups along a type $F_\infty $ subgroup is of type $F_\infty $ ; indeed, the amalgamation acts cocompactly on a tree with type $F_{\infty }$ vertex and edge stabilizers, and hence is itself $F_\infty $ , for example, by [Reference Brown3, Propositions 1.1 and 3.1]. The same holds for other finiteness properties, such as finite presentability. Therefore, part ( $2$ ) of the theorem follows.

(3) We use the following fact [Reference Grigorchuk20] (see also [Reference Fujiwara16]): an amalgamated product $A *_C B$ has an infinite-dimensional space of homogeneous quasimorphisms whenever $C \neq B$ and C has at least $3$ double cosets in A. This automatically holds if C is not maximal in A, in particular, it applies to M, which therefore has an infinite-dimensional space of homogeneous quasimorphisms. Being moreover perfect, all such quasimorphisms represent non-trivial classes in bounded cohomology, and witness that M is not uniformly perfect [Reference Calegari9].

(4) The fact that M admits a proximal action follows from the fact that the quotient of M by the normal closure of $\overline {G}_2$ is $G_1$ , which acts proximally on the circle. We now show that this action of M is unique (up to conjugacy).

Let $\rho $ be a proximal action of M on the circle. First, we claim that $\rho (g)$ fixes a point. Assume otherwise. In this case, we obtain that both actions $\rho (\overline {G}_1),\rho (\overline {G}_2)$ are fixed point-free, since the element $\rho (g)=\rho (z)$ acts without fixed points on the circle and is contained in both actions. Since $\overline {G}_1,\overline {G}_2$ do not admit non-trivial finite quotients by Lemma 3.2, it further follows that $\rho (\overline {G}_1),\rho (\overline {G}_2)$ do not admit a finite orbit. This means that they both admit proximalizations, using Theorems 2.1 and 2.4. Now, using the same argument as in the proof of part ( $1$ ), we obtain the contradiction that $\rho (g)=\rho (z)$ has both a rational and an irrational rotation number. This proves our claim that $\rho (g)$ fixes a point in the circle.

Next, we claim that $\rho (\overline {G}_2)$ fixes a point in the circle. If not, again it also cannot admit a finite orbit, so by Theorems 2.1 and 2.4, it must admit a proximalization $\rho^{\prime}$ . Since this is conjugate to the standard action (by our assumption on groups in $\mathcal {G}$ ), this means that $\rho^{\prime}(g)$ has an irrational rotation number. However, this is impossible, since $\rho (g),\rho^{\prime}(g)$ are semiconjugate, and $\rho (g)$ admits a fixed point, so it has rotation number $0$ . This proves that $\rho (\overline {G}_2)$ fixes a point in the circle.

The complement of $\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (\overline {G}_2))$ is a union of open intervals, each of which are individually $\rho (\overline {G}_2)$ -invariant. Since $\overline {G}_2$ does not admit a non-trivial left orderable quotient by Lemma 3.2, the action of $\rho (\overline {G}_2)$ on each these intervals is faithful. Thanks to Lemma 3.3, each of these is semiconjugate to the standard action of $\overline {G}_2$ on $\mathbb {R}$ . Since in the standard action, g does not fix a point, this implies that $\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (\overline {G}_2))=\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (g))$ .

Now let $X=\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (\overline {G}_2))=\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (g)) \subset \mathbb {S}^1$ . Clearly, X is a closed subset of the circle, and X is $\rho (\overline {G}_1)$ -invariant, since $\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (g))=\mathrm{Fix}(\rho (z))$ and $\rho (z)$ is central in $\rho (\overline {G}_1)$ . Hence, X is a closed non-empty $\rho (M)$ -invariant set. By the minimality of $\rho (M)$ , we conclude that $X=\mathbb {S}^1$ . It follows that the element $\rho (g)=\rho (z)$ fixes the circle pointwise, and hence lies in the kernel $\rho :M\to {\operatorname {Homeo}}^+(\mathbb {S}^1)$ . Therefore, $\rho (M)$ descends to a proximal action of $G_1$ , which is unique by our assumption.

We conclude with the main corollary.

Proof of Corollary 1.5

Let $G_1,G_2,M$ be as in the statement of Theorem 1.4, and moreover assume that they are finitely presented (or type $F_\infty $ ). Part ( $4$ ) of Theorem 1.4 tells us that $G_1$ is an invariant for the isomorphism type of M. The class $\mathcal {G}$ contains the finitely presented (even type $F_\infty $ ) groups $T_{2,3,n_3,\dots ,n_k}$ (Example 3.7), which are pairwise non-isomorphic [Reference Liousse25]. We conclude that finitely presented (even type $F_\infty $ ) M can also take on infinitely many isomorphism types.

Acknowledgements

The first author was supported by an ETH Zürich Doc. Mobility Fellowship. The third author was supported by grant no. 635763 from the Simons Foundation.

References

Bludov, V. V. and Glass, A. M. W.. Conjugacy in lattice-ordered groups and right ordered groups. J. Group Theory 11(5) (2008), 623633.10.1515/JGT.2008.038CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bludov, V. V. and Glass, A. M. W.. Word problems, embeddings, and free products of right-ordered groups with amalgamated subgroup. Proc. Lond. Math. Soc. (3) 99(3) (2009), 585608.10.1112/plms/pdp008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, K. S.. Finiteness properties of groups. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 44 (1987), 4575.10.1016/0022-4049(87)90015-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burger, M. and Monod, N.. Bounded cohomology of lattices in higher rank Lie groups. J. Eur. Math. Soc. (JEMS) 1(2) (1999), 199235.10.1007/s100970050007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burger, M. and Monod, N.. Continuous bounded cohomology and applications to rigidity theory. Geom. Funct. Anal. 12(2) (2002), 219280.10.1007/s00039-002-8245-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burger, M. and Mozes, S.. Lattices in product of trees. Publ. Math. Inst. Hautes Études Sci. 92 (2000), 151194 (2001).10.1007/BF02698916CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burillo, J., Nucinkis, B. and Reeves, L.. An irrational-slope Thompson’s group. Publ. Mat. 65(2) (2021), 809839.10.5565/PUBLMAT6522112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burillo, J., Nucinkis, B. and Reeves, L.. Irrational-slope versions of Thompson’s groups $T$ and $V$ . Proc. Edinb. Math. Soc. (2) 65(1) (2022), 244262.10.1017/S0013091522000050CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calegari, D.. scl (MSJ Memoirs, 20). Mathematical Society of Japan, Tokyo, 2009.10.2969/msjmemoirs/020010000CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cannon, J. W., Floyd, W. J. and Parry, W. R.. Introductory notes on Richard Thompson’s groups. Enseign. Math. (2) 42(3–4) (1996), 215256.Google Scholar
Cleary, S.. Regular subdivision in $\mathbf{Z}[\frac{1+\sqrt{5}}{2}]$ . Illinois J. Math. 44(3) (2000), 453464.10.1215/ijm/1256060407CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deroin, B. and Hurtado, S.. Non left-orderability of lattices in higher rank semi-simple Lie groups. Preprint, 2020, arXiv:2008.10687.Google Scholar
Deroin, B., Navas, A. and Rivas, C.. Groups, orders, and dynamics. Preprint, 2016, arXiv:1408.5805.Google Scholar
Fournier-Facio, F. and Lodha, Y.. Second bounded cohomology of groups acting on $1$ -manifolds and applications to spectrum problems. Adv. Math., to appear, arXiv:2111.07931.Google Scholar
Fournier-Facio, F., Löh, C. and Moraschini, M.. Bounded cohomology and binate groups. J. Aust. Math. Soc. doi: 10.1017/S1446788722000106. Published online 10 May 2022.Google Scholar
Fujiwara, K.. The second bounded cohomology of an amalgamated free product of groups. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 352(3) (2000), 11131129.10.1090/S0002-9947-99-02282-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghys, E.. Actions de réseaux sur le cercle. Invent. Math. 137(1) (1999), 199231.10.1007/s002220050329CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghys, E.. Groups acting on the circle. Enseign. Math. (2) 47(3–4) (2001), 329407.Google Scholar
Ghys, E. and Sergiescu, V.. Sur un groupe remarquable de difféomorphismes du cercle. Comment. Math. Helv. 62(2) (1987), 185239.10.1007/BF02564445CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grigorchuk, R. I.. Bounded cohomology of group constructions. Mat. Zametki 59(4) (1996), 546550.Google Scholar
Guelman, N., Liousse, I. and Arnoux, P.. Uniform simplicity for subgroups of piecewise continuous bijections of the unit interval. Bull. Lond. Math. Soc., to appear, arXiv:2109.05706.Google Scholar
Hyde, J. and Lodha, Y.. Finitely generated infinite simple groups of homeomorphisms of the real line. Invent. Math. 218(1) (2019), 83112.10.1007/s00222-019-00880-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyde, J., Lodha, Y., Navas, A. and Rivas, C.. Uniformly perfect finitely generated simple left orderable groups. Ergod. Th. & Dynam. Sys. 41(2) (2021), 534552.10.1017/etds.2019.59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kazhdan, D. A.. On the connection of the dual space of a group with the structure of its closed subgroups. Funkcional. Anal. i Priložen. 1 (1967), 7174.Google Scholar
Liousse, I.. Rotation numbers in Thompson–Stein groups and applications. Geom. Dedicata 131 (2008), 4971.10.1007/s10711-007-9216-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lodha, Y.. A finitely presented infinite simple group of homeomorphisms of the circle. J. Lond. Math. Soc. (2) 100(3) (2019), 10341064.10.1112/jlms.12254CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lodha, Y. and Zaremsky, M. C. B.. The BNSR-invariants of the Lodha–Moore groups, and an exotic simple group of type ${\mathrm{F}}_{\infty }$ . Math. Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc. 174(1) (2023), 2548.10.1017/S0305004122000111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malyutin, A. V.. Classification of group actions on the line and the circle. Algebra i Analiz 19(2) (2007), 156182.Google Scholar
Margulis, G.. Free subgroups of the homeomorphism group of the circle. C. R. Math. Acad. Sci. Paris 331(9) (2000), 669674.10.1016/S0764-4442(00)01694-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matte Bon, N. and Triestino, M.. Groups of piecewise linear homeomorphisms of flows. Compos. Math. 156(8) (2020), 15951622.10.1112/S0010437X20007356CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Navas, A.. Groups of Circle Diffeomorphisms (Chicago Lectures in Mathematics), Spanish edition. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 2011.10.7208/chicago/9780226569505.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Navas, A.. Group actions on 1-manifolds: a list of very concrete open questions. Proc. Int. Congress of Mathematicians (Rio de Janeiro, 2018). Vol. III. Invited Lectures. Eds. B. Sirakov, P. Ney de Souza and M. Viana. World Scientific Publishing, Hackensack, NJ, 2018, pp. 20352062.Google Scholar
Stein, M.. Groups of piecewise linear homeomorphisms. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 332(2) (1992), 477514.10.1090/S0002-9947-1992-1094555-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar