Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T00:05:56.072Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Social Deliberation: Nash, Bayes, and the Partial Vindication of Gabriele Tarde

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

At the very end of the 19th century, Gabriele Tarde wrote that all society was a product of imitation and innovation. This view regarding the development of society has, to a large extent, fallen out of favour, and especially so in those areas where the rational actor model looms large. I argue that this is unfortunate, as models of imitative learning, in some cases, agree better with what people actually do than more sophisticated models of learning. In this paper, I contrast the behaviour of imitative learning with two more sophisticated learning rules (one based on Bayesian updating, the other based on the Nash-Brown-von Neumann dynamics) in the context of social deliberation problems. I show for two social deliberation problems, the Centipede game and a simple Lewis sender-receiver game, that imitative learning provides better agreement with what people actually do, thus partially vindicating Tarde.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alexander, J. McKenzie. 2007. The Structural Evolution of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexander, J. McKenzie. 2009. “Local Interaction and the Dynamics of Rational Deliberation.” Philosophical Studies. Forthcoming.Google Scholar
Alexander, Jason and Skyrms, Brian. 1999. “Bargaining with Neighbors: Is Justice Contagious?Journal of Philosophy 96(11): 588–98.Google Scholar
Fey, Mark, McKelvey, Richard D., and Palfrey, Thomas R.. 1996. “An Experimental Study of Constant-Sum Centipede Games.” International Journal of Game Theory 25: 269–87.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd and Selten, Reinhard. (eds.) 2001. Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hollis, Martin. 1994. The Philosophy of Social Science: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2002. “Gabriel Tarde and the End of the Social.” In Joyce, P. (ed.), The Social in Question, pp. 117–32. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lehrer, Keith and Wagner, Carl. 1981. Rational Consensus in Science and Society. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David K. 1969. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McKelvey, Richard D. and Palfrey, Thomas R.. 1992. “An Experimental Study of the Centipede Game.” Econometrica 60(4): 803–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millet, Jean. 1970. Gabriel Tarde et la philosophie de l'Histoire. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, Robert W. 1981. “Games of Perfect Information, Predatory Pricing, and the Chain Store.” Journal of Economic Theory 25: 92100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 1990. The Dynamics of Rational Deliberation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 2009. “Evolution of Signalling Systems with Multiple Senders and Receivers.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 364: 771–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smead, Rory. 2008. “The Evolution of Cooperation in the Centipede Game with Finite Populations.” Philosophy of Science 75: 157–77.Google Scholar
Tarde, Gabriel. 1890/1903. The Laws of Imitation. Trans. Elsie Clews Parsons from 2nd French ed. New York: Henry Holt and Company.Google Scholar
Vanderschraaf, Peter and Alexander, J. McKenzie. 2005. “Follow the Leader: Local Interactions with Influence Neighborhoods.” Philosophy of Science 72: 86113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar