Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-30T20:26:55.404Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PERMISSIVISM AND THE ARBITRARINESS OBJECTION

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 October 2016

Abstract

Permissivism says that for some propositions and bodies of evidence, there is more than one rationally permissible doxastic attitude that can be taken towards that proposition given the evidence. Some critics of this view argue that it condones, as rationally acceptable, sets of attitudes that manifest an untenable kind of arbitrariness. I begin by providing a new and more detailed explication of what this alleged arbitrariness consists in. I then explain why Miriam Schoenfield's prima facie promising attempt to answer the Arbitrariness Objection, by appealing to the role of epistemic standards in rational belief formation, fails to resolve the problem. Schoenfield's strategy is, however, a useful one, and I go on to explain how an alternative form of the standards-based approach to Permissivism – one that emphasizes the significance of the relationship between people's cognitive abilities and the epistemic standards that they employ – can respond to the arbitrariness objection.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ballantyne, N. and Coffman, E. J. 2011. ‘Uniqueness, Evidence, and Rationality.’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 11: 113.Google Scholar
Ballantyne, N. Coffman, E. J. 2012. ‘Conciliationism and Uniqueness.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90: 657–70.Google Scholar
Berker, S. 2013. ‘Epistemic Teleology and the Separateness of Propositions.’ Philosophical Review, 122: 337–93.Google Scholar
Brueckner, A. and Bundy, A. 2012. ‘On ‘Epistemic Permissiveness’.’ Synthese, 188: 165–77.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. 2007. ‘Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good News.’ Philosophical Review, 116: 187217.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. 2010. ‘Higher-order Evidence.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81: 185215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. Forthcoming. ‘Conciliationism, Uniqueness, and Rational Toxicity.’ Noûs. doi: 10.1111/nous.12077.Google Scholar
Conee, E. 2009. ‘Peerage.’ Episteme, 6: 313–23.Google Scholar
Conee, E. 2010. ‘Rational Disagreement Defended.’ In Feldman, R. and Warfield, T. A. (eds), Disagreement, pp. 6990. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Douven, I. 2009. ‘Uniqueness Revisited.’ American Philosophical Quarterly, 46: 347–61.Google Scholar
Elga, A. 2007. ‘Reflection and Disagreement,’ Noûs, 41: 478502.Google Scholar
Elga, A. 2010. ‘How to Disagree about How to Disagree.’ In Feldman, R. and Warfield, T. A. (eds), Disagreement, pp. 175–86. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Elga, A. 2013. ‘The Puzzle of the Unmarked Clock and the New Rational Reflection Principle.’ Philosophical Studies, 164: 127–39.Google Scholar
Elgin, C. Z. 2010. ‘Persistent Disagreement.’ In Feldman, R. and Warfield, T. A. (eds), Disagreement, pp. 5368. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2010. ‘Not Just a Truthometer: Taking Oneself Seriously (But Not Too Seriously) in Cases of Peer Disagreement.’ Mind, 119: 953–97.Google Scholar
Feldman, R. 2006. ‘Epistemological Puzzles about Disagreement.’ In Hetherington, S. (ed.), Epistemology Futures, pp. 216–36. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, R. 2007. ‘Reasonable Religious Disagreements.’ In Antony, L. (ed.), Philosophers Without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fumerton, R. 2010. ‘You Can't Trust a Philosopher.’ In Feldman, R. and Warfield, T. (eds), Disagreement, pp. 91110. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, J. 2009. ‘Probabilism Today: Permissibility and Multi-account Ethics.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87: 235–50.Google Scholar
Horowitz, S. 2014. ‘Epistemic Akrasia.’ Noûs, 48: 718–44.Google Scholar
Kelly, T. 2014. ‘Evidence Can Be Permissive.’ In Steup, M., Turri, J. and Sosa, E. (eds), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd edition, pp. 298311. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
King, N. L. 2012. ‘Disagreement: What's the Problem? Or A Good Peer is Hard to Find.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85: 249–72.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1993. The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lougheed, K. and Simpson, R. M. Forthcoming. ‘Indirect Epistemic Reasons and Religious Belief.’ Religious Studies.Google Scholar
Lynch, M. P. 2010. ‘Epistemic Circularity and Epistemic Incommensurability.’ In Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D. (eds), Social Epistemology, pp. 262–77. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Matheson, J. 2011. ‘The Case for Rational Uniqueness.’ Logos and Episteme, 2: 359–73.Google Scholar
Matheson, J. 2015. The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1859. On Liberty. London: J. W. Parker and Son.Google Scholar
Riggs, W. D. 2008. ‘Epistemic Risk and Relativism.’ Acta Analytica, 23: 18.Google Scholar
Rosa, L. 2012. ‘Justification and the Uniqueness Thesis.’ Logos & Episteme, 3: 571–77.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. 2001. ‘Nominalism, Naturalism, Epistemic Relativism.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 15: 6991.Google Scholar
Schoenfield, M. 2012. ‘Chilling Out on Epistemic Rationality: A Defence of Imprecise Credences (and Other Imprecise Doxastic Attitudes).’ Philosophical Studies, 158: 197219.Google Scholar
Schoenfield, M. 2014. ‘Permission to Believe: Why Permissivism Is True and What It Tells Us about Irrelevant Influences on Belief.’ Noûs, 48: 193218.Google Scholar
Simpson, R. M. 2013. ‘Epistemic Peerhood and the Epistemology of Disagreement.’ Philosophical Studies, 164: 561–77.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 2010. ‘The Epistemology of Disagreement.’ In Haddock, A., Millar, A. and Pritchard, D. (eds), Social Epistemology, pp. 278–97. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbot, B. 2014. ‘Truth Promoting Non-evidential Reasons for Belief.’ Philosophical Studies, 168: 599618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. 2005. ‘Epistemic Permissiveness.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 19: 445–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. 2009. ‘On Treating Oneself and Others as Thermometers.’ Episteme, 6: 233–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. 2014. ‘Evidence Cannot Be Permissive.’ In Steup, M., Turri, J. and Sosa, E. (eds), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd edition, pp. 312–23. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar