Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T05:59:52.306Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

IS FOUNDATIONAL A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION INDISPENSABLE?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 August 2013

Abstract

Laurence BonJour's (1985) coherence theory of empirical knowledge relies heavily on a traditional foundationalist theory of a priori knowledge. He argues that a foundationalist, rationalist theory of a priori justification is indispensable for a coherence theory. BonJour (1998) continues this theme, arguing that a traditional account of a priori justification is indispensable for the justification of putative a priori truths, the justification of any non-observational belief and the justification of reasoning itself. While BonJour's indispensability arguments have received some critical discussion (Gendler 2001; Harman 2001; Beebe 2008), no one has investigated the indispensability arguments from a coherentist perspective. This perspective offers a fruitful take on BonJour's arguments, because he does not appreciate the depth of the coherentist alternative to the traditional empiricist-rationalist debate. This is surprising on account of BonJour's previous defense of coherentism. Two significant conclusions emerge: first, BonJour's indispensability arguments beg central questions about an explanationist form of coherentism; second, BonJour's original defense of coherentism took on board certain assumptions that inevitably led to the demise of his form of coherentism. The positive conclusion of this article is that explanatory coherentism is more coherent than BonJour's indispensability arguments assume, and more coherent than BonJour's earlier coherentist epistemology.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Beebe, J. 2011. ‘A Priori Skepticism.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXXIII(3): 583602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergmann, M. 2004. ‘Epistemic Circularity: Malignant and Benign.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXIX(3): 709–27.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P. 2001. ‘Inference and Insight.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXIII(3): 633–40.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
BonJour, L.. 1997. ‘Haack on Experience and Justification.’ Synthese 112: 1323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BonJour, L.. 1998. In Defense of Pure Reason. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
BonJour, L.. 2001a. ‘Precis of in Defense of Pure Reason.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXIII(3): 625–31.Google Scholar
BonJour, L.. 2001b. ‘Replies.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(3): 673–98.Google Scholar
Brewer, W. and Lambert, B. 2001. ‘The Theory-ladenness of Observation and the Theory-ladenness of the Rest of the Scientific Process.’ Philosophy of Science 68: S176–86.Google Scholar
Cornman, J. 1980. Scepticism, Justification, and Explanation. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Field, H. 1996. ‘The a Prioricity of Logic.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96: 359–79.Google Scholar
Fumerton, R. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. 1965. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 2001. ‘General Foundations versus Rational Insight.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXIII(3): 657–63.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. 2007. Quine. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1982. ‘Logic for Equivocators.’ Nous 16(3): 431–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P. 2004. Inference to the Best Explanation, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1988. Judgment and Justification, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W.. 1996. “Plantinga and Coherentisms.” In Kranvig, Jonathan (ed.), Warrant in Contemporary Epistemology: Essays in Honor of Plantinga's Theory of Knowledge. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Lycan, W.. 2002. “Explanation and Epistemology.” In Moser, Paul (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 2012. ‘Explanationist Rebuttals (Coherentism Defended Again).’ The Southern Journal of Philosophy 50(1): 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1993. Warrant and Proper Function. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, G. 1985–1986. ‘Contradiction, Belief and Rationality.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86:99116.Google Scholar
Priest, G.. 1998. ‘What Is so Bad about Contradictions?Journal of Philosophy 95(8): 410–26.Google Scholar
Quine, W. and Ullian, J. 1970. The Web of Belief. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Roland, J. 2009. ‘On Naturalizing the Epistemology of Mathematics.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90:6397.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1963. Science, Perception and Reality. Atacadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing.Google Scholar