Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T02:07:32.991Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Epistemological Disjunctivism and the Conditionality Problem for Externalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2022

Santiago Echeverri*
Affiliation:
Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Mexico City, Mexico
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Epistemological disjunctivism (ED) has been thought to solve the conditionality problem for epistemic externalism. This problem arises from externalists’ characterization of our epistemic standings as conditional on the obtaining of worldly facts which we lack any reflective access to. ED is meant to avoid the conditionality problem by explicating subjects’ perceptual knowledge in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge via their possession of perceptual reasons that are both factive and reflectively accessible. I argue that ED's account of reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons is also prey to the conditionality problem. After that, I submit that Stroud's influential formulation of the conditionality problem relies on a methodological requirement that is potentially dissociable from ED. So, it is possible to put ED in the service of a more modest anti-skeptical strategy. I close by suggesting that this modest anti-skeptical strategy successfully undercuts the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox. Nevertheless, it does not have substantial advantages over some forms of epistemic externalism.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

While Hannah is strolling through the market, she sees some asparagus exhibited in a stand and forms the belief that there are asparagus in the stand. The asparagus are in plain view, the illumination conditions are normal, Hannah's visual system is in good order, and she lacks any reasons for doubt. So, Hannah knows that there are asparagus in the stand.

A central philosophical task is to elucidate the contribution of perception to Hannah's perceptual knowledge. Epistemological disjunctivism (ED) offers an influential proposal:

ED: epistemological disjunctivism. In paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge, a subject, S, has perceptual knowledge that p in virtue of being in possession of reasons for her belief that p which are both factive and reflectively accessible to S (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 13).Footnote 1

A familiar view holds that, if a subject, S, has reflective access to p, then S reflectively knows p. There has been little work on the nature of reflective knowledge of factive perceptual reasons (but see Greco Reference Greco2014; Fratantonio Reference FratantonioForthcoming; Giananti Reference GianantiForthcoming). Nevertheless, the following paraphrase will work for our current purposes: ‘reflection’ characterizes the ability that we deploy when we search our memories to answer some questions (e.g., ‘Who was the first president of the United States?’), or when we make the contents of our experiences explicit (e.g., ‘I have an experience as of a green apple’). Reflective access denotes knowledge gained by deploying that ability (Cunningham Reference Cunningham2016). In our original example, Hannah sees that there are asparagus in the stand, her reason is factive because it entails that there are asparagus in the stand, and Hannah can know that she has this factive reason at her disposal by deploying the ability mentioned in the previous examples.

It has been argued that ED can improve upon internalist and externalist accounts of perceptual knowledge (McDowell Reference McDowell1995, Reference McDowell2002, Reference McDowell, Haddock and Macpherson2008, Reference McDowell2010, Reference McDowell2011, Reference McDowell2013, Reference McDowell, Doyle, Milburn and Pritchard2019; Rödl Reference Rödl2007; Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012, Reference Pritchard2016; Kern Reference Kern2017).Footnote 2 This article focuses on ED's attempt at improving upon externalist treatments of radical skepticism.Footnote 3 Externalist treatments of skepticism have been thought to face the ‘conditionality problem’. The conditionality problem arises when a theory of knowledge makes our epistemic standings conditional on the obtaining of worldly facts which we lack any reflective access to (Stroud Reference Stroud1989, Reference Stroud1994, Reference Stroud and Greco2004; Fumerton Reference Fumerton, Roth and Ross1990, Reference Fumerton1995, Reference Fumerton, Crisp, Davidson and Laan2006; Pritchard Reference Pritchard2005, Reference Pritchard2012; Ahlstrom-Vij Reference Ahlstrom-Vij2011; Fernández-Vargas Reference Fernández-Vargas2020; Echeverri Reference EcheverriMs a). An alleged advantage of ED over externalism is that it offers a way out of the conditionality problem.

I will argue that ED's account of reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons is also prey to the conditionality problem. After that, I will submit that the conditionality problem is parasitic on a methodological requirement that is potentially dissociable from ED. So, it is possible to put ED in the service of a more modest anti-skeptical strategy. I will close by showing that this modest anti-skeptical strategy successfully undercuts the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox. Nevertheless, it does not have substantial advantages over some forms of externalism.Footnote 4

The article has six sections. I start with a reconstruction of two alleged advantages of ED over externalist theories of perceptual knowledge (section 2). I then use that reconstruction to present the conditionality problem (section 3) and explain how it arises for ED (section 4). Next, I respond to some pressing objections (section 5). Subsequently, I identify a methodological requirement that generates the conditionality problem and suggest that it is potentially dissociable from ED (section 6). Finally, I use the results of the discussion to sketch a modest solution to the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox (section 7).

2. Epistemic responsibility and radical skepticism

Duncan Pritchard has advertised ED as having two advantages over externalism. The first one concerns epistemic responsibility:

From epistemic internalism [ED] takes the idea that knowledge demands epistemic support that is reflectively available to the subject. In doing so it is in a position to capture, in line with standard forms of epistemic internalism, the role that epistemic responsibility plays in our acquisition of (perceptual) knowledge. (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 3)

The second putative advantage of ED over externalism concerns skepticism. For Pritchard, epistemic externalism ‘side-steps’ the skeptical problem instead of facing it ‘head on’ (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 120, 134, 137):

[O]pting for epistemic externalism as a route out of the skeptical predicament … appears to side-step the issue altogether by making our epistemic standings conditional on the obtaining of worldly facts which one lacks any reflective access to and which are in any case in dispute in a debate with the skeptic. In contrast, if epistemological disjunctivism were a viable theory then a potential route out of this problem becomes available, since we can now appeal to reflectively accessible elements of our epistemic standings which entail facts about the world. Thus, the problem is not side-stepped by appealing to facts beyond our reflective ken. (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 4)

The concept of epistemic responsibility that features in the first passage is key to ED's attempt at facing the skeptical challenge ‘head on’. We will need to elucidate this link before we can understand the conditionality problem mentioned in the second passage.

Let us introduce the concept of epistemic responsibility with a familiar, internalist conception of knowledge. We will generalize this account in due time.

internalist knowledge. If a subject, S, has internalist knowledge of p, then S is in a position to rationally claim knowledge of p in response to challenges.

Knowledge claims can be explicit, as in ‘I know p’. But they can also be implicit, as when a subject asserts ‘p’, presenting herself as someone who knows p. We can use this internalist conception of knowledge to formulate a necessary condition for epistemic responsibility:

epistemic responsibility. If S's knowledge of p is epistemically responsible, then S is in a position to rationally claim ‘(I know) p’.

Internalist knowledge requires epistemic responsibility. Under what conditions is it rational for a subject to make a knowledge claim? Let us abstract from pragmatic considerations and focus on the epistemic conditions to rationally make a knowledge claim. If we bracket knowledge of obvious propositions like [I am thinking] and [A=A], two epistemic conditions seem necessary: If it is rational for a subject, S, to claim knowledge of p, then:

  1. (1) S has reasons that favor p over some salient, incompatible alternative not-p, and

  2. (2) S could potentially cite those reasons to back up her knowledge claim.

Conditions 1–2 partly explain why epistemic responsibility has led some philosophers to defend a form of internalism known as ‘accessibilism’. accessibilism is at the heart of ED as well:

accessibilism. S's internalist epistemic support for believing that p is constituted solely by facts that S can know by reflection alone (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 36).Footnote 5

Suppose that a subject, S, is in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge and perceptually knows p. If S cannot know her perceptual reasons by reflection, it is hard to see how S could potentially cite those reasons to back up her claim to know p. Suppose now that our subject can know her perceptual reasons by reflection, but her reasons do not favor p over some incompatible alternative q that is salient in the relevant context. Once again, it is hard to see how S could potentially cite those reasons to back up her claim to know p. The situation seems to change dramatically with ED. Given ED, S knows p in virtue of seeing that p. Seeing that p is factive, so it favors p over any incompatible proposition. This factive reason is reflectively accessible to S in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. So, S could potentially cite this reason to back up her claim to know p.

Many internalists think of epistemic responsibility and accessibilism as necessary for knowledge. Nevertheless, weaker views are available. A subject who can take epistemic responsibility for her knowledge of p is surely in a better epistemic position than another subject who knows p but who cannot take epistemic responsibility for her knowledge of p. As an illustration, think of the proverbial chicken sexers, a group of subjects who reliably form beliefs about the sex of chickens but who also lack reflectively accessible reasons in favor of their beliefs (Foley Reference Foley1987; Brandom Reference Brandom1998). Compare these subjects with some ‘enlightened chicken sexers’ who have reflectively accessible reasons in favor of their beliefs. One can recognize that the enlightened chicken sexers are in a better epistemic position than the proverbial chicken sexers without thereby construing epistemic responsibility and accessibilism as necessary for knowledge. In addition, one might hold that satisfying epistemic responsibility is necessary to attain some epistemic aims. It is this weaker view that we need to understand why externalism has been thought to provide an unsatisfactory treatment of skepticism. For Pritchard, the externalist ‘side-steps’ the skeptical problem “by making our epistemic standings conditional on the obtaining of worldly facts which one lacks any reflective access to and which are in any case in dispute in a debate with the skeptic”. In doing so, the externalist cannot face the skeptical problem ‘head on’. To face the skeptical problem ‘head on’, we need to provide an account of perceptual knowledge that puts us in a position to make perceptual knowledge claims in the context of a skeptical challenge.

Interestingly, ED seems to offer what we are looking for. Suppose that a subject, S, is in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge. If S perceptually knows p, S has reflectively accessible reasons that conclusively favor p over any incompatible proposition. So, ED gives S all it takes – from an epistemic point of view – to rationally claim knowledge of p in response to a skeptical challenge. Abstracting from pragmatic considerations, S could back up her claims to know p by citing her seeing that p.

I will argue that this view is still prey to the conditionality problem mentioned in the second quote from Pritchard. I will first present the conditionality problem in a general form (section 3) and then show how it arises for ED (section 4).

3. The conditionality problem

Several authors think that externalism provides an unsatisfactory treatment of skepticism because it makes our epistemic standings conditional on the obtaining of worldly facts which we lack any reflective access to (Stroud Reference Stroud1989, Reference Stroud1994, Reference Stroud and Greco2004; Fumerton Reference Fumerton, Roth and Ross1990, Reference Fumerton1995, Reference Fumerton, Crisp, Davidson and Laan2006; Pritchard Reference Pritchard2005, Reference Pritchard2012). Why is this a problem? Different authors have provided different answers to this question. Rather than offering an exhaustive review of these answers, I will make a relatively uncontroversial proposal: the conditionality problem is a problem because the conditional character of externalist accounts of knowledge prevents subjects from rationally making any knowledge claims when the conditional character of knowledge becomes salient. Crucially, the conditional character of knowledge becomes salient when a subject recognizes radical skeptical hypotheses as incompatible with her everyday beliefs.Footnote 6

Let us focus on those ‘reflective subjects’ who have examined the problem of skepticism (Stroud Reference Stroud1984: 80–1; Pritchard Reference Pritchard2005: 210, 246). Reflective subjects want to determine whether they have any perceptual knowledge of the world. It will be useful to think of those subjects as trying to determine whether a given perceptual belief is a case of knowledge. Simplifying a bit, we could think of reflective subjects as using their favored theory of knowledge to perform ‘self-ascription transitions’ of the following form:

self-ascription transition (I)

Premise 1. I believe p.

Premise 2. A given theory of knowledge is true.

Conclusion. So, I know p.

Starting from a (perceptual) belief, the reflective subject wonders whether that belief is a case of knowledge. Our subject tries to make use of her favored theory of knowledge to move from the self-ascribed (perceptual) belief to a first-person knowledge claim. There is a problem, though. Any theory of knowledge has a conditional structure:

If S's belief in p satisfies conditions C1, C2…, Cn, then S knows p.

Given the conditional structure of theories of knowledge, a subject cannot rationally move from her two premises to a first-person knowledge claim. To do so, the subject should be able to ‘detach’ the antecedent of her favored theory of knowledge and apply it to her herself (Stroud Reference Stroud1994: 152). So, our reflective subject should be able to reason as follows:

self-ascription transition (II)

Premise 1. I believe p.

Premise 2. If S's belief in p satisfies conditions C1, C2…, Cn, then S knows p.

Premise 3. My belief in p satisfies conditions C1, C2…, Cn.

Conclusion. So, I know p.

To make a first-person knowledge claim, the reflective subject needs to determine whether her belief in p satisfies conditions C1, C2…, Cn. Recall now the example of the proverbial chicken sexers. Externalists hold that the chicken sexers can have knowledge of the sex of chickens despite their lack of reflective access to the conditions that explain that knowledge. So, the chicken sexers do not know whether the conditions for their own knowledge are satisfied. Perhaps we could grant that the chicken sexers have knowledge. However, this verdict becomes problematic when we generalize the epistemic standing of the chicken sexers to reflective subjects. If reflective subjects only have ‘crude’ externalist knowledge at their disposal, they won't be able to determine whether a given perceptual belief is a case of knowledge. That is, in a nutshell, the conditionality problem.Footnote 7

4. The conditionality problem for epistemological disjunctivism

A solution to the conditionality problem must provide reflective subjects with the resources to ‘detach’ the antecedent of their favored theory of knowledge. One might try to achieve this goal by incorporating an accessibilist component into one's favored theory of knowledge. If the conditions imposed by the theory of knowledge are accessible by reflection, reflective subjects could manage to self-ascribe knowledge (Stroud Reference Stroud and Greco2004: 170–1). We have seen that ED incorporates reflective access to factive perceptual reasons. So, one might think that ED provides all we need to detach the antecedent. However, when we consider ED in a broader context, we can see that the conditionality problem has not been solved; it has been pushed one level up (see also Stroud Reference Stroud1994: 152; Fumerton Reference Fumerton1995: 178–9).

Here is my argument in a nutshell. ED's account of reflective knowledge of factive perceptual reasons is also conditional on the obtaining of worldly facts which one lacks any reflective access to. The conditional character of reflective knowledge of factive perceptual reasons becomes salient when a reflective subject recognizes a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with her everyday beliefs. Alas, there is nothing in ED that would enable a reflective subject to ‘detach’ the antecedent of ED's conditional characterization of reflective knowledge. This problem immediately spreads to the subject's attempt at self-ascribing first-order knowledge of everyday propositions. Therefore, ED's appeal to reflective knowledge of factive perceptual reasons does not genuinely put a reflective subject in a position to rationally make perceptual knowledge claims when the conditional character of her own reflective knowledge becomes salient in the light of a radical skeptical hypothesis.

I will develop this argument by spelling out the epistemic consequences of a reflective subject's consideration of a radical skeptical hypothesis.

Step 1. While Hannah is strolling through the market, she sees that there are asparagus in the stand. So, she decides to call her husband to report on her finding: ‘I see that there are asparagus in the stand. Would you like to have asparagus for lunch?’ Being a sincere speaker, Hannah has expressed the belief that she sees that there are asparagus in the stand. After Hannah hangs up, she suddenly remembers the brain in a vat (BIV) hypothesis. This irruptive thought is not as surprising as it might seem. Hannah has been working on a paper on radical skepticism. The BIV hypothesis says that Hannah's brain has been recently envatted and her experiences are now produced by a supercomputer. Upon realizing that this error possibility is incompatible with her current belief that she sees that there are asparagus in the stand, Hannah wonders whether she knows that she sees that there are asparagus in the stand.

Step 2. It might be tempting for Hannah to appeal to her reflectively accessible factive perceptual reason to settle the question. But this does not seem to be a viable option. The BIV hypothesis casts doubt on her seeing that there are asparagus in the stand. Dismissing a hypothesis that casts doubt on Hannah's possession of a perceptual reason by citing the same perceptual reason would be like trying to justify the reliability of the testimony of an eyewitness by asking the eyewitness whether she is telling the truth. These considerations lead Hannah to conclude that she may not avail herself of a factive perceptual reason to rationally dismiss the BIV hypothesis.Footnote 8

Step 3. Hannah has some familiarity with externalist theories of knowledge. However, those theories of knowledge do not enable Hannah to answer her original question. After all, no matter what externalist view she favors, any externalist theory will make her epistemic standing “conditional on the obtaining of worldly facts which one lacks any reflective access to and which are in any case in dispute in a debate with the skeptic” (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 4). Perhaps ED offers her a way out of her predicament. She recalls the following definition: “In paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge, a subject, S, has perceptual knowledge that p in virtue of being in possession of reasons for her belief that p which are both factive and reflectively accessible to S” (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 13). Unfortunately, this formulation has a hidden, conditional structure. It tells her that, if she is in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge, she has perceptual knowledge in virtue of being in possession of perceptual reasons that are both factive and reflectively accessible to her. So, the key to answering her original question lies in the concept of a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge.

Defenders of ED have developed a complex analysis of paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. For our current purposes, we can focus on one key feature. Paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge are ‘objectively epistemically good’. If Hannah is in one of those cases, she is in an environment that allows for the reliable formation of perceptual beliefs and her cognitive and perceptual capacities are functioning properly (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 29).Footnote 9

With these materials in hand, Hannah tries to self-ascribe knowledge that she sees that there are asparagus in the stand:

self-ascription transition (III)

Premise 1. I believe that I see that there are asparagus in the stand.

Premise 2. If I am in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge (which entails that I am in an environment that allows for the reliable formation of perceptual beliefs and my cognitive and perceptual capacities are functioning properly), then I can know by reflection that I see that there are asparagus in the stand.

Upon reaching Premise 2, Hannah is stuck. ED tells her that, if she is in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge, she is in possession of perceptual reasons which are both factive and reflectively accessible to her. However, nothing in ED tells her that the condition of being in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge is indeed satisfied. So, Hannah may not self-ascribe knowledge that she sees that there are asparagus in the stand.

To be sure, there is a key difference between ED and (some forms of) externalism: there is less epistemic opacity in ED than in the case of the proverbial chicken sexers.Footnote 10 ED explains the possession of perceptual knowledge in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge via reasons that are both factive and reflectively accessible to the subject. However, this difference is of little significance when it comes to Hannah's attempt at self-ascribing second-order knowledge that she sees that p after having recognized a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with her belief that she sees that p. For ED, the possession of this reflective knowledge is relative to the obtaining of worldly facts that the subject “lacks any reflective access to and which are in any case in dispute in a debate with the skeptic” (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 4). Unfortunately, this conditional structure is sufficient to generate the conditionality problem.

Some readers might wonder why this version of the conditionality problem matters. After all, it might seem that ED fares better than (some forms of) externalism. While (some) externalists treat all subjects as epistemically on a par with the proverbial chicken sexers, ED enables us to accommodate epistemic responsibility.

The answer is that the conditionality problem for reflective knowledge of factive perceptual reasons will soon contaminate Hannah's ability to rationally claim first-order perceptual knowledge. Suppose that Hannah tries to self-ascribe knowledge that there are asparagus in the stand. Trying to employ ED, Hannah will get stuck at the same point as before:

self-ascription transition (IV)

Premise 1. I believe that there are asparagus in the stand.

Premise 2. If I am in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge (which entails that I am in an environment that allows for the reliable formation of perceptual beliefs and my cognitive and perceptual capacities are functioning properly), then I know that there are asparagus in the stand in virtue of being in possession of reasons for my belief that there are asparagus in the stand which are both factive and reflectively accessible to me.

Unfortunately, it is not reflectively accessible to Hannah whether she is in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge. So, Hannah cannot rationally claim to know [I see that there are asparagus in the stand]. If she cannot rationally claim to know [I see that there are asparagus in the stand], she has no way of backing up her claim to know the first-order proposition [There are asparagus in the stand]. Once Hannah realizes that she cannot take epistemic responsibility for the truth of the second-order belief, and she realizes that this is her way of backing up her first-order belief in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge, the rational support for the first-order belief starts to look baseless.

The conditionality problem relies on a simple logical observation. To make a first-person knowledge claim, the reflective subject should be able to determine whether her perceptual belief satisfies all the conditions for knowledge. Otherwise, the reflective subject won't be able to rationally detach the antecedent of her favored theory of knowledge and apply it to her herself (Stroud Reference Stroud1994: 152). ED tries to improve upon externalist theories of knowledge by reducing the opacity of the subject's epistemic standing. However, this move is insufficient to overcome the logical obstacle that generates the conditionality problem. It suffices that ED posits one opaque worldly condition to prevent the reflective subject from rationally detaching the antecedent. This problem soon contaminates the subject's ability to rationally claim first-order perceptual knowledge.

5. Objections and replies

In this section, I consider some ways in which defenders of ED might try to block the conditionality problem for ED.

Objection 1. Paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge are cases where there are no defeaters. In the presence of defeaters, however, subjects lack reflective access to factive perceptual reasons. When a subject engages in self-ascription transitions (III) and (IV), she becomes aware of a defeater. Therefore, ED's account of reflective access is not undermined.

Reply. Talk of defeaters is a red herring. It obscures the fact that the conditionality problem relies on a logical observation. If you are a reflective subject who is in the business of self-ascribing knowledge, you must be able to detach the antecedent of your favored theory of knowledge and apply it to you yourself. One can make this point even if one remains neutral on whether the mere recognition of an error possibility as incompatible with a given belief is sufficient to introduce a defeater. Suppose now that the mere recognition of an error possibility as incompatible with a given belief is sufficient to introduce a defeater. In this case, ED should avail itself of the means of rationally dismissing the defeater and show that those means will enable the subject to detach the antecedent of ED. I shall examine three salient options.

Objection 2. We all tacitly know what it takes to be in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge. Defenders of ED rely on this tacit knowledge when they formulate their theory. This tacit knowledge is sufficient to know that the antecedent of ED is satisfied. Thus, it is a mistake to hold that ED does not provide the reflective subject with sufficient conditions to detach the antecedent of ED.

Reply. Let us grant that we all have tacit knowledge of what it takes to be in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge. We can also concede that some of the conditions to be in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge are reflectively accessible. For example, we are in a position to know whether we have grounds for doubt about a proposition. Thus, we are in a position to tell whether our case is ‘subjectively epistemically good’—to use Pritchard's (Reference Pritchard2012: 30) apt phrase. However, nothing in ED entails that we can know, by reflection, that our current environment allows for the reliable formation of perceptual beliefs and that our cognitive and perceptual capacities are functioning properly.

Perhaps one might insist that subjects normally have background empirical evidence that speaks to the ‘benevolent’ character of their environment and the proper functioning of their cognitive and perceptual capacities (Vogel Reference Vogel, Roth and Ross1990; Williams Reference Williams2001; Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012, Reference Pritchard2016). Nevertheless, this background empirical evidence is not available in the current context. Radical skeptical error possibilities cast doubt on all one's empirical beliefs. Thus, no empirical reasons are available to ground one's knowledge that one's current environment allows for the reliable formation of perceptual beliefs and that one's cognitive and perceptual capacities are functioning properly (McDowell Reference McDowell1982: 273–4, 391, Reference McDowell1995: 398; Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 85, 123, 126, Reference Pritchard2016: 137–8). Crucially, the satisfaction of these objective conditions is necessary to be in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge.

It might be argued that Hannah has a priori knowledge that she is in an objectively good case (Cohen Reference Cohen1999). Unfortunately, defenders of ED have expressed skepticism about the possession of this type of a priori knowledge (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 19, Reference Pritchard2016: 129–30). To my mind, they are antecedently committed to making this move. If Hannah had a priori knowledge that she is in an objectively good case, ED's claim that internalism provides an inadequate treatment of skepticism would be unwarranted. If Hannah had a priori knowledge that she is in an objectively good case, it would be hard to understand why ED insists on the possession of perceptual reasons that are both factive and reflectively accessible. Hence, ED is best understood as arising from the conviction that those a priori reasons are unavailable.

Having exhausted all her options, Hannah recalls the ‘indistinguishability intuition’:

indistinguishability intuition. There can be pairs of veridical and non-veridical experiences that cannot be discriminated by introspection alone.

If Hannah grants the indistinguishability intuition, she should also grant that the veridicality of her experience lies beyond the way things seem to her. From a phenomenological perspective, it is an incidental fact about her experience that it is veridical.

This point can be generalized to cases in which a subject's perceptual and cognitive capacities are not working properly.

indistinguishability intuition*. There can be cases in which a subject's perceptual and cognitive capacities are not working properly and yet they cannot be discriminated by introspection alone from cases in which a subject's perceptual and cognitive capacities are working properly.

If Hannah grants the indistinguishability intuition*, she should also grant that the proper functioning of her perceptual and cognitive capacities lies beyond the way things seem to her. From a phenomenological perspective, it is an incidental fact about her own case that her perceptual and cognitive capacities are working properly.

Given the two indistinguishability intuitions, there is nothing in Hannah's tacit knowledge of what it takes to be in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge that would enable her to know, by reflection, that she is in an objectively good case. Without that additional piece of knowledge, Hannah cannot solve the conditionality problem.

Objection 3. It might be objected that Hannah's reasoning has been too hasty. As McDowell (Reference McDowell1995, Reference McDowell2002, Reference McDowell, Haddock and Macpherson2008, Reference McDowell2011, Reference McDowell2013, Reference McDowell, Doyle, Milburn and Pritchard2019) has forcefully argued, indistinguishability intuitions register the fact that we are fallible. In other words, they register the fact that it is possible to be misled into thinking that one sees that p when one does not genuinely see that p. However, it does not follow from this familiar fact that, in cases where Hannah has no reason for thinking that she is being misled, she cannot have reflective knowledge that she sees that p. Thus, it is simply not true that, given the prior indistinguishability intuitions, Hannah's being in a paradigmatic case of perceptual knowledge lies beyond the way things seem to her.Footnote 11

Reply. There is an important insight in this remark: indistinguishability intuitions are consistent with a subject's possession of reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. However, we would need to go beyond this plausible observation to solve the conditionality problem. We would need to assume that the consistency between the two claims (fallibility and the possession of reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge) is sufficient for a reflective subject like Hannah to rationally claim that she sees that p. This is not obviously true, given Step 2 of the argument: “Dismissing a hypothesis that casts doubt on Hannah's possession of a perceptual reason by citing the same perceptual reason would be like trying to justify the reliability of the testimony of an eyewitness by asking the eyewitness whether she is telling the truth. These considerations lead Hannah to conclude that she may not avail herself of a factive perceptual reason to rationally dismiss the BIV hypothesis.” If we factor in this observation, we have a situation in which two incompatible propositions are on an equal footing: [I see that there are asparagus in the stand] and [I merely seem to see that there are asparagus in the stand]. Of course, it does not follow from Hannah's fallibility that she merely seems to see that p. However, it does not follow that she genuinely sees that p either. At this stage of the game, the rational attitude would be agnosticism.

Objection 4. The previous reply underestimates the resources available to ED. Defenders of ED have not merely identified an invalid argument from fallibility to the claim that subjects lack perceptual reasons that are both factive and reflectively accessible. They have also argued that, in the absence of reasons to think the contrary, it is rational for Hannah to believe that she sees that there are asparagus in the stand. Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2012, Reference Pritchard2016) has developed this line of argument on behalf of the Austinian distinction between ‘merely raised’ and ‘rationally motivated error possibilities’. On Pritchard's view, a subject can rationally dismiss an error possibility in two different ways. If the error possibility is rationally motivated, the subject should provide independent reasons that speak to the reasons offered in support of the error possibility. If the error possibility is not rationally motivated (but it is ‘merely raised’), it is rational for the subject to ignore the error possibility. Think of hypotheses formulated ‘on a whim’. It seems wrong to expect someone to provide independent reasons to dismiss whimsical hypotheses.

Pritchard thinks that this distinction can be used to rationally dismiss radical skeptical hypotheses (see also McDowell Reference McDowell2014: 319–20). On Pritchard's view, radical skeptical hypotheses are never rationally motivated. He reasons as follows. Radical skeptical hypotheses call into question all our empirical grounds. So, there can be no empirical considerations that speak in favor of radical skeptical hypotheses. If one assumes that the only way of rationally motivating a radical skeptical hypothesis is to cite empirical grounds, it follows that radical skeptical hypotheses are never rationally motivated.Footnote 12 So, we may ignore radical skeptical hypotheses without being required to introduce independent considerations that speak against them:

[I]f this just means the mere presentation of a not-p possibility, then there is nothing inherently suspect about the idea that our agent can continue to cite the factive rational support she has for the target proposition, and hence regard this error possibility as excluded. Effectively, she is treating this particular evidence for not-p as misleading (though ‘evidence’ is not quite the right word, given that the error possibility isn't rationally motivated). (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016: 211, footnote 19; see also his 2012: 125–9)

Reply. Let us concede that there is a sense in which it is rational to set aside merely raised error possibilities. Let us also grant that radical skeptical hypotheses are never rationally motivated. However, the key question is whether this move is sufficient to solve the conditionality problem. In my view, the distinction between ‘merely raised’ and ‘rationally motivated error possibilities’ cannot solve the conditionality problem. To see why, let us consider the following self-ascription transition:

self-ascription transition (V)

Premise 1. If I believe p and I recognize a hypothesis h both as incompatible with p and as a hypothesis that is never rationally motivated, then I may believe p.

Premise 2. I believe that I see that there are asparagus in the stand.

Premise 3. I recognize the BIV hypothesis both as incompatible with my seeing that there are asparagus in the stand and as a hypothesis that is never rationally motivated.

Conclusion. So, I may believe that I see that there are asparagus in the stand.

This self-ascription bypasses the relativity of ED to paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge by relying on the rationality of ignoring hypotheses that are not rationally motivated and the claim that the BIV is never rationally motivated. Unfortunately, Premise 1 is too weak to solve the conditionality problem.

Let us grant that, in everyday conversations, it is legitimate to set aside error possibilities that are not rationally motivated. Nevertheless, this concession is insufficient to solve the conditionality problem. To solve this problem, Hannah needs an epistemic reason to believe that she is in an objectively good case. Roughly, an epistemic reason in favor of p is a reason that speaks to the truth of p. Nevertheless, the fact that the BIV hypothesis is never rationally motivated neither speaks to the truth of her being in an objectively good case, nor to the falsity of the BIV hypothesis. In objectively good cases, the subject can reliably form perceptual beliefs and her cognitive and perceptual capacities are functioning properly. The fact that the BIV hypothesis is never rationally motivated speaks neither to the reliability of Hannah's perceptual belief-forming mechanisms nor to the proper functioning of Hannah's cognitive and perceptual capacities. To paraphrase Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2016: 40), the fact that a hypothesis has been merely raised seems to be “completely indifferent to whether or not we are the victims of a radical skeptical scenario”. Imagine that Hannah is a BIV. At some point, she has an experience as of someone who tells her, ‘You are a BIV’. Suppose now that Hannah realizes that there is no way in which this hypothesis could be rationally motivated. So, it might be rational for Hannah to set aside the BIV hypothesis. Nevertheless, Hannah still lacks epistemic reasons that speak to the truth of her being in an objectively good case and the falsity of the BIV hypothesis. For all Hannah knows, she might be living an envatted existence.Footnote 13

6. A diagnosis

I have argued that ED cannot solve the conditionality problem. In this section, I submit that the conditionality problem is parasitic on a controversial methodological requirement. After that, I suggest that ED need not meet that requirement. Therefore, it is possible to put ED in the service of a more modest anti-skeptical strategy.Footnote 14

Stroud thinks that the conditionality problem originates from a requirement of the traditional epistemological project:

generality requirement. The theory of knowledge should explain all our knowledge of the world at once.Footnote 15

In the project of ‘pure inquiry’, the inquirer sets aside all her interests and attachments to examine all her knowledge at once (Williams Reference Williams1978, Reference Williams1991: 6, 26, 193; Stroud Reference Stroud1984). The generality requirement entails that the pure inquirer should set aside all her knowledge of the world; she should see herself at the outset as “not knowing anything about the external world” (Stroud Reference Stroud1989: 120; see also Stroud Reference Stroud1984: 209, 223; Williams Reference Williams1991: 193). This creates a problem, though. If the inquirer sets aside all her knowledge of the world, a successful explanation of knowledge of the world should restitute the subject's ability to self-ascribe knowledge of the world. To perform this self-ascription, however, the subject must determine that all the conditions for knowledge are satisfied. Alas, some of these conditions involve worldly facts. Thus, the satisfaction of all the conditions for knowledge can only be ascertained by relying on some knowledge of the world. This leads to a dilemma: either we must embrace skepticism, or we must give up on the project of offering a fully general explanation of our knowledge.

Many philosophers have noted that the conditionality problem imposes very demanding epistemological requirements (Sosa Reference Sosa1994, Reference Sosa, Coppenger and Bergmann2016; Greco Reference Greco2000; Bergmann Reference Bergmann and Greco2008; Echeverri Reference EcheverriMs a). In my view, they are right to think so. However, very few philosophers have realized that, when a reflective subject tries to rationally dismiss a radical skeptical hypothesis, she is tacitly subject to the generality requirement.Footnote 16 A radical skeptical hypothesis casts doubt on all our empirical grounds. So, when the reflective subject tries to rationally dismiss a radical skeptical hypothesis, she finds herself in the same situation as someone who must restitute her knowledge of the world without illicitly relying on any knowledge of the world. This raises the question of whether there is any way of rejecting the generality requirement without giving up on the project of providing an adequate treatment of skepticism.

Since I have discussed this issue elsewhere (Echeverri Reference EcheverriMs a), I will only draw a moral for our current discussion. The way ED entered the philosophical scene seems to be at odds with the project of pure inquiry and its correlative idea of facing skepticism ‘head on’. Rather than embracing the generality requirement, ED is best seen as starting from the commonsense assumption that subjects often are, or can be, in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. From this perspective, the philosophical task is not to provide an account of perceptual knowledge that confers on us the ability to rationally claim perceptual knowledge in response to skeptical challenges, but to preserve the central role of reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons in our everyday practices. In this vein, ED can be put in the service of undercutting putative skeptical paradoxes. Given that putative skeptical paradoxes are not challenges one must meet by rationally claiming perceptual knowledge, the two tasks are potentially dissociable.

7. Underdetermination-based skepticism

Pritchard has offered an illuminating contrast between two ways of understanding the skeptical problem. On one interpretation, radical skepticism is a position. On this view, there is a (possible or actual) skeptic who takes on several commitments such as ‘knowledge is impossible’. On another interpretation, radical skepticism is a putative paradox that arises from a set of claims that strike us as individually true, but which (seem to) entail that knowledge of the external world is not possible (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012, Reference Pritchard2016; see also Stroud Reference Stroud1984; Wright Reference Wright1985; Williams Reference Williams1991, Reference Williams2001; Byrne Reference Byrne2004). This second view depicts “[t]he dispute with the ‘skeptic’ [as] a quarrel that is completely internal to our conceptual realm” (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016: 161).

If skepticism is construed as a position, it may seem reasonable to expect a theory of perceptual knowledge to secure our ability to rationally make perceptual knowledge claims in response to skeptical challenges. After all, knowledge claims are intended for an audience, even if that audience turns out to be the skeptic in you. If skepticism is construed as a putative paradox, however, our ability to rationally make perceptual knowledge claims seems irrelevant.

There are two main ways of solving a putative paradox. An overriding strategy grants that radical skepticism is a bona fide paradox, for “it arises out of our most fundamental epistemological commitments” (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016: 161). Therefore, an anti-skeptic project should provide independent arguments to revise (some of) the pre-theoretical commitments that generate the paradox (see also Wright Reference Wright1985; Greco Reference Greco2000: 3). By contrast, the undercutting strategy denies that the putative skeptical paradox is a genuine paradox. It holds that radical skepticism “smuggles contentious theoretical claims into the set-up of the skeptical argument, disguised as common sense” (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016: 172; see also Clarke Reference Clarke1972; Williams Reference Williams1991, Reference Williams2001).

Imagine that you opt for an overriding strategy. It suffices to rationally motivate a revision of (some of) the pre-theoretical commitments that generate the paradox. These commitments can have the form of general principles that we tacitly rely on when we assess knowledge claims in everyday practices. Alternatively, suppose that you choose the undercutting strategy. In this case, it seems sufficient to display the theoretical character of the putative paradox. In doing so, you do not need to take the extra step of securing the capacity to rationally make perceptual knowledge claims in response to skeptical challenges.

Of course, one's verdict on a putative skeptical paradox will depend on how exactly one understands it. ED has been used to block the closure-based skeptical paradox (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012) and the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016). Pritchard's considered view is that ED is best suited to block the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox. Therefore, I will focus on this putative paradox. To this end, I will present Pritchard's account of the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox (section 7.1), sketch a modest solution to it (section 7.2), show that this modest solution is available to some forms of externalism (section 7.3), and suggest that this modest solution undercuts the putative paradox (section 7.4).Footnote 17

7.1. The underdetermination-based skeptical paradox

The underdetermination-based skeptical paradox is the conjunction of three claims:

underdetermination-based skeptical paradox

U1. One cannot have reflectively accessible reasons that favor one's belief in an everyday proposition over an incompatible radical skeptical hypothesis.

U2. If one cannot have reflectively accessible reasons that favor one's belief in an everyday proposition over an incompatible radical skeptical hypothesis, then one does not have widespread everyday knowledge based on reflectively accessible reasons.

U3. One has widespread everyday knowledge based on reflectively accessible reasons.

U1–U3 form an inconsistent triad. An undercutting solution must reject at least one of the three claims without revising any of our pre-theoretical commitments. Otherwise, we are led to advocate an overriding solution. Pritchard thinks that externalists are committed to offering an overriding solution.

Consider a radical externalist. Our radical externalist holds that the satisfaction of an external condition on knowledge (reliability, safety, sensitivity, and so on) is necessary and sufficient for knowledge. Our radical externalist is committed to the truth of U1, for there is nothing in her theory that licenses the claim that one can have reflectively accessible reasons that favor one's belief in an everyday proposition over an incompatible radical skeptical hypothesis.Footnote 18 This creates a problem. If one cannot have reflectively accessible reasons that favor one's belief in an everyday proposition over an incompatible radical skeptical hypothesis, and U2 is true, then U3 is false: It is not the case that one has widespread everyday knowledge based on reflectively accessible reasons. But this leads us to a troubling form of skepticism. The conjunction of U1 and U2 leads us to assimilate all our perceptual knowledge to the knowledge possessed by the chicken sexers (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016: 35–6; see also Pritchard Reference Pritchard2005: 115, 206). This result conflicts with our pre-theoretical epistemic commitments. As we have seen, it is very natural to hold that there is an epistemic asymmetry between the proverbial chicken sexers and their enlightened counterparts (section 2).

Another option would be to reject U2. However, Pritchard thinks that U2 relies on a very intuitive principle:

underdetermination. If S knows that p and q are incompatible propositions, and yet S lacks reflectively accessible reasons that favor p over q, then S lacks knowledge of p based on reflectively accessible reasons.Footnote 19

Suppose that Hannah knows that the proposition [There are asparagus in the stand] is incompatible with the proposition [There are leeks in the stand] (Let us assume that there is a single type of vegetable in the stand). Suppose that Hannah lacks reflectively accessible reasons that favor [There are asparagus in the stand] over [There are leeks in the stand]. Therefore, it seems highly intuitive that Hannah lacks knowledge of [There are asparagus in the stand] based on reflectively accessible reasons. It is hard to find anything objectionable in this inferential pattern.

Pritchard thinks that internalist accessibilism faces similar problems. Assuming that he is right to think so, the only way of undercutting the putative paradox is to reject U1: It is not the case that one cannot have reflectively accessible reasons that favor one's belief in an everyday proposition over an incompatible radical skeptical hypothesis. A good way of rejecting U1 is to identify a principle underlying it. Pritchard suggests that U1 relies on the insularity of reasons thesis:

insularity of reasons. The reasons we have reflective access to in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge are compatible with their widespread falsity (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016: 3, 55–6, 172).

If we reject insularity of reasons, we can reject U1 while endorsing U2 and U3. Happily, ED offers us the materials to reject insularity of reasons. Assume that Hannah can be in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. Given ED, Hannah can have reflectively accessible reasons that favor the everyday proposition [There are asparagus in the stand] over an incompatible radical skeptical hypothesis like [I am a BIV]. Having rejected U1, we can keep U2 and U3 without contradiction. Thus, we can avoid the counterintuitive result of assimilating all our perceptual knowledge to the knowledge possessed by the proverbial chicken sexers.

7.2. Modest ED

ED's denial of U1 relies on a key assumption: Hannah can be in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. To solve the conditionality problem, a reflective subject should be able to discharge this assumption. Let us define ‘ambitious ED’ as the view that uses ED to discharge this assumption. Interestingly, we do not need to discharge this assumption if we are pursuing the more modest goal of solving a putative paradox. This follows from our definition of a putative paradox. One can successfully solve a putative paradox if one manages to sketch a theory of knowledge that eliminates the contradiction generated by a set of claims. One can successfully undercut a putative paradox if one can show that the resulting view coheres with one's pre-theoretical commitments. Crucially, one can sketch an account of perceptual knowledge that coheres with one's pre-theoretical epistemic commitments even though one cannot vindicate those commitments in response to a skeptical challenge. What did the work in the prior solution was the denial of insularity of reasons. But what justifies this denial? McDowell (Reference McDowell2002: 98) and Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2012: 17, Reference Pritchard2016: 134) have argued that insularity of reasons is at odds with our pre-theoretical epistemic commitments. They have pointed out that ED captures the practice of citing factive perceptual reasons in everyday life. They have also insisted that it is very unusual to cite non-factive perceptual reasons in everyday practices.Footnote 20

Here is another way of looking at the dialectic. Ambitious ED holds that a reflective subject can solve the conditionality problem when she recognizes a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with her everyday beliefs. Suppose now that the conditionality problem has no solution. Thus, ambitious ED is not available. Modest ED holds, by contrast, that a reflective subject cannot solve the conditionality problem when she recognizes a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with her everyday beliefs. After all, radical skeptical hypotheses reveal the conditional character of S's reflectively accessible reasons and there is nothing in ED that would enable a reflective subject to detach the antecedent of ED. Given that the theoretical work was done by ED's denial of insularity of reasons because it deviates from our pre-theoretical epistemic commitments, the proposed solution is orthogonal to the debate between ambitious ED and modest ED. insularity of reasons is a synchronic claim about the limited strength of the perceptual reasons that are reflectively accessible in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. All we can get from ED is the denial of this synchronic claim. However, the contrast between ambitious and modest ED concerns the diachronic question of whether a reflective subject can solve the conditionality problem after she recognizes a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with her everyday beliefs.

Does modest ED lead to first-order skepticism? The answer to this question will depend on one's further commitments about knowledge. If there can be non-luminous knowledge (Williamson Reference Williamson2000; Lasonen-Aarnio Reference Lasonen-Aarnio2010), a subject who recognizes a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with her everyday belief might retain a more primitive, non-luminous perceptual knowledge of the world. If one denies the existence of non-luminous knowledge, the proposed analysis will lead to a diachronic form of first-order skepticism.Footnote 21

7.3. Modest ED and externalism

Radical externalists are compelled to grant U1. Nevertheless, not all externalists are radical. We have already introduced a weaker form of externalism according to which externalist conditions on knowledge might be necessary and sufficient for knowledge when skeptical hypotheses are ‘live’. Other externalists could try to offer externalist accounts of perceptual reasons that are both factive and reflectively accessible (Greco Reference Greco2014). For example, a subject can know p in virtue of seeing that p, which is both factive and reflectively accessible. Crucially, her reflective knowledge that she sees that p could be explained in virtue of the obtaining of some external condition (reliability, safety, sensitivity, and so on). This type of externalism could mimic modest ED's solution to the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox. Our discussion suggests, however, a stronger, externalist claim. The reason why the conditionality problem has no solution is that all our knowledge is ultimately externalist knowledge. When we go all the way down to vindicate all our perceptual knowledge at once, we reach a type of explanation that traces knowing to the obtaining of some external conditions. When the reflective subject faces the skeptical problem ‘head on’, she lacks epistemic reasons that speak to the truth of her seeing that p because her seeing that p is ultimately grounded in the obtaining of some external condition. Yet, this is consistent with a subject's possession of reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge and her retention of a more primitive first-order perceptual knowledge when skeptical hypotheses are ‘live’.

7.4. Overriding vs. undercutting

Recall Pritchard's distinction between overriding and undercutting strategies. He seems to think that ambitious ED undercuts the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox. I beg to disagree. Ambitious ED conceals an overriding component. Indeed, modest ED is in a better position than ambitious ED to genuinely undercut the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox.

A way of determining whether a theory of knowledge reflects our pre-theoretical epistemic commitments is to ask whether it articulates the principles at work in our everyday epistemic practices. ED tells us that, in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge, a subject, S, has perceptual knowledge that p in virtue of being in possession of reasons for her belief that p which are both factive and reflectively accessible to S (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 13). This claim gains support from the role of factive perceptual reasons in everyday exchanges of reasons. However, ambitious ED goes beyond this simple observation. Ambitious ED requires that a subject can avail herself of her reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons when she becomes aware of a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with her everyday beliefs. Everyday practices do not support this stronger claim. While it may seem natural to cite a factive perceptual reason when radical skeptical hypotheses have been bracketed, it is extremely unnatural to do so when radical skeptical hypotheses are ‘live’. Indeed, it requires a lot of reasoning to make the view palatable. So, ambitious ED is the result of theoretical reasoning that is presented as common sense. Pace Pritchard, ambitious ED is an overriding strategy.Footnote 22

If modest ED can capture our pre-theoretical epistemic commitments better than ambitious ED, why is it so tempting to prefer ambitious ED over modest ED? Defenders of ED are reluctant to assimilate all our perceptual knowledge to the knowledge possessed by the proverbial chicken sexers. There is, however, an ambiguity in U3: One has widespread everyday knowledge based on reflectively accessible reasons. On a modest reading, the epistemic position of the enlightened chicken sexers is relatively better than the epistemic position of the proverbial chicken sexers. Any epistemological theory that blurs the relative epistemic asymmetry between the two groups of subjects would be inadequate. On an immodest reading, preserving this relative epistemic asymmetry is not enough. It is also necessary to show that the reasons available to the enlightened chicken sexers are so sound that they remain available when they recognize a radical skeptical hypothesis as incompatible with their everyday beliefs. Pritchard seems to flirt with this immodest reading when he describes the (radical) externalist as embracing the counterintuitive “claim that our (perceptual) knowledge is in its nature lacking in rational support” (2016: 35–6). This claim misleadingly prejudges the case against any externalist outlook. The insolvability of the conditionality problem suggests that, even if there is a relative epistemic asymmetry between the proverbial chicken sexers and their enlightened counterparts, our knowledge is ultimately externalist knowledge. So, in a sense, all our knowledge is in its nature ultimately lacking in rational support.

Some might find this conclusion disquieting. However, our unease with a solution need not reveal its failure to capture our pre-theoretical epistemic commitments. Some disquieting conclusions could reveal overlooked aspects of our natural condition. A young child is oblivious to the unavoidability of death. Growing up will inevitably face her with this fundamental aspect of life. This realization might be a cause of long-lasting anxiety, even if our child had no prior epistemic commitment to being immortal. Something similar might be at work in radical skepticism. Not all disquieting revelations contradict our pre-theoretical epistemic commitments. Some disquieting revelations can help us sharpen the relatively vague contours of common sense. If skepticism is a putative paradox, one can eliminate the tension in our conceptual framework and remain anxious with the result. The remaining anxiety can arise from the realization that we cannot occupy an unconditioned epistemic position. Learning to live with this realization is part and parcel of growing up.

8. Conclusion

Epistemological disjunctivism (ED) has been thought to offer a way out of the conditionality problem for epistemic externalism. I have shown that ED's account of reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons is key to ED's attempt at solving that problem. I have also argued that ED's conception of reflective access faces a version of the conditionality problem. Given that this problem prevents a reflective subject from self-ascribing first-order knowledge of external world propositions, ED's attempt at solving the conditionality problem fails. Fortunately, the conditionality problem arises from a generality requirement that is potentially dissociable from ED. This makes room for a modest understanding of ED's anti-skeptical project that can survive the realization that the conditionality problem has no solution. ED can help us undercut the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox by enabling us to reject the insularity of reasons thesis on behalf of our pre-theoretical commitment to our possession, in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge, of perceptual reasons that are both factive and reflectively accessible. Unfortunately, this modest ED offers no substantial advantages over all forms of externalism. Indeed, a moderate externalism provides a good framework to explain the anti-skeptical limitations of our reliance on reflectively accessible factive perceptual reasons.Footnote 23, Footnote 24

Footnotes

2 I refer to ‘knowledge internalism’ and ‘knowledge externalism’ as ‘internalism’ and ‘externalism’ respectively.

3 By ‘radical skepticism’ I mean a family of paradoxes that cast doubt on our perceptual knowledge of everyday propositions about the external world. I examine the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox in section 7. I often abbreviate ‘radical skepticism’ to ‘skepticism’.

4 Recent discussions of the anti-skeptical scope of ED include Neta (Reference Neta, Haddock and Mapherson2008, Reference Neta2016), Ashton (Reference Ashton2015), Zalabardo (Reference Zalabardo2015), Lockhart (Reference Lockhart2018), Stuchlik (Reference Stuchlik2020), Coliva (Reference Coliva2021), and some of the essays in Doyle et al. (Reference Doyle, Milburn and Pritchard2019). Our discussion differs from previous ones in its focus on the conditionality problem.

5 See also McDowell (Reference McDowell2011: 21, 35, Reference McDowell2019: 33). For similar formulations of accessibilism, see Sosa (Reference Sosa1994: 273), Zagzebski (Reference Zagzebski1996: 31), Greco (Reference Greco2000: 181), and Steup (Reference Steup, Machuca and Reed2018: 597). Hereafter, I leave out mentalist internalism. The locus classicus of mentalism is Conee and Feldman (Reference Conee and Feldman2004).

6 For alternative reconstructions of the conditionality problem, see Pritchard and Ranalli (Reference Pritchard, Ranalli, Coppenger and Bergmann2016) and Fernández-Vargas (Reference Fernández-Vargas2020), and various essays in Coppenger and Bergmann (Reference Coppenger and Bergmann2016).

7 As a referee has pointed out, this formulation would create a problem for any theory that denies that we have reflective access to empirical propositions. Nevertheless, few philosophers would grant that we have reflective access to empirical propositions. Does this observation invalidate my reconstruction of the conditionality problem? I do not think so. First, I have argued elsewhere (Echeverri Reference EcheverriMs a) that the formulation of the conditionality problem that features in the main text can be derived from the requirements of Cartesian inquiry, which play a key role in Stroud's (Reference Stroud1989, Reference Stroud1994, Reference Stroud and Greco2004) seminal discussion. In section 6, I identify one of those methodological requirements. Second, defenders of ED are committed to our possession of reflective access to empirical propositions. After all, they hold that a subject can have reflective access to her seeing that p. Notably, both [S sees that p] and [p] are empirical propositions. Pritchard's discussion of the so-called access problem for ED is meant to make this idea plausible. The access problem is a version of McKinsey's problem for externalist theories of content. Externalist theories of content have been thought to entail that a subject can have fully a priori knowledge of external world propositions, which is absurd. Pritchard has tried to show that a McKinsey-style problem does not arise for ED. His strategy is to show that reflective knowledge of factive perceptual reasons does not require that the relevant knowledge is fully a priori (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 19–20, 46–52). Rödl (Reference Rödl2007), McDowell (Reference McDowell, Haddock and Macpherson2008, Reference McDowell2011, Reference McDowell, Doyle, Milburn and Pritchard2019), and Kern (Reference Kern2017) have argued in turn that the perceptual knowledge enjoyed by adult humans is grounded in one and the same capacity as their capacity for self-knowledge. If this view is true, then a subject who perceptually knows p will automatically have the capacity to reflectively know empirical propositions like [I see that p] and [p].

8 McDowell (Reference McDowell, Haddock and Macpherson2008: 379) has granted that citing one's seeing that p in an anti-skeptical argument would ‘beg the question’. Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2012, Reference Pritchard2016) relies on the Austinian distinction between ‘merely raised’ and ‘rationally motivated’ error possibilities to justify one's right to cite one's seeing that p when one becomes aware of a radical skeptical hypothesis (Austin Reference Austin1946). Still, a subject must first recognize an error possibility as being merely raised before she can avail herself of her seeing that p to dismiss it. I examine the Austinian move in section 5.

9 For related accounts of paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge, see Kern (Reference Kern2017: 202–3, 216), McDowell (Reference McDowell2011: 13), and Rödl (Reference Rödl2007: Ch. 5). In section 5, I discuss a subjective condition on paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge.

10 The qualification ‘some forms of externalism’ will become important when we assess the merits of externalist treatments of the underdetermination-based skeptical paradox (section 7).

11 I owe this objection to a referee for this journal.

12 I have argued that radical skeptical hypotheses can be rationally motivated via conceivability arguments (Echeverri Reference Echeverri2017). I have shown, however, that those conceivability arguments ultimately rely on unjustified suppositions. So, my analysis is consistent with Pritchard's overall verdict.

13 This line of argument parallels Stroud's (Reference Stroud1984: Ch. 2) critique of Austin's reliance on intuitions about the propriety and impropriety of challenges to knowledge claims in everyday contexts as an anti-skeptical strategy. In Echeverri (Reference EcheverriMs b), I argue that the main attempts at meeting Stroud's challenge are at odds with a conception of epistemic responsibility as being governed by the aim of truth.

14 For reasons of space, I will only focus on a methodological requirement that guides Stroud's formulation of the conditionality problem. Fumerton (Reference Fumerton, Roth and Ross1990, Reference Fumerton1995, Reference Fumerton, Crisp, Davidson and Laan2006) is another proponent of the conditionality problem. For discussion of Fumerton's view, see the essays in Coppenger and Bergmann (Reference Coppenger and Bergmann2016).

15 Williams (Reference Williams1991: 22ff.) calls it the ‘totality condition’.

16 Williams (Reference Williams2001) is an exception.

17 For reasons of space, I will skip many details of Pritchard's rich discussion. I will also reformulate some of his principles in my own terminology.

18 I examine weaker forms of externalism in section 7.3.

19 See Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2016: 34). Pritchard's formulation of underdetermination appeals to the concept of ‘rational support’. He takes rational support to be equivalent to the epistemic support provided by reflectively accessible reasons (40, 192 n 15). I have amended the principle accordingly.

20 Whether those are the only relevant intuitions is moot, as the debate on the new evil demon problem illustrates.

21 Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2016: 36) suggests that it would be revisionary to hold that adult human perceptual knowledge “does not entail” the possession of reflectively accessible reasons. This view would inevitably lead to first-order skepticism. Pritchard (Reference Pritchard, Doyle, Milburn and Pritchard2019) makes room for perceptual knowledge outside of paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge. This type of view could be reconciled with the existence of primitive, non-luminous perceptual knowledge. In Echeverri (Reference EcheverriMs c), I suggest that Pritchard's move faces some serious problems and sketch a different amendment to ED.

22 In previous work, Pritchard was acutely aware of this point. He writes: “One of the key points in favor of McDowell's claim that reasons can be factive is the linguistic evidence that, outside of ‘philosophical’ conversational contexts at any rate, we do indeed adduce factive reasons in favor of our beliefs” (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2005: 234; emphasis mine). He also suggests that offering factive reasons in favor of one's perceptual beliefs in skeptical contexts would be problematic: “whilst it is clearly sometimes acceptable to offer factive reasons in favor of one's beliefs, there are also cases where offering such factive reasons would be problematic. The obvious example in this respect is the skeptical case, where one is asked to support one's claims in a conversational context where the truth or otherwise of skepticism is at issue” (235). Later, he insists that it is “in accordance with intuition” that factive perceptual reasons cannot be transferred to philosophical contexts (238). It would take us too far afield to examine the reasons why Pritchard changed his mind on this issue. My point is that this change of mind transforms ambitious ED into an overriding strategy.

23 Another framework might be provided by Wittgenstein's (Reference Wittgenstein, Anscombe and von Wright1969) hinge epistemology. My remarks on the project of pure inquiry bear interesting relations to what Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2016) calls the universality of rational evaluation thesis. My view is that much of the work played by so-called ‘hinge commitments’ can be played by externalist conditions on knowledge. I also think that my arguments should lead us to revise the way Pritchard sees the division of anti-skeptical labor between ED and a hinge epistemology. But these are complex issues that should be left for another occasion.

24 I am grateful to Miguel Ángel Fernández, Chuck Goldhaber, and two anonymous referees from this journal for their insightful comments on previous drafts of this paper. Work on this project was funded by a grant from UNAM-PAPIIT IN 400621: “Alcances y límites del externismo epistémico”.

References

Ahlstrom-Vij, K. (2011). ‘Dream Skepticism and the Conditionality Problem.’ Erkenntnis 75(1), 4560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashton, N.A. (2015). ‘Undercutting Underdetermination-Based Scepticism.’ Theoria 81(4), 333–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. (1946). ‘Other Minds.’ In Philosophical Papers, pp. 76116. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bergmann, M. (2008). ‘Externalist Responses to Skepticism.’ In Greco, J. (ed.), Oxford Handbook to Skepticism, pp. 504–38. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (1998). ‘Insights and Blindspots of Reliabilism.’ The Monist 81(3), 371–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, A. (2004). ‘How Hard are the Sceptical Paradoxes?Noûs 38, 299325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, T. (1972). ‘The Legacy of Skepticism.’ Journal of Philosophy 64, 754–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. (1999). ‘Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons.’ Philosophical Perspectives 13, 5789.Google Scholar
Coliva, A. (2021). ‘Strange Bedfellows: On Pritchard's Disjunctivist Hinge Epistemology.’ Synthese 198(Suppl. 15), 3521–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, E. and Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coppenger, B. and Bergmann, M. (eds) (2016). Intellectual Assurance: Essays on Traditional Epistemic Internalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cunningham, J. (2016). ‘Reflective Epistemological Disjunctivism.’ Episteme 13(1), 111–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doyle, C., Milburn, J. and Pritchard, D. (eds) (2019). New Issues in Epistemological Disjunctivism. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Echeverri, S. (2017). ‘How to Undercut Radical Skepticism.’ Philosophical Studies 174(5), 1299–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Echeverri, S. (Ms a). Inquiry and Skepticism.Google Scholar
Echeverri, S. (Ms b). Error Possibilities and the Social Division of Epistemic Labor.Google Scholar
Echeverri, S. (Ms c). Searching for the Epistemological Holy Grail.Google Scholar
Fernández-Vargas, M.-A. (2020). ‘The ‘Conditional Position Problem’ for Epistemic Externalism.’ Synthese 197(12), 5203–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foley, R. (1987). A Theory of Epistemic Rationality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fratantonio, G. (Forthcoming). ‘Reflective Access, Closure, and Epistemological Disjunctivism.’ Episteme.Google Scholar
Fumerton, R. (1990). ‘Metaepistemology and Skepticism.’ In Roth, M.D. and Ross, G. (eds), Doubting: Contemporary Perspectives on Skepticism, pp. 5768. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Fumerton, R. (2006). ‘Epistemic Internalism, Philosophical Assurance and the Skeptical Predicament.’ In Crisp, T.M., Davidson, M. and Laan, D.V. (eds), Knowledge and Reality: Essays in Honor of Alvin Plantinga, pp. 179–91. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giananti, A. (Forthcoming). ‘I Know How I Know: Perception, Self-Awareness, Self-Knowledge.’ Synthese.Google Scholar
Greco, J. (2000). Putting Skeptics in Their Place: The Nature of Skeptical Arguments and Their Role in Philosophical Inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, J. (2014). ‘Pritchard's Epistemological Disjunctivism: How Right? How Radical? How Satisfying?Philosophical Quarterly 64(254), 115–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kern, A. (2017). Sources of Knowledge: On the Concept of a Rational Capacity for Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lasonen-Aarnio, M.L. (2010). ‘Unreasonable Knowledge.’ Philosophical Perspectives 24(1), 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lockhart, T. (2018). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism and the Random Demon Hypothesis.’ International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 8(1), 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (1982). ‘Criteria, Defeasibility, and Knowledge.’ Proceedings of the British Academy 68, 455–79. Reprinted in Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality, pp. 369–94. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1995). ‘Knowledge and the Internal.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55(4), 877–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2002). ‘Knowledge and the Internal Revisited.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64(1), 97105. Reprinted in The Engaged Intellect, pp. 278–87. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (2008). ‘The Disjunctive Conception of Experience as Material for a Transcendental Argument.’ In Haddock, A. and Macpherson, F. (eds) Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, pp. 376–89. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2010). ‘Tyler Burge on Disjunctivism.’ Philosophical Explorations 13(3), 243–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2011). Perception as a Capacity for Knowledge. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (2013). ‘Tyler Burge on Disjunctivism (II).’ Philosophical Explorations 16(3), 259–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2014). ‘A Note on the Significance of Surface Inquiry.’ International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 4, 317–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2019). ‘Perceptual Experience and Empirical Rationality.’ In Doyle, C., Milburn, J. and Pritchard, D. (eds), New Issues in Epistemological Disjunctivism, pp. 3140. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neta, R. (2008). ‘In Defense of Disjunctivism.’ In Haddock, A. and Mapherson, F. (eds), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, pp. 311–29. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neta, R. (2016). ‘How Holy is the Disjunctivist Grail?Journal of Philosophical Research 41, 193200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2012). Epistemological Disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2016). Epistemic Angst: Radical Scepticism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2019). Epistemological Disjunctivism and Anti-Luck Virtue Epistemology. In Doyle, C., Milburn, J. and Pritchard, D. (eds), New Issues in Epistemological Disjunctivism, pp. 4157. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. and Ranalli, C. (2016). ‘On Metaepistemological Scepticism.’ In Coppenger, B. and Bergmann, M. (eds), Intellectual Assurance: Essays on Traditional Epistemic Internalism, pp. 205–23. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rödl, S. (2007). Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (1994). ‘Philosophical Scepticism.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 68, 263–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2016). ‘How Our Knowledge Squares with Skeptical Intuitions Despite the Circle.’ In Coppenger, B. and Bergmann, M. (eds), Intellectual Assurance: Essays on Traditional Epistemic Internalism, pp. 224–35. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steup, M. (2018). ‘Skepticism and the Internalism-Externalism Debate.’ In Machuca, D. and Reed, B. (eds), Skepticism: From Antiquity to Present, pp. 592608. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. (1984). The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, B. (1989). ‘Understanding Human Knowledge in General.’ Reprinted in Understanding Human Knowledge, pp. 99121. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. (1994). ‘Scepticism, ‘Externalism’, and the Goal of Epistemology.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 68, 290307.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. (2004). ‘Perceptual Knowledge and Epistemological Satisfaction.’ In Greco, J. (ed.), Sosa and His Critics, pp. 165–73. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stuchlik, J. (2020). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism: Neo-Wittgensteinian and Moderate Neo-Moorean.’ Episteme 17(4), 438–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogel, J. (1990). ‘Are There Counterexamples to the Closure Principle?’ In Roth, M. and Ross, G. (eds), Doubting: Contemporary Perspectives on Skepticism, pp. 1327. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1978). Descartes: The Project of Pure Inquiry. New York, NY: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Williams, M. (1991). Unnatural Doubts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, M. (2001). Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On Certainty, ed. Anscombe, G.E.M. and von Wright, G.H.. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (1985). ‘Facts and Certainty.’ Proceedings of the British Academy 71, 429–72.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalabardo, J. (2015). ‘Epistemic Disjunctivism and the Evidential Problem.’ Analysis 75(4), 615–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar