Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T07:15:48.108Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Epistemic Dependence and Oppression: A Telling Relationship

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 October 2020

Ezgi Sertler*
Affiliation:
Butler University, Indianapolis, IN, USA
*
*Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]

Abstract

Epistemic dependence refers to our social mechanisms of reliance in practices of knowledge production. Epistemic oppression concerns persistent and unwarranted exclusions from those practices. This article examines the relationship between these two frameworks and demonstrates that attending to their relationship is a fruitful practice for applied epistemology. Paying attention to relations of epistemic dependence and how exclusive they are can help us track epistemically oppressive practices. In order to show this, I introduce a taxonomy of epistemic dependence (interpersonal – communal – structural). I argue that this particular taxonomy is useful for tracking epistemically oppressive practices in institutional contexts. This is because, first, the forms of epistemic dependence in this taxonomy yield, what I call, diagnostic questions. These are questions that help us track how relations of epistemic dependence could become exclusive and that thus help reveal epistemic oppression in institutional contexts. Second, the forms of epistemic dependence in the taxonomy are interrelated. Paying attention not just to each of three forms of epistemic dependence but also to the way in which they are interrelated is useful for illuminating epistemically oppressive practices. I conclude by demonstrating how the diagnostic questions can be used in analyses of concrete institutional practices in asylum law and higher education.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alcoff, L.M. (2007). ‘Epistemologies of Ignorance: Three Types.’ In Sullivan, S. and Tuana, N. (eds), Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, pp. 3957. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Alcoff, L.M. (2008). ‘How is Epistemology Political?’ In Bailey, A. and Cuomo, C. (eds), The Feminist Philosophy Reader, pp. 705–18. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Berenstain, N. 2016. ‘Epistemic Exploitation.Ergo 3(22), 569–90.Google Scholar
Broncano-Berrocal, F. and Vega-Encabo, J. (2019). ‘A Taxonomy of Types of Epistemic Dependence: Introduction to the Synthese Special Issue on Epistemic Dependence.Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-019-02233-6.Google Scholar
Code, L. (1991). What Can She Know? Feminist Theory and the Construction of Knowledge. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, L. (1993). ‘Taking Subjectivity into Account.’ In Alcoff, L. and Potter, E. (eds), Feminist Epistemologies, pp. 1548. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
P.H., Collins (2009) Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment, 2nd edition. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the State of Nature. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, A. (1998). The Angela Y. Davis Reader (edited by James, Joy). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
Davis, A. (2003). Are Prisons Obsolete? New York, NY: Seven Stories Press.Google Scholar
Davis, A. (2005). Abolition Democracy: Beyond Empire, Prisons, and Torture. New York, NY: Seven Stories Press.Google Scholar
DiAngelo, R. (2011). ‘White Fragility.’ International Journal of Critical Pedagogy 3(3), 5470.Google Scholar
Dotson, K. (2011). ‘Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing.’ Hypatia 26(2), 236–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, K. (2012). ‘A Cautionary Tale: On Limiting Epistemic Oppression.’ Frontiers: A Journal of Women's Studies 33(1), 2447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, K. (2014). ‘Conceptualizing Epistemic Oppression.’ Social Epistemology 28(2), 115–38.10.1080/02691728.2013.782585CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, K. (2017). ‘Theorizing Jane Crow, Theorizing Unknowability.’ Social Epistemology 31(5), 417–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, K. (2018). ‘Accumulating Epistemic Power: A Problem with Epistemology.’ Philosophical Topics 46(1), 129–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fatima, S. (2020). ‘I Know What Happened to Me: The Epistemic Harms of Microaggression.’ In Schroer, J.W. and Freeman, L. (eds), Microaggressions and Philosophy, pp. 163–83. New York, NY: Routledge.10.4324/9780429022470-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic Injustice: The Power and Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2010). Relying on Others: An Essay in Epistemology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199593248.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2011 a). ‘If That Were True: I Would Have Heard It by Now.’ In Goldman, A. and Whitcomb, D. (eds), Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, pp. 92108. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2011 b). ‘The Division of Epistemic Labor.’ Episteme 8(1), 112–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2013). ‘Epistemic Dependence in Testimonial Belief, in the Classroom and Beyond.’ Journal of Philosophy of Education 47(2), 168–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grasswick, H. (2004). ‘Individuals-in-Communities: The Search for a Feminist Model of Epistemic Subjects.Hypatia 19(3): 85120.10.1111/j.1527-2001.2004.tb01303.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haraway, D. (2004). ‘Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective.’ In Harding, S. (ed.), The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader: Intellectual and Political Controversies, pp. 81101. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Harding, S. (1991). Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? Thinking from Women's Lives. New York, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Harding, S. (1993). ‘Rethinking Standpoint Epistemology: ‘What is Strong Objectivity?’’ In Alcoff, L. and Potter, E. (eds), Feminist Epistemologies, pp. 4982. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hardwig, J. (1985). ‘Epistemic Dependence.’ Journal of Philosophy 82(7), 335–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, J. (1991). ‘The Role of Trust in Knowledge.’ Journal of Philosophy 88(12), 693708.10.2307/2027007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kukla, R. (2006). ‘Objectivity and Perspective in Empirical Knowledge.Episteme 3(1–2), 8095.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lugones, M. and Spelman, E. (1983). ‘Have We Got a Theory for You! Feminist Theory, Cultural Imperialism, and the Demand for the Woman's Voice.’ Women's Studies International Forum 6(6), 573581.10.1016/0277-5395(83)90019-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malewski, E. and Jaramillo, N. (2011). The Epistemologies of Ignorance in Education. Information Age Publishing Inc.Google Scholar
McDonald-Norman, D. (2017). ‘No One to Bear Witness: Country Information and LGBTQ Asylum Seekers.’ Refuge 33(2), 88100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinnon, S.L. (2012). ‘Essentialism, Intersectionality, and Recognition: A Feminist Rhetorical Approach to the Audience.’ In Chávez, K.R. and Griffin, C. L. (eds), Standing in the Intersection: Feminist Voices, Feminist Practices in Communication Studies, pp. 189210. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
McKinnon, S.L. (2016). Gendered Asylum: Race and Violence in U.S. Law and Politics. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Medina, J. (2013). The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merry, S.E. (2016). The Seductions of Quantification: Measuring Human Rights, Gender Violence, and Sex Trafficking. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, C. (1997). The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, C. (2007). ‘White Ignorance.’ In Sullivan, S. and Tuana, N. (eds), Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, pp. 1138. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Nayak, M. (2015). Who Is Worthy of Protection? Gender-Based Asylum and US Immigration Politics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, L.H. (1993). ‘Epistemological Communities.’ In Alcoff, L. and Potter, E. (eds), Feminist Epistemologies, pp. 121–59. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nguyen, C.T. (2020). ‘Echo Chambers and Epistemic Bubbles.’ Episteme 17(2), 141–61. doi: 10.1017/epi.2018.32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pohlhaus, G. Jr. (2012). ‘Relational Knowing and Epistemic Injustice: Toward a Theory of Willful Hermeneutical Ignorance.’ Hypatia 27(4), 715–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pohlhaus, G. Jr. (2014). ‘Discerning the Primary Epistemic Harm in Cases of Testimonial Injustice.’ Social Epistemology 28(2), 99114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruíz, E. (Forthcoming a). ‘‘Structural Trauma.’ Meridians: Feminism, Race, Transnationalism.Google Scholar
Ruíz, E. (Forthcoming b). ‘Women of Color Structural Feminisms.’ In Tate, S-A. (ed.), The Palgrave Handbook on Critical Race and Gender. New York, NY: Palgrave.Google Scholar
Ruíz, E. and Sertler, E. (2019). ‘Asylum, Credible Fear Tests, and Colonial Violence.Guest Post for Biopolitical Philosophy. https://biopoliticalphilosophy.com/Google Scholar
Schutte, O. (1998). ‘Cultural Alterity: Cross-Cultural Communication and Feminist Theory in North-South Contexts.’ Hypatia 13(2), 5372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shotwell, A. (2017). ‘Forms of Knowing and Epistemic Resources.’ In Kidd, I.J., Medina, J. and Pohlhaus, G. Jr. (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice, pp. 7988. New York, NY: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, S. and Tuana, N. (2007). Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Toole, B. (2019). ‘From Standpoint Epistemology to Epistemic Oppression.’ Hypatia 34(4), 598618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Townley, C. (2011). A Defense of Ignorance: Its Value for Knowers and Roles in Feminist and Social Epistemologies. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Tuana, N. (2004). ‘Coming to Understand: Orgasm and the Epistemology of Ignorance.’ Hypatia 19(1), 194232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuana, N. (2006). ‘The Speculum of Ignorance: The Women's Health Movement and Epistemologies of Ignorance.’ Hypatia 21(3), 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagenknecht, S. (2014). ‘Opaque and Translucent Epistemic Dependence in Collaborative Scientific Practice.’ Episteme 11(4), 475–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Webb, M.O. (1993). ‘Why I Know About As Much As You: A Reply to Hardwig.’ Journal of Philosophy 90(5), 260–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Webb, M.O. (1995). ‘Feminist Epistemology and the Extent of the Social.’ Hypatia 10(3), 8598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar