Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T22:04:05.211Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Demystifying Humility's Paradoxes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 April 2022

Derick Hughes*
Affiliation:
University of Colorado Boulder, Boulder, Colorado, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The utterance “I am humble” is thought to be paradoxical because a speaker implies that they know they are virtuous or reveals an aim to impress others – a decidedly non-humble aim. Such worries lead to the seemingly absurd conclusion that a humble person cannot properly assert that they are humble. In this paper, I reconstruct and evaluate three purported paradoxes of humility concerning its self-attribution, knowledge and belief about our own virtue, and humility's value. I argue that humility is not genuinely paradoxical and that these puzzles do not have meaningful implications for its conceptual analyses. I instead offer error theoretical explanations of humility's apparent paradoxicality.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

The utterance “I am humble” is often said to be paradoxical. Driver (Reference Driver1989: 375) remarked that self-attributing modesty “seems to be oddly self-defeating,” and that some would think it “nonsensical.” Curiously, we do not face this problem with other virtues: one can truly be compassionate and assert this fact without absurdity. With humility, however, a speaker who self-attributes seemingly reveals attitudes generally seen as incompatible with humility – if not at least partially constitutive for being a braggart – for instance, that they believe they are virtuous or that they want to impress others with their virtue. This leads to the conclusion that the humble person cannot, on pain of losing their own humility, assert that they are humble.

This self-attribution problem is one of several generated by humility, but few authors have endeavored to identify the precise source of contradiction.Footnote 1 In an attempt to uncover the source, in this paper, I identify and discuss three different puzzles: the aforementioned self-attribution problem, an epistemic problem that one cannot believe or know that one is humble, and an axiological puzzle that humility seems to require that we be brought down or not be excellent. Since many find these features incompatible with a traditional understanding of virtue, authors search for a conceptual analysis of humility that explains away its apparently paradoxical qualities in order to avoid succumbing to the view that humility is no virtue at all.Footnote 2

In what follows, I will argue that all of the puzzles in question stem from problematic reasoning. In section 2, I sketch an account of the nature of a paradox with attention to pragmatic paradoxes and argue that the self-attribution puzzle falls short of being a bona fide pragmatic paradox. In section 3, I consider the epistemic problem of whether uttering “I believe that I am humble” conflicts with any core features of virtue theory. I argue that it does not, and I offer error theoretical explanations of the apparent paradoxicality of such an utterance. These explanations in hand, in section 4, I consider but ultimately reject the remaining axiological problem. I do so on the ground that humility is (quite rightly) assumed to be valuable – and in fact, that this assumption is necessary to make the other puzzles worth considering. This leads me to conclude that humility is not genuinely paradoxical and the puzzles do not provide meaningful implications for its conceptual analysis.

As a preliminary note, I take modesty and humility to be synonymous in this article. I do this because modesty and humility are frequently taken to share a cluster of features, one of which Bommarito (Reference Bommarito and Zalta2018) identifies as “self-attribution strangeness.” Intuitively, the strangeness of uttering “I am modest” is identical to the strangeness of uttering “I am humble.” While some authors distinguish between modesty and humility, several others find that both traits are afflicted by self-attribution strangeness and the additional problems concerning knowledge and value.Footnote 3 In general, then, whatever differences may exist between modesty and humility are not expected to affect the central discussion in this paper regarding their puzzling nature.Footnote 4

2. Pragmatic paradoxes and self-attribution

I follow Sainsbury (Reference Sainsbury2009: 1) in understanding a paradox to be “an apparently unacceptable conclusion derived from apparently acceptable reasoning from apparently acceptable premises.” Citing Sainsbury, Huemer (Reference Huemer2018) requires that the reasoning for the unacceptable conclusion have widespread and robust appeal that leads to persistent disagreement among experts. To borrow Huemer's example, a statement such as “I am nothing” fails to qualify as a paradox because it is either false, or has an alternate meaning such as “I am unimportant.” The air of contradiction in the statement is better explained by a more widely appealing intuition (i.e., that “I” is in fact something), or a lack of robustness (i.e., that “nothing” is ambiguous). Sometimes, too, we use “paradox” in a loose sense to simply describe an odd phenomenon when there is nevertheless agreement among experts. For example, the so-called “paradox of happiness,” in which we decrease our odds of achieving happiness by directly pursuing it, does not present us with any unacceptable conclusion; we would not need to reevaluate what happiness means when considering this fact, because happiness is not typically defined by whether we directly aim toward it or not.Footnote 5 To be a genuine paradox, then, a puzzle must (1) have an apparently unacceptable conclusion, (2) apparently acceptable reasoning from apparently acceptable premises, and (3) one can reasonably expect (1) and (2) to yield persistent disagreement among experts; the more a puzzle satisfies these conditions, the more intractable and paradoxical it is. These conditions should be enough to guide us through our discussion.

With these preliminaries in place, do philosophers think that humility is genuinely paradoxical? It seems they do; persistent disagreement among philosophers about how to explain humility's puzzling features is one indication that it generates a problem that is rather intractable. Brennan (Reference Brennan2007: 126), for instance, takes himself to be offering a “competing account of why saying ‘I am modest’ or thinking it is paradoxical,” in response to Driver's (Reference Driver1989) view. While Brennan argues that one can have knowledge of one's worth by comparing oneself to the ideally virtuous person, Driver (Reference Driver1989: 376) contends that the utterance “I am modest” is self-contradictory because it implies that one is knowledgeable about one's self-worth.Footnote 6 Statman (Reference Statman1992) for modesty, and Hare (Reference Hare1996) for humility, follow this line as well by arguing that an accurate assessment of one's worth generates paradoxes for those who are also egalitarians about human worth (e.g., Ben-Ze'ev Reference Ben-Ze'ev1993). On their views, it is seemingly impossible for someone to be humble by accurately judging that they are morally superior to most, because this belief directly undermines one's commitment to egalitarianism.Footnote 7 I will address this specific worry in the following section. For now, I only wish to highlight how philosophers find assertions of modesty and humility to be self-contradictory or in conflict with other widely held commitments, indicating that authors do find something seriously paradoxical about these traits. The precise way that purported solutions attempt to account for these paradoxical features will become evident as we progress. Let us begin then with the self-attribution puzzle, which will lay the foundation for considering our other puzzles.

Self-attribution (SAP): “I am humble.”

SAP presents us with a pragmatic contradiction as opposed to a logical contradiction. Paradoxes of self-reference, such as the liar paradox (“This sentence is false”) are logically self-contradictory, appearing false if true, and true if false. By contrast, pragmatic paradoxes are “falsified by their own utterance,” meaning that they contradict a fact that the speaker implies by making the utterance, often the propositional attitude that the speaker expresses (Cohen Reference Cohen1950: 85). Ebersole (Reference Ebersole1953) notes examples such as “there are no sentences” and “I believe nothing” as instances of pragmatic paradoxes; the speaker who utters “there are no sentences” has contradicted a fact she implies by making the utterance, which is itself a sentence; similarly, the speaker who asserts “I believe nothing” expresses a belief that is inconsistent with her utterance. Most authors consider Moore's paradox, often expressed as “It is raining, but I do not believe it is,” or, “It is raining, but I believe it is not raining,” to be another example of a pragmatic paradox.Footnote 8 Moore (Reference Moore and Schilpp1944) explained the absurdity of the speaker's utterance by noting that when a speaker asserts that p, they imply that they believe that p. The intractability of Moore's paradox is affirmed in part by the disagreement among philosophers about various solutions, which have additional consequences for understanding norms of assertion, belief, and rationality.Footnote 9

Does self-attributing humility generate a pragmatic paradox? I do not think so. While philosophers converge upon the belief that, in normal cases, the humble person would not utter SAP, a speaker who utters SAP doesn't imply anything about their attitudes or the truth of their utterance. Let me illustrate by first attempting to articulate the reasoning that is motivating the puzzle. I suspect it goes something like this:

  1. (1a) If a speaker S is humble, then he will not assert SAP.

  2. (2a) S asserts SAP.

  3. (3a) Therefore, S is not humble.

Robinson (Reference Robinson, Alfano, Lynch and Tanesini2020: 27) describes this reasoning in a manner that is telling of its lack of robustness, writing, “if I truly possess that characteristic, I (typically) will not have made the utterance in question.” Note the parenthetical “typically” here, which is playing a more substantial role than is often admitted. Robinson's own solution to the puzzle requires that the humble person rarely face circumstances where they need to self-attribute humility, because most of the time, what it means to be humble is to be inattentive to one's own merit.Footnote 10 This strikes me as a reasonable explanation, but I worry that it does not resolve any genuine paradox given its attention to exceptional circumstances. For instance, Robinson would permit a humble person to utter “I am humble” to appease an annoyingly insistent complimenter. Yet, such an exception means that the utterance in question is not a pragmatic paradox, because the contextual factor of an annoying complimenter is unrelated in principle to a humble speaker's being inattentive to their own self-worth; notice that such contextual factors could not similarly absolve “there are no sentences” from being paradoxical. I reckon that more emphasis ought to be placed on taking the quality of being inattentive to be part of humility's definition, as opposed to emphasizing the exceptional circumstances that might sometimes lead a humble person to attend to their own merit.

If hedging on typical cases is only possible when something unrelated to the utterance stands to make it false, a better case is one that considers whether self-attribution undermines humility's constitutive features. Here is one problem, again invoking Robinson's proposed solution: if being inattentive to one's worth is part of humility's definition, one may worry that a self-attribution always implies attentiveness. But I do not think that this is right. For example, suppose that a PhD student, Laura, is searching for a humble dissertation advisor. Laura has some evidence that Professor Smith is humble, having seen him engage in characteristically humble behaviors such as downplaying his achievements, attempting to change the topic of conversation away from himself, and so on. She also has some testimonial evidence from Smith's colleagues and students who find Smith to be humble. But imagine that Laura wants to hear Smith's assessment of himself, so she directly asks her prospective advisor, “Are you humble?” – to which Smith replies, “Yes, I am humble.”

How should this self-attribution affect Laura's assessment of Smith? Laura should, I think, bear in mind that trait attributions suggest many facts about an individual's psychological states and behavior. These qualities are much murkier than the facts a speaker implies by uttering other paradoxical statements (e.g., “there are no sentences” is obviously a sentence). It might be true that the humble person typically does not self-attribute, but we mean this as something that follows from humility's definition as one fact among an uncountable number of interrelated facts that Smith implies about his character. Among these, importantly, are the characteristically humble behaviors that Laura has already observed and gathered from Smith's colleagues’ testimony. More, however, Smith implies that he has characteristically humble psychological attitudes – inattentiveness to his worth, desires to consider others’ worth more than his own, a lower estimation of his worth, or other attitudes along these lines. Without simply begging the question, one could not say that X is a quality necessary for being humble, which a speaker implies by their self-attribution, and which is also defeated by that self-attribution. Here are three reasons why. First, note that it would be odd for Laura to take Smith's self-attribution as evidence that Smith is not humble, and much less reasonable for her to think that it counts against her previous observations and testimonial evidence of Smith's characteristically humble behavior. This is further motivated, second, by the fact that the evidence that Laura possesses of Smith's humility could in principle be obtained by Smith, such that his self-attribution amounts to an ordinary instance of self-reflection. Just as the generous person may reflect on their charitable contributions, a humble person may reflect on their own willingness to shift attention away from themselves. Third, and finally, the facts that most conclusively falsify Smith's utterance are unrelated character flaws. Self-attribution is unjustified if, for example, Smith really views himself as great, admirable, and unbeatable as a dissertation advisor. But in that case, Smith has said something false only because he views himself as great, admirable, and unbeatable. There is nothing paradoxical about self-attribution if typically, one refrains from uttering SAP because of considerations unrelated to the utterance in question. Insofar as exceptional cases exist in virtue of Smith's other characteristically humble states and behaviors, self-attribution is not contradicted by whatever Smith implies by his utterance.

What's needed is a claim to the effect that asserting SAP constitutes a kind of obvious immodesty – that is, that self-attribution strangeness is in fact part of humility's meaning. Once more, however, I am unsure how one could hold this view without begging the question in favor of strangeness. Presumably, virtue theorists should want to explain away strangeness at least to the extent that it no longer generates wider problems for one's virtue theory. Consider one such wider problem: should one's virtue theory favor a doxastic explanation (i.e., in terms of our having or lacking certain beliefs) or non-doxastic explanations (e.g., in terms of emotions, desires, attention, etc.) of strangeness? As I see it, the answer is “neither,” since both types of account offer comparatively reasonable explanations of strangeness – something one would not expect if there was live disagreement about a genuine paradox. For instance, consider Robinson's non-doxastic explanation which locates the problem of SAP in a speaker's cognitive attention.Footnote 11 Aside from exceptional cases of being prompted by a third-party in which S might reluctantly admit that he is humble, in premise (2a), S implies that he is attending to his humility too much to count as genuinely humble. But as we said, the issue with this explanation is that exceptional cases show that we cannot draw any conclusions about S's attitudes from his assertion, because in some contexts, S might say “I am humble” to appease an annoying complimenter who will not go away until S finally admits that he is humble. This explanation is not a unique solution to the problem; a doxastic account of humility could alternatively hold that S would not self-attribute only if he has the right sorts of beliefs about his worth and the worth of others. Hence, it may be reasonable for S to assert that he is humble if it is in fact true, and he is in a context with an interlocutor who would recognize the truth of the assertion as well. Emphasis on context leads us back to the kind of situation between Laura and Smith, where we admit that humility's definition can turn on a theoretical commitment to doxastic or non-doxastic attitudes – but the alleged strangeness of the utterance itself is not relevant to that definition.

Since both doxastic and non-doxastic explanations agree that S is not humble in ordinary cases when he asserts SAP, we must admit that definitions of humility do not turn on apparent strangeness. And as we would expect with a non-paradox, we find more consensus among experts about the reasoning and conclusion than originally thought. We can, of course, make the above reasoning seem more contradictory by inserting the premise that S is humble. But this will only help to further solidify the consensus about the puzzle.

  1. (1b) S is humble.

  2. (2b) If S is humble, then he will not assert SAP.

  3. (3b) S asserts SAP.

  4. (4b) Therefore, S is not humble.

We can now see the contradiction here, and why both doxastic and non-doxastic explanations would be correct to reject (1b) here. The problem with (1b), in short, is that it neglects widely shared norms about virtue confirmation and disconfirmation. For example, we could initially judge that Smith is compassionate but one day find him torturing puppies. In such a case, either Smith must never have been compassionate, or he suddenly became cruel (since the compassionate person would not torture puppies). Therefore, it is either false that Smith is compassionate, or true that he is compassionate in one sense (perhaps prior to torturing the puppies) and not another (upon torturing the puppies). Similarly, we can reject the claim that S was humble in the first place given (1b).

Perhaps the problem lies with humility's conflict with a norm of assertion. So, maybe we have a problem that looks like this:

  1. (1c) If a speaker S possesses an attribute, then S can truthfully assert they have that attribute.

  2. (2c) If S possesses the attribute of humility, then S cannot truthfully assert SAP.

  3. (3c) Therefore, it is not true that if S possesses an attribute, then S can truthfully assert they have the attribute.

We should recall that, as Robinson pointed out, (2c) is false. It is only typically the case that the humble person will not self-attribute. Once we admit that an individual can sometimes be in a context that permits a truthful assertion that they are humble, we give up on the prospect of locating a genuine paradox.Footnote 12 Pragmatic paradoxes involve contradictions, not exceptions. Frequency of context aside though, a more important concern is that (2c) misses the distinction between humility and the kind of speech act that could in principle cancel itself. That is, it is implausible that the utterance “I am humble” is strong enough to show, all by itself, that the person uttering it is not humble, or worse, that they are a braggart. In their account, Alfano and Robinson (Reference Alfano and Robinson2014) define bragging as asserting something about oneself that aims to impress one's addressee. Since bragging depends on a speaker's communicative intentions, SAP cannot be paradoxical simply because humility is an excellent or impressive quality. It can, however, be implicated in what Alfano and Robinson (Reference Alfano and Robinson2014: 268) would call “the braggart's version of Moore's paradox” if a speaker pairs their brag with a disclaimer, leading them to humblebrag. A proposition of this sort is considered below.

Self-attribution (SAP+ Disclaimer (D) (SAP-D): “I am not trying to impress you, but I am humble.”

There is something strange about making the disclaimer of not attempting to impress while simultaneously attributing an impressive quality to oneself. What makes SAP-D more robust than SAP is this seemingly inconsistent demand imposed upon the addressee. Self-attributing humility demands an addressee both accept that the speaker has an impressive quality and that they not be impressed by it. Thus, humility may be the sort of impressive quality that cannot easily be cancelled by a disclaimer when self-attributed.Footnote 13

There are a few things to say about this. First, note the apparent contradiction here is not in humility, but rather, in the meaning that the disclaimer is supposed to communicate given the speaker's intentions. Alfano and Robinson take bragging to involve a speaker aiming to produce the emotion of being impressed in the hearer. Therefore, we could replace humility with any other admirable quality and obtain a similarly contradictory result, as Alfano and Robinson illustrate with the statement “I'm not trying to impress you by saying this, but I am a genius.” In this case, we see that the contradiction arises in large part from the impressiveness of being a genius. Yet, if something like “I am a concert pianist” is not bragging, and we assume this to be an impressive quality, it is not clear why “I am humble” would be bragging either.Footnote 14 One might still worry that humility, unlike intelligence or being a concert pianist, is somehow disconfirmed by the utterance; one can be a genius and a braggart, but we do not think one can be humble and a braggart. This is true. However, this is owed to the fact that the speaker has bragged by having the intention to impress, which she implies by her disclaimer “I'm not trying to impress you.” So, it is the ‘D’ part of SAP-D that generates a paradox. As Alfano and Robinson note, an agent cannot intend to assert what she takes to be an impossibility. Hence, a speaker who asserts SAP-D implicitly rejects the apparent strangeness of her assertion.

Second, notice that if bragging depends on an agent's intentions, there are cases which may look like bragging but fail to qualify as such because the speaker intends something else. This means that even apparent brags are insufficient for undermining one's humility unless the speaker's intentions are definitively anti-humble. Consider the statement, “I think I'm much more humble than you would understand.”Footnote 15 In typical cases, of course, we should think that this utterance reflects negatively on a speaker's humility, since the speaker goes beyond self-attributing humility and openly disparages the addressee's intelligence. Such a statement might negatively reflect on a person's humility, but they also may intend to convey (rather rudely) that others are failing to appreciate the positive features of their character. Moreover, such a statement seems an unlikely candidate for a humblebrag as well, since the speaker is not merely presuming unintelligence or insensitivity in the addressee, but rather states it outright.Footnote 16 Thus, the utterance by itself is insufficient to undermine one's humility independently of the speaker's intentions. So long as self-attribution permits these exceptions, there is nowhere for a genuine paradox to take hold.

One might wonder why we have not tried to appeal more to the propositional attitudes of the speaker to explain what has gone wrong with their utterance. The reason is that SAP, by itself, does not purport to be saying much about the speaker's attitudes – at least not in the way that we would expect with pragmatic paradoxes such as “I believe nothing” or “It is raining, but I do not believe that it is.” Because virtues presuppose that the agent have certain beliefs, desires, and intentions, we are unlikely to find a contradiction that will be illuminating for our understanding of humility as a virtue unless we invoke these propositional attitudes explicitly. While the self-attribution case does not pose a genuine paradox, it still shows that humility might be in tension with other requirements for being virtuous, such as accurate or true beliefs about oneself, an ability to cultivate virtue, and an intention to perform virtuous actions. Of these, I think belief poses the most formidable challenge. So it is to the epistemic problem that I now turn.

3. The epistemic puzzle and its errors

Recall from our discussion of pragmatic paradoxes that a speaker's utterance contradicts a fact implied by the utterance, often the propositional attitude of the speaker. With Moore's paradox, for instance, we find the speaker to be asserting ~p, even though we think that the speaker should be rationally required to believe that p. In that case, we locate a problem with the attitudes of a speaker who ought to be guided by a rational norm to believe that p. So, the best way to make SAP more paradoxical is to explicitly state that the person who utters it believes it, in a manner akin to Moore's paradox. Driver (Reference Driver1989: 377) draws a direct comparison between SAP and Moore's paradox, writing:

It is self-defeating to utter [“I am modest”]. Like Moore's “It is raining, but I do not believe it,” [“I am modest”] can be true, but I cannot believe it to be true or utter the sentence sensibly. I can be modest, but I cannot know it.

So, we can simply add the conjunct “I believe that I am humble” to form an apparent contradiction:

Epistemic (EP): “I am humble, and I believe that I am humble.”

Driver's case for the paradoxicality of EP rests on a single intuition: if one knows or believes one is modest, then acts of modesty are insincere or false modesty – i.e., not modesty at all. Essentially, Driver's view generates the following dilemma: either modesty is not a virtue, or modesty requires ignorance of one's self-worth. According to Driver, one could be modest, but it would nevertheless be paradoxical to believe or know that one is modest.Footnote 17

While we are dealing with some competing intuitions, I find that none of them can successfully generate a paradox. These intuitions are as follows:

  1. (A) Ignorance of one's worth is necessary for modesty or humility.

  2. (B) Ignorance of one's worth is compatible with modesty or humility.

  3. (C) Ignorance of one's worth is incompatible with modesty or humility.

To my knowledge, Driver is the only philosopher to fully endorse (A), and I believe that only (A) can underwrite EP. Virtue theorists usually reject (A) because virtues are excellent qualities that seem to require that an individual have the skillful know-how virtue called practical wisdom. So, if EP depends on something like (A) to be paradoxical, then it will not succeed since (A) lacks widespread appeal. Among non-philosophers, Driver's intuition fares better. However, non-philosophers might endorse an externalist view about the value and attribution of virtue in general.Footnote 18 That is, for non-philosophers, behavior is often what matters for attributions of virtue, not the internal states of the agent. This would not show that ignorance is necessary for modesty as (A) states, but rather, that humility is an ordinary instance of the intuition that virtues can permit ignorance, as (B) states. Therefore, Driver's intuition that the person who knowingly understates their worth is falsely modest is weak compared against broader intuitions we have about how virtues are attributed. So, this leaves us with either (B) or (C) to get a paradox.

The problem is that intuitions (B) and (C) force us to confront virtue theoretical commitments about propositional knowledge while not generating any paradoxical effects on their own; namely, we consider whether propositional ignorance makes one more or less virtuous. Assuming the standard view that virtues are excellent traits of character, virtue theorists generally agree that virtuous dispositions require knowledge-how, not knowledge-that, a view widely endorsed regardless of whether one favors intuition (B) or (C). Accordingly, (B) and (C) are not doxastic requirements about knowing or believing something about one's modesty or humility. They arise instead from broader considerations about whether propositional knowledge or ignorance makes one's virtue more or less valuable. Consider (B): just as we are not morally or intellectually better or worse off for not knowing exactly how many stars are in the sky, or the recipe for a delicious soufflé, we don't seem better or worse off simply not knowing some good quality we possess. This is why Driver (Reference Driver2001) adopts the view that propositional ignorance is neither intrinsically good nor bad in response to the worry that modesty as ignorance would apparently violate the general constraint that virtues be voluntarily acquired (since we assume that one cannot be voluntarily ignorant of one's self-worth).Footnote 19 Those who accept such a general constraint on the voluntary acquisition of virtue would favor (C); however, proponents of (C) could adopt the view that modesty or humility requires non-overestimation (e.g., Richards 1988 (for humility); Flanagan Reference Flanagan1990 (for modesty)). Importantly, one's account of modesty or humility need not turn on intuitions (B) or (C) because neither entail that believing or knowing that one is humble means that one is not humble. One could simply hold, as Flanagan (Reference Flanagan1990: 427) does, that “[modesty] need not involve, ideally it should not involve, the relatively rare defect of underestimation [emphasis mine].” In short, proponents of (B) and (C) agree that propositional knowledge circumstantially matters for humility, independently of one's first-order judgements about one's own humility. However, nothing about (B) or (C) suggests that beliefs about our own humility generate any paradoxical effects.

I take it that paradoxical effects can only arise if propositional knowledge or ignorance specifically includes attitudes toward one's own modesty or humility, as opposed to one's other merits and achievements. This “strong-ignorance claim” as Flanagan (Reference Flanagan1990: 423) calls it, “requires ignorance at the second level,” about one's own virtue. Since becoming virtuous usually involves being sensitive to evidence about how we ought to cultivate virtue, one worry is that our higher-order attitudes about our own virtue will be in tension with our attitudes in expressing the virtue itself. Consider this problem: can one believe that one is humble and believe that this belief is reasonable? The straightforward answer is yes – indeed, some philosophers might argue that such coherence is rationally required (e.g., Huemer Reference Huemer2011).Footnote 20 It may be incoherent to assert something like “I am humble, but humble people do not believe they are humble,” but it is an open question whether EP is incoherent in this way; the second conjunct may simply be false. This open question does not arise when we are confronted with other pragmatically paradoxical propositions, which cannot be truly believed. One cannot appropriately assert “there are no sentences” precisely because it is not an open question whether “there are no sentences” is a sentence.

What about humility's conflict with virtues that have clearer descriptions? Admittedly, practical wisdom still requires that a person have some propositional knowledge in order to act virtuously. For instance, an honest person cannot be honest without uttering propositions that they believe to be true; similarly, a generous person may need to know that their generous act is going to produce good states of affairs. Perhaps then, the humble person must have certain attitudes about their worth. And, maybe these attitudes conflict with some other important normative commitment that the virtuous person ought to have. Statman (Reference Statman1992: 426) develops this worry into a paradox:

  1. (1d) It is possible that there exists a person P who is genuinely admirable and worthy, as well as modest.

  2. (2d) Necessarily, either P knows he is genuinely worthy, or he does not.

  3. (3d) If P knows he is worthy, he cannot be modest, since his worth is exceptionally high.

  4. (4d) If P is ignorant of his value, his alleged modesty cannot be considered a virtue.Footnote 21

A similar, but more precise formulation of the problem is described by Hare (Reference Hare1996: 236):

Let M stand for the moral principle that all people have equal moral worth, regardless of their special abilities and distinctions, which vary markedly among individuals. Now for S as for any person,

  1. (1e) S is humble only if S adheres to M.

However,

  1. (2e) Moral ability and distinction, which consists in the degree to which one adheres to basic moral principles such as M, varies markedly among individuals.

  2. (3e) Those people who have a markedly higher level of moral ability and achievement than most are properly described as morally superior to most.

Therefore,

  1. (4e) S is morally superior to most.

Therefore,

  1. (5e) In believing M, in being humble, and in understanding the extent of her own moral achievements, S believes that

    1. i. All people have equal moral worth; and

    2. ii. S is morally superior to most.Footnote 22

According to Statman and Hare, however, the epistemic contradiction is now embodied by the following:

Epistemic + Egalitarianism (EEP): “I am humble and believe in the equal moral worth of human beings.”

Flanagan (Reference Flanagan1990: 423) says that it is “extremely odd, counterintuitive, and moralistic if it disqualified a person from being modest if she knew she was.” I am inclined to agree. However, if knowing that one is humble conflicts with egalitarian beliefs, then Flannagan is mistaken, because one is apparently led to believe that they are better than others in order to be humble. In EEP, the first conjunct implies that the second conjunct is false, because the speaker really is morally superior to others and believes it. So, the epistemic paradox seems to create a normative contradiction that undermines one's commitment to egalitarianism.

This could work in generating a pragmatic paradox, but only if we thought that an individual's propositional knowledge concerning others’ merits matters for humility. But I don't think it matters. For example, consider an Olympic swimmer who has just won gold and believes the proposition “I outperformed my competitors.” Does this belief reflect negatively on the swimmer's humility? I don't see how. It seems that one's humility is not defeated by this knowledge any more than it is constituted by a lack of such knowledge. Here are two reasons to support this claim. First, beliefs about performing better in comparison to other members of the moral community do not suggest nasty beliefs; from “I outperformed my competitors,” it does not follow that the agent believes “I am better than them,” and it is a proposition of this latter sort that would undermine one's humility or commitment to egalitarianism. Indeed, there are many ways to explain why one's worth as a swimmer is not determined by the performance of other swimmers. A humble person could compare herself to an ideal swimmer (e.g., Brennan Reference Brennan2007), or think of herself with respect to humanity as a whole (e.g., Tanesini Reference Tanesini, Alfano, Lynch and Tanesini2020). However one wants to put it, the important, but often overlooked, insight is that humility is essentially noncomparative – like other virtues, its value is not owed to how we compare ourselves to other moral agents, but rather, how we grow in accordance with the ideal agent to become a better version of ourselves.Footnote 23 This view is intuitively more plausible than any view based on the alleged tension generated by EEP.

Second, we often look to general constraints on virtue to avoid character fragmentation and acquire a coherent value system. We would think it strange if someone were to frequently make racist remarks and say they are committed to egalitarianism, not just because egalitarianism precludes racism, but because this fact can, in principle, be grasped by the racist.Footnote 24 If we judge that a racist is unable to grasp this fact, we would likely judge them to have diminished responsibility, which in turn, changes whether they possess a given trait at all. Likewise, if humility is a moral virtue, and virtues are traits, it is fair to think that there must be a normative reason to be humble that one could grasp in principle, even if one does not currently recognize such a reason. On the assumption that humility is a virtue, we would expect properly humble beliefs to cohere with egalitarian beliefs (or other beliefs that are involved in one's other virtuous character traits), unless given a reason to suppose otherwise.

To summarize, I identified two errors by considering EP and EEP. The first error involves confusing knowledge-how with knowledge-that. Virtues are not explained by an agent's propositional knowledge or lack thereof, and thus, there are no pragmatic contradictions between an agent's first-order attitudes, or coherence between these and her higher-order attitudes. The second error involves mistakenly supposing some propositional attitude to have normative significance for humility when it does not. Beliefs or knowledge about one's worth do not entail that an agent has anti-humble attitudes, as we considered among the potential conflicts with the attitudes implicated in one's other traits or broader normative commitments.

4. The axiological puzzle

So far, we have assumed that humility is a virtue. We make this assumption because SAP and EP try to force us into a dilemma: to account for humility's apparent strangeness, we must either reject humility as a virtue, or accept some feature that is incompatible with traditional virtue theory. Among several features potentially at odds with traditional virtue theory, we considered whether all virtues can be self-attributed, whether humility's main feature is non-doxastic, whether virtue requires ignorance or propositional knowledge, and whether humility is at odds with egalitarianism. To resolve SAP and EP, authors generally proceed by arguing that humility is a virtue and one of these features can be accepted without damaging consequences to one's virtue theory.

The axiological problem, however, challenges the assumption that humility is a virtue. Sidgwick puts this problem well when he writes:

The common account, however, of [humility] is somewhat paradoxical. For it is generally said that Humility prescribes a low opinion of our own merits: but if our merits are comparatively high, it seems strange to direct us to have a low opinion of them. (Sidgwick Reference Sidgwick1907 [1962]: 334)

Here is one way that this view could be formulated into a paradoxical dilemma: either humility is not a virtue, or a virtue can direct us to have a low opinion of ourselves even if our merits are high. Sidgwick thinks that humility's strangeness privileges the first horn of the dilemma since humility is in tension with the virtue of self-respect, given one's “comparatively high” merits. Indeed, apart from those working in the Judeo-Christian tradition, philosophers have historically rejected modesty and humility as moral virtues given their apparent tension with another virtue.Footnote 25 Aristotle (Reference Ross and Brown2009: 1125a33) understood humility to be “both commoner and worse” than vanity, believing instead that the ideally virtuous person, who possesses pride, accepts the goods and praises they deserve. Hume (Reference Hume and Schneewind1751 [1983]: 73–4) includes humility among the monkish virtues which “serve to no manner of purpose; neither advance a man's fortune in the world, nor render him a more valuable member of society.” Nietzsche (Reference Nietzsche, Clark and Swensen1887 [2006]: 26–7) roughly thought that the weak turn “timid baseness” into humility, where humility is a type of false self-righteousness in which one chooses mediocre inoffensiveness over curiosity.Footnote 26 Although Kant (Reference Kant, Gregor, Guyer and Wood1797 [1996]: 6: 434) believed humility to be a virtue, he worried that interpersonal humility risked being “false” or “lying humility” in which one tries to “equal or surpass others … believing that in this way one will get an even greater inner worth.” Drawing from Kant, Dillon (Reference Dillon, Timmons and Johnson2015: 45) contends that humility must be constrained by self-respect, and she views humility's status as a great moral virtue on its own puzzling given the comparison between humility's low estimation of oneself against the fortitude of traditional virtues such as wisdom and courage.

For the sake of argument, I will put the axiological problem into a single utterance by placing it in tension with another virtue, using pride for illustration:

Axiological (AXP): “I am proud of my humility.”Footnote 27

To think that AXP presents a genuine paradox, I believe, is to rely more upon one's virtue theoretical commitments as opposed to widely shared intuitions. If humility is not an excellence, one likely believes, like Dillon, that humility is on par with humiliation or self-deprecation, or that it yields few or no benefits for humanity on its own. Dillon takes such a view to be the more intuitive one – yet, in order for AXP to be paradoxical, one must show that humility and another value are mutually exclusive, be it pride, self-respect, or something else, requiring us to make additional judgements about these values. It is a fair generalization, I think, to say that philosophers have historically worked from their broader normative commitments to make sense of ambiguous traits such as modesty and humility, but to the detriment of identifying these traits’ virtuous qualities. For instance, consider the ancients’ unity of the virtues thesis: the view that you can have one virtue if and only if you have all virtues. If one accepts this thesis and the view of pride as Aristotle has characterized it, then one is essentially forced to exclude humility from the virtues. We can expect similar issues to arise when considering just how complex and nuanced the above philosophers’ moral psychological projects are – complexities that cannot be thoroughly explored in this paper. However, not only are some of these background commitments implausible (such as a strong unity of the virtues thesis), but I see no reason why they should bear upon our intuitive assessments of humility's value.Footnote 28

A similar critique could be made against the Judeo-Christian tradition for treating humility as a virtue because of our special relationship to God. However, it seems to me that when humility takes a positive role in a coherent value system, its value does not strictly depend upon the system itself; the qualities that stand to make humility a virtue for Christians can be valued regardless of whether one also adopts the Judeo-Christian doctrine. I don't think that this can be said when humility is framed negatively, because we must accept theoretical commitments such as the unity of virtues thesis, Hume's category of monkish virtues, Kant's conception of self-respect, and so forth. I do not deny that the Judeo-Christian tradition similarly assigns humility positive value for its role in Judeo-Christian doctrine. However, we could imagine, for instance, a once devout Christian who inculcates humility for religious reasons but who continues to find humility morally valuable after becoming an atheist; it would not be abnormal for an atheist to view Jesus's humility as morally valuable. For worse, Jesus is rarely considered in the secular philosophical literature on humility, even though he would be a paradigm example of virtuous humility and the perfectly virtuous person.Footnote 29 Interestingly too, Jesus is not shy about attributing humility to himself. He says, for example, “Take my yoke upon you, and learn of me; for I am meek and lowly in heart: and ye shall find rest unto your souls.”Footnote 30 What is stranger is that Jesus's claim that he is the son of God is apparently far less humble than the phrase “I am humble” because the former implies that he is perfect and possesses all the virtues. Yet, such a claim to virtue does not seem to pose any paradox either.

What explains this? I reckon we find utterances such as “I am God's humble servant” reference broader commitments to religious doctrine but need not reference any character-level merit of the speaker. Hence, having a complete value system – one that can be represented by some ideally virtuous person – does not entail that a speaker's self-attribution must coincide with a character-level evaluative judgement. Instead, the speaker might just be describing themselves, as one could when saying “I am open-minded.” Or, it might be a higher-order value judgement, for instance, “if we want to reason well about p, we should defer to expert authority.” Neither of these propositions suggest that an agent has any evaluative attitudes toward their own merits. Returning to the apparent tension in AXP, nothing would suggest that the relevant sort of pride is an evaluative judgement as opposed to a descriptive one, or that it is an evaluative judgement of the sort at the same level of one's merits as opposed to being a higher-order judgement of oneself. As far as I can tell, these are complex theoretical commitments that are to be sorted out after engaging with intuitions about humility's value, which are by far positive, even if apparently strange.

If reasoning from the ideally virtuous person is not a convincing illustration of humility's place in a complete value system, we can also consider real world concerns about description and measurement. On the generally accepted view that modesty and humility are positive personality traits (e.g., Peterson and Seligman Reference Peterson and Seligman2004: ch. 20; Gregg et al. Reference Gregg, Hart, Sedikides and Kumashiro2008), the empirical literature would also direct us to be more cautious about treating assertions such as AXP as inherently contradictory. Consider the so-called modesty effect hypothesis, which suggests that the humbler individuals are, the more modest they are rating their own humility on self-reports. Davis et al. (Reference Davis, Placeres, Choe, DeBlaere, Zeyala, Hook, Worthington, Davis and Hook2017) note two competing approaches to this hypothesis: guilty until proven innocent, and innocent until proven guilty. Since people are likely to self-enhance on evaluative traits, some researchers opt for the highly cautious guilty until proven innocent approach, which mistrusts self-reports because they appear inherently paradoxical; as SAP and EP aimed to show, self-reports of humility amount to bragging that undermines one's humility. This conservative approach has fallen by the wayside, however, because it prevents researchers from relying on those reports to describe and assess levels of humility. Researchers who adopt the more liberal innocent until proven guilty approach are still able to locate instances in which self-reports are correlated with exaggerating one's own intelligence (Hilbig et al. Reference Hilbig, Heydasch and Zettler2014; Kajonius Reference Kajonius2014), but not because the self-reports themselves are discredited. The liberal approach allows researchers to discover the various contextual factors that can influence self-reports of humility to explain why some people might be more prone to the modesty effect than others. These valuable insights are not reached from any a priori notion that humility is paradoxical, or a theoretical framework that places humility in tension with another positive trait of character.

AXP rests on a kind of skepticism about the value of humility that, I think, shows that neither SAP nor EP are genuinely paradoxical. To accept AXP, one must believe that SAP and EP wrongly assume that humility is something excellent, because the only way to find a plausible contradiction involved considering how virtuous humility conflicts with some other thing we care about: e.g., avoiding bragging, commitment to egalitarianism, avoiding deception and vicious desires, and so on. But we generally agree that humility is excellent, or at least, that the other puzzles have merited discussion on that assumption. Once more, the relevant kind of disagreement in a pragmatic paradox is found in a fact that the speaker implies by their utterance; for good reason, we do not disagree about whether a speaker who utters “I believe nothing” expresses a belief. By contrast, when we reject AXP as genuinely paradoxical, we admit that disagreements about the nature of virtuous humility are disagreements worth having. Intuitions about humility's value ought to come first, and revisions to one's virtue theory, if any, ought to come second.

5. Conclusion

Recent philosophical work on humility has often proceeded, somewhat ironically, from the virtue's standout features. I hope to have demystified these alleged paradoxes and shown humility to be an ordinary virtue. The error of judging humility to be paradoxical stems from theoretical judgements such as “really humble people cannot know how good they are,” or “humility is low opinion of self-worth,” which, I argued, do not properly follow from humility's apparent strangeness. This leads me to conclude that strangeness is not a feature that we must account for in humility's conceptual analysis. We might instead reconsider whether judgements about humility's strangeness are plausible against a strong intuition that it is a virtue. I therefore recommend that philosophers examine humility in this more ordinary light; it is, after all, in the spirit of what the virtue would ask of us.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer at Episteme for their excellent comments on an earlier draft of this paper. I am also grateful for Iskra Fileva's commitment to helping me develop and revise this project.

Footnotes

1 Robinson (Reference Robinson, Alfano, Lynch and Tanesini2020) recently described four more puzzles to accompany the self-attribution problem, three of which feature a contradiction between an agent's internal attitudes and their assertion; it seems that humble people cannot know or believe they are humble, or intentionally cultivate humility, or successfully perform humble actions, without undermining their humility or engaging in an act of bragging. I have opted not to address what Robinson calls the inculcation and agentic paradoxes for this paper since they are not widely discussed in the humility literature.

2 See, for instance, Driver (Reference Driver1989), Hare (Reference Hare1996), Garcia (Reference Garcia2006), and Kellenberger (Reference Kellenberger2010).

3 Concerning the epistemic problem, Bommarito (Reference Bommarito and Zalta2018) writes, “a person seems less modest for thinking about how modest they are [emphasis in original].” On the axiological problem, Williams (Reference Williams1993: 10) wrote, “it is a notorious truth that a modest person does not act under the title of modesty,” suggesting that modesty's value cannot be owed to acting under its description.

4 As Bommarito (2018) notes in his survey of modesty and humility, there is no consensus about the difference between these traits. In response to Slote (Reference Slote1983), Driver (Reference Driver1989: 378n5) contends that “a humble person, unlike a modest person, can paint an accurate, though perhaps unflattering picture of himself.” If Driver is right, then humility may not require a non-traditional psychological criterion such as ignorance or underestimation, which she takes to account for self-attribution strangeness. Driver's suggestion, though made quickly in passing, presents an interesting possibility to get modest behavior (or something substantially close to it) without apparent absurdity. However, it is less clear whether other distinctions avoid the paradoxical air. For example, Ben-Ze'ev (Reference Ben-Ze'ev1993: 239) says that only humility admits of degrees; Sinha (Reference Sinha2012: 265) claims that humility has a private side while modesty has a public side; and Robinson and Alfano (Reference Robinson and Alfano2016) distinguish false modesty from false humility by using Google Ngram results. I assume that these distinctions between modesty and humility don't directly affect the strangeness in question.

5 I thank Iskra Fileva for this example.

6 One may worry that Driver (Reference Driver1989) is careful to specify that the utterance “I am modest” is merely self-defeating and not paradoxical. While this is a reasonable interpretation, the responses to Driver mentioned here – particularly the quoted passage from Brennan – have understood the self-defeating quality to amount to a paradox. Furthermore, given Driver's comparison of modesty's self-defeat to Moore's paradox (section 3), I find it more plausible to read her as endorsing the view that the utterance is paradoxical. I thank an anonymous reviewer at Episteme for raising this concern.

7 See Nuyen (Reference Nuyen1998) for a further discussion of these accounts.

8 For a discussion and criticism of a pragmatic approach and solution to Moore's paradox, see Chan (Reference Chan2010).

9 Green (Reference Green, Green and Williams2007: 191), writes, for instance, “Absurdity arises from severe violation of a system of norms.”

10 For similar views, see Bommarito (Reference Bommarito2013) and Robinson and Alfano (Reference Robinson and Alfano2016).

11 Also see Bommarito (Reference Bommarito2013).

12 Psychological evaluations might be another acceptable context for the utterance (see section 4). One might also argue that Smith cannot truthfully assert either that he possesses humility or that he doesn't. I set these concerns aside for the sake of our discussion here.

13 Alfano and Robinson (Reference Alfano and Robinson2014: 268) note that this strangeness exists in some attempts to assert-without-bragging as well because a speaker makes “inconsistent demands on the addressee's interpretation of her utterance” and “the addressee is meant to believe something impressive about the speaker but not meant to be impressed.” Some cases lend themselves well to giving the speaker a route for cancelling a brag while self-attributing an impressive quality: e.g., uttering “I am a licensed doctor,” during a medical emergency. With respect to judging SAP-D to be paradoxical, however, it seems that there are few cases in which a speaker can point to an aim besides impressing the addressee when self-attributing humility to cancel the brag. Hence, SAP-D is treated as a humblebrag because we imagine that an addressee won't normally accept the disclaimer.

14 The difference may be owed to an addressee's perception of a descriptive claim in the first instance “I am a concert pianist” and an evaluative claim in the second case “I am humble.” If it is a requirement that the braggart intend to convey impressiveness, as Alfano and Robinson believe, then I am inclined to say that this difference would not matter much, since the addressee would likely be in error to judge that the latter case is an instance of bragging without any clear evidence of the speaker's intention to do so.

15 This phrase was recently uttered on the CBS News program 60 Minutes. See Stahl (Reference Stahl2016). The same points can be made regarding the phrase, “I am so humble,” also considered by Robinson (Reference Robinson, Alfano, Lynch and Tanesini2020).

16 Although the speaker in this case does not intend the addressee to be impressed, he may intend observers to be impressed – albeit, not by the content of the self-attribution, but by the comparative judgement that he is more intellectually sensitive than his interlocutor.

17 One might argue that I am being uncharitable to Driver here. However, a similar claim has been advanced by Slote (Reference Slote2004), and, to my knowledge, no one endorses Driver's view that modesty requires ignorance, though many believe that it is circumstantially permitted. Driver could perhaps have done more to defend a precise account of modesty, which she simply takes to rest on intuitions that, as far as I can tell, are mostly unshared.

19 Driver (Reference Driver2001: 30) writes, “There are lots of things I don't know, that I'm ignorant of, but that ignorance doesn't diminish me. I don't know the current number of coins in my pocket. I don't believe that this is in and of itself bad.”

20 For more discussion of the coherence requirements between our first and second order attitudes, see Feldman (Reference Feldman and Heatherington2006), Huemer (Reference Huemer2011), and Hazlett (Reference Hazlett2012).

21 The premises are written verbatim. Numbering has been adjusted to avoid confusion with the other arguments in this article.

22 See remark on formatting in footnote 21.

23 Here, I draw from Morgan-Knapp's (Reference Morgan-Knapp2019) recent work on comparative pride. One might worry on this account that humility is identical to pride. However, humility seems to be an easier fit for being a noncomparative excellence because one's merits do not need to be a function of others’ performance – competitive settings are perhaps paradigmatic sources of prideful attitudes, but not humble ones.

24 Here, I borrow from Fileva (Reference Fileva2018: 245).

25 See Snow (Reference Snow, Alfano, Lynch and Tanesini2020) for a comprehensive discussion of this literature.

26 Alfano (Reference Alfano and SteinbergForthcoming) contends that Nietzsche views modesty to be a virtue particularly in epistemic contexts, but that he regards humility to be a vice because, among other things, it leads to a conflict in an agent's drives.

27 Concerning humility's tension with pride, Hume (Reference Hume and Nidditch1739 [1978]: 2.1.1) said, “Tis impossible a man can at the same time be both proud and humble.” Robinson (Reference Robinson, Alfano, Lynch and Tanesini2020) cites Baier (Reference Baier1991: 216), who writes: “Humility as a virtue faces a paradox, namely that the very approval of it seems to threaten to destroy the thing approved. Pride in due pride presents no paradox, and neither does shame for shame, but pride in shame and shame for pride are at best unstable, degenerate cases of reflexivity.” This is also why I have chosen to juxtapose humility and pride, which is rightly thought to be different from bragging. For a further discussion of the contrast between humility and pride, see Kellenberger (Reference Kellenberger2010).

28 Weaker versions of the unity of the virtues thesis are sometimes endorsed. See Wolf (Reference Wolf2007).

29 Roberts and Wood (Reference Roberts and Wood2007: 261–2) are a notable exception.

30 King James Version (Reference Huemer1987: Matthew 11:29).

References

Alfano, M. (Forthcoming). ‘Nietzsche on Humility and Modesty.’ In Steinberg, J. (ed.), Humility: A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alfano, M. and Robinson, B. (2014). ‘Bragging.’ Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 3(4), 263–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle. (2009). The Nicomachean Ethics. Ross, W.D. (transl.) and Brown, Lesley (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baier, A.C. (1991). A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ben-Ze'ev, A. (1993). ‘The Virtue of Modesty.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 30(3), 235–46.Google Scholar
Brennan, J. (2007). ‘Modesty Without Illusion.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75(1), 111–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bommarito, N. (2013). ‘Modesty as a Virtue of Attention.’ Philosophical Review 122(1): 93117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bommarito, N. (2018). ‘Modesty and Humility.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2018 Edition. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/modesty-humility/.Google Scholar
Chan, T. (2010). ‘Moore's Paradox is Not Just Another Pragmatic Paradox.’ Synthese 173(3), 211–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, J.L. (1950). ‘Mr. O'Connor's ‘Pragmatic Paradoxes’.’ Mind 59(223), 85–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, D.E., Placeres, V., Choe, E., DeBlaere, C., Zeyala, D. and Hook, J.N. (2017). ‘Relational Humility.’ In Worthington, E.L., Davis, D.E. and Hook, J.N. (eds), Handbook of Humility: Theory Research, and Applications, pp. 105–18. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dillon, R. (2015). ‘Humility, Arrogance, and Self-Respect in Kant and Hill.’ In Timmons, M. and Johnson, R.N. (eds), Reason, Value, and Respect, pp. 4369. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Driver, J. (1989). ‘The Virtues of Ignorance.’ Journal of Philosophy 86(7), 373–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driver, J. (2001). Uneasy Virtue. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ebersole, F.B. (1953). ‘The Definition of Pragmatic Paradox.’ Mind 62(245), 80–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, R. (2006). ‘Epistemological Puzzles about Disagreement.’ In Heatherington, S. (ed.), Epistemology Futures, pp. 216–36. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Feltz, A. and Cokely, E.T. (2012). ‘The Virtues of Ignorance.’ Review of Philosophy and Psychology 3(3), 335–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feltz, A. and Cokely, E.T. (2013). ‘Virtue or Consequences: The Folk Against Pure Evaluational Internalism.’ Philosophical Psychology 26(5), 702–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fileva, I. (2018). ‘Can Character Traits be Based on Brute Psychological Facts?’ Ratio 31(2), 233–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, O. (1990). ‘Virtue and Ignorance.’ Journal of Philosophy 87(8), 420–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garcia, J.L.A. (2006). ‘Being Unimpressed with Ourselves: Reconceiving Humility.’ Philosophia 34(4), 417–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, M.S. (2007). ‘Moorean Absurdity and Showing What's Within.’ In Green, M.S. and Williams, J.N. (eds), Moore's Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person, pp. 189214. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregg, A.P., Hart, C.M., Sedikides, C. and Kumashiro, M. (2008). ‘Everyday Conceptions of Modesty: A Prototype Analysis.’ Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 34(7), 978–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hare, S. (1996). ‘The Paradox of Moral Humility.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 33(2), 235–41.Google Scholar
Hazlett, A. (2012). ‘Higher-Order Epistemic Attitudes and Intellectual Humility.’ Episteme 9(3), 205–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilbig, B.E., Heydasch, T. and Zettler, I. (2014). ‘To Boast or Not to Boast: Testing the Humility Aspect of the Honesty–Humility Factor.’ Personality and Individual Differences 69, 1216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. (2011). ‘The Puzzle of Metacoherence.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82(1), 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. (2018). Paradox Lost: Logical Solutions to Ten Puzzles of Philosophy. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1739 [1978]). A Treatise of Human Nature. Nidditch, P.H. (ed.). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1751 [1983]). An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Schneewind, J.B. (ed.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kajonius, P.J. (2014). ‘Honesty–Humility in Contemporary Students: Manipulations of Self-Image by Inflated IQ Estimations.’ Psychological Reports 115(1), 311–25.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kant, I. (1797 [1996]). The Metaphysics of Morals. Gregor, M.J. (transl.), Guyer, P. and Wood, A.W. (eds). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kellenberger, J. (2010). ‘Humility.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 47(4), 321–36.Google Scholar
Moore, G.E. (1944). ‘Russell's Theory of Descriptions.’ In Schilpp, P.A. (ed.), The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, pp. 175205. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Morgan-Knapp, C. (2019). ‘Comparative Pride.’ Philosophical Quarterly 69(275), 315–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nietzsche, F. (1887 [2006]). On the Genealogy of Morality. Clark, M. and Swensen, A.J. (transl.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Nuyen, A.T. (1998). ‘Just Modesty.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 35(1), 101–9.Google Scholar
Peterson, C. and Seligman, M.E.P. (2004). Character Strengths and Virtues: A Handbook and Classification, Vol. 1. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Richards, N. (1988). ‘Is Humility a Virtue?' American Philosophical Quarterly 25(3), 253–9.Google Scholar
Roberts, R.C. and Wood, W.J. (2007). Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, B. (2020). ‘I Am So Humble! On the Paradoxes of Humility.’ In Alfano, M., Lynch, M. and Tanesini, A. (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Humility, pp. 2634. New York, NY: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, B. and Alfano, M. (2016). ‘I Know You Are, But What am I? Anti-Individualism in the Development of Intellectual Humility and Wu-Wei.’ Logos & Episteme 7(4), 435–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sainsbury, R.M. (2009). Paradoxes, 3rd Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidgwick, H. (1907 [1962]). The Methods of Ethics, 7th Edition. Toronto: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Sinha, G.A. (2012). ‘Modernizing the Virtue of Humility.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90(2), 259–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slote, M. (1983). Goods and Virtues. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Slote, M. (2004). ‘Driver's Virtues.’ Utilitas 16(1), 2232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snow, N.E. (2020). ‘Theories of Humility.’ In Alfano, M., Lynch, M. and Tanesini, A. (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Humility, pp. 925. New York, NY: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stahl, L. (2016). ‘The Republican Ticket: Trump and Pence.’ CBS News: 60 Minutes. 17 July 2016. https://www.cbsnews.com/news/60-minutes-trump-pence-republican-ticket/.Google Scholar
Statman, D. (1992). ‘Modesty, Pride and Realistic Self-Assessment.’ Philosophical Quarterly 42(169), 420–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tanesini, A. (2020). ‘Humility and Self-Knowledge.’ In Alfano, M., Lynch, M. and Tanesini, A. (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Humility, pp. 283–91. New York, NY: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weaver, S., Doucet, M. and Turri, J. (2017). ‘It's What's on the Inside that Counts … Or is It? Virtue and the Psychological Criteria of Modesty.’ Review of Philosophy and Psychology 8(3), 653–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1993). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana Press.Google Scholar
Wolf, S. (2007). ‘Moral Psychology and the Unity of the Virtues.’ Ratio 20(2), 145–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar