Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T03:18:25.091Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Priority of the Epistemic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 February 2020

Scott Scheall*
Affiliation:
Arizona State University, Arizona, USA
Parker Crutchfield
Affiliation:
Western Michigan University Homer Stryker M.D. School of Medicine, Michigan, USA
*
*Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]

Abstract

Epistemic burdens – the nature and extent of our ignorance (that and how) with respect to various courses of action – serve to determine our incentive structures. Courses of action that seem to bear impossibly heavy epistemic burdens are typically not counted as options in an actor's menu, while courses of action that seem to bear comparatively heavy epistemic burdens are systematically discounted in an actor's menu relative to options that appear less epistemically burdensome. That ignorance serves to determine what counts as an option means that epistemic considerations are logically prior to moral, prudential, and economic considerations: in order to have moral, prudential, or economic obligations, one must have options, and epistemic burdens serve to determine our options. One cannot have obligations without doing some epistemic work. We defend this claim on introspective grounds. We also consider how epistemic burdens distort surrogate decision-making. The unique epistemology of surrogate cases makes the priority of the epistemic readily apparent. We then argue that anyone who accepts a principle similar to ought implies can is committed to the logical priority of the epistemic. We also consider and reject several possible counterarguments.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Besch, T.A. (2011). ‘Factualism, Normativism and the Bounds of Normativity.’ Dialogue 50(2), 347–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, N. (1966). ‘Some Presuppositions of Moral Judgments.’ Mind 75(297), 4557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crutchfield, P. and Scheall, S. (2019). ‘Epistemic Burdens and the Incentives of Surrogate Decision-makers.’ Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy 22, 613–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Driver, J. (2011). ‘Promising Too Much.’ In Scheinman, H. (ed.), Promises and Agreements, pp. 183–97. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2017). ‘Should Have Known.’ Synthese 194, 2863–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hampshire, S. (1951). ‘Symposium: Freedom of the Will.’ Aristotelian Society Supplementary 25, 161–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, R.M. (1951). ‘Symposium: Freedom of the Will.’ Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 25, 201–16.Google Scholar
Hare, R.M. (1963). Freedom and Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (2009). ‘‘Ought’, ‘Can’, and Practical Reasons.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 46(4), 363–73.Google Scholar
Martin, W. (2009). ‘Ought but Cannot.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109(2), 103–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mizrahi, M. (2015). ‘Ought, Can, and Presupposition: An Experimental Study.’ Methode 4(6), 232–43.Google Scholar
Oppenheim, F.E. (1987). ‘National Interest, Rationality, and Morality.’ Political Theory 15(3), 369–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saka, P. (2000). ‘Ought Does Not Imply Can.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 37(2), 93105.Google Scholar
Scheall, S. (2019). ‘Ignorance and the Incentive Structure Confronting Policymakers.Cosmos + Taxis 7(1–2), 3951.Google Scholar
Singer, P. (1972). ‘Famine, Affluence, and Morality.’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 1(3), 229–43.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (1984). ‘Ought’ Conversationally Implies ‘Can’. Philosophical Review 93, 249–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallentyne, P. (1989). ‘Two Types of Moral Dilemmas.’ Erkenntnis 30, 301–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogelstein, E. (2012). ‘Subjective Reasons.’ Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15, 239–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar