Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-dtkg6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-06T08:02:34.004Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rationality, uncertainty, and unanimity: an epistemic critique of contractarianism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 February 2020

Alexander Schaefer*
Affiliation:
University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ, USA

Abstract

This paper considers contractarianism as a method of justification. The analysis accepts the key tenets of contractarianism: expected utility maximization, unanimity as the criteria of acceptance, and social-scientific uncertainty of modelled agents. In addition to these three features, however, the analysis introduces a fourth feature: a criteria of rational belief formation, viz. Bayesian belief updating. Using a formal model, this paper identifies a decisive objection to contractarian justification. Insofar as contractarian projects approximate the Agreement Model, therefore, they fail to justify their conclusions. Insofar as they fail to approximate the Agreement Model, they must explain which modelling assumption they reject.

Type
Article
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, S.J. 1994. The Jury: Trial and Error in the American Courtroom. New York, NY: Crown Publishing Group.Google Scholar
Asch, S.E. 1951. Effects of group pressure upon the modification and distortion of judgments. In Groups, Leadership, and Men: Research in Human Relations, ed. Guetzkow, H., 177190. New York, NY: Carnegie Press.Google Scholar
Austen-Smith, D. and Banks, J.S. 1996. Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem. American Political Science Review 90(1), 3445.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bacharach, M. 1976. Economics and the Theory of Games. London: Macmillan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bacharach, M. 1987. A theory of rational decision in games. Erkenntnis 27(1), 1755.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K. 1994 a. Game Theory and the Social Contract. Volume 1: Playing Fair. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. 1994 b. Game Theory and the Social Contract. Volume 2: Just Playing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. 2004. Reciprocity and the social contract. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 3(1), 535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K. 2005. Natural Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boettke, P.J., Coyne, C.J. and Leeson, P.T. 2011. Quasimarket failure. Public Choice 149(1), 209224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogardus, T. 2009. A vindication of the equal-weight view. Episteme 6(3), 324335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, G. and Buchanan, J.M. 2000. The Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1975. The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 2002. John Rawls, Justice as fairness: a restatement. Public Choice 113(3), 488490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. and Faith, R.L. 1980. Subjective elements in Rawlsian contractual agreement on distributional rules. Economic Inquiry 18(1), 2338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. and Tullock, G. 2004. The Calculus of Consent. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Calabresi, G. and Melamed, A.D. 1972. Property rules, liability rules, and inalienability: one view of the cathedral. Harvard Law Review 85, 10891128. Faculty Scholarship Series, 1983. https://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. 2007. Epistemology of disagreement: the good news. Philosophical Review 116(2), 187217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chung, H. 2015. Hobbes’s state of nature: a modern Bayesian game-theoretic analysis. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1(3), 485508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chung, H. 2018. Rawls’s self-defeat: a formal analysis. Erkenntnis. doi: 10.1007/s10670-018-0079-4.Google Scholar
Cohen, G.A. 2009. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cudd, A. and Eftekhari, S. 2000. Contractarianism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), ed. Zalta, E.N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/contractarianism/.Google Scholar
d’Agostino, F., Gaus, G. and Thrasher, J. 1996. Contemporary approaches to the social contract. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 Edition), ed. Zalta, E.N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/contractarianism-contemporary/.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2008. Contractarianism/Contractualism. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1973. The original position. The University of Chicago Law Review 40(3), 500533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elga, A. 2007. Reflection and disagreement. Noûs 41(3), 478502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feddersen, T.J. and Pesendorfer, W. 1996. The swing voter’s curse. American Economic Review 86, 408424.Google Scholar
Feddersen, T. and Pesendorfer, W. 1998. Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts under strategic voting. American Political Science Review 92(1), 2335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feddersen, T. and Pesendorfer, W. 1999. Elections, information aggregation, and strategic voting. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 96(19), 1057210574.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gaus, G. 2008. On Philosophy, Politics, and Economics. Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2010. The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, G. 2013. Hobbesian contractarianism, orthodox and revisionist. In The Bloomsbury Companion to Hobbes, ed. Lloyd, S., 263278. New York, NY: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2016. The Tyranny of the Ideal: Justice in a Diverse Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. and Thrasher, J. 2016. Rational choice in the original position: the (many) models of Rawls and Harsanyi. In The Original Position, ed. Hinton, T., 3958. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1969. The Logic of Leviathan: The Moral and Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 2013. Twenty-five on. Ethics 123(4), 601624.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hampton, J. 1988. Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harsanyi, J.C. 1967. Games with incomplete information played by “Bayesian” players, i–iii. Management Science 14(3), 159182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D.M. 1992. The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D.M., ed. 1994. Why look under the hood. In The Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology, 217221. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, D.M. 2003. Rational belief and social interaction. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26(2), 163164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirschman, A.O. 1970. Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. 1991. Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. 2013. The Problem of Political Authority. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. 1978. A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Selby-Bigge, L.A.. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Kalven, H. Jr and Zeisel, H. 1966. The American Jury. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1996. Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kavka, G.S. 1986. Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Knight, F.H. 1971. Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kreps, D.M. 2012. Microeconomic Foundations I: Choice and Competitive Markets, Volume 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kreps, D.M. and Wilson, R. 1982. Sequential equilibria. Econometrica 50, 863894.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kukathas, C. 2003. The Liberal Archipelago: A Theory of Diversity and Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kymlicka, W. 1991. Liberalism, Community, and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K. 1976. When rational disagreement is impossible. Noûs 10, 327332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, J.P. 1992. Juries and Politics. Boston, MA: Brooks/Cole Publishing.Google Scholar
Locke, J. 1980. Second Treatise of Government. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Google Scholar
Loungani, P. 2001. How accurate are private sector forecasts? cross-country evidence from consensus forecasts of output growth. International Journal of Forecasting 17(3), 419432.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mas-Colell, A., Whinston, M.D. and Green, J.R. 1995. Microeconomic Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Matheson, J. 2015. Disagreement and the ethics of belief. In The Future of Social Epistemology: A Collective Vision, ed. Collier, J., 139148. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Matheson, J. and Frances, B. 2018. Disagreement. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 Edition), ed. Zalta, E.N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/disagreement/.Google Scholar
McCart, S.W. 1964. Trial by Jury: A Complete Guide to the Jury System. Boston, MA: Chilton Books.Google Scholar
Moehler, M. 2010. The (stabilized) Nash bargaining solution as a principle of distributive justice. Utilitas 22(4), 447473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moehler, M. 2018. Minimal Morality: A Multilevel Social Contract Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muldoon, R. 2016. Social Contract Theory for a Diverse World: Beyond Tolerance. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C., Colyvan, M., Martini, C., Sillari, G. and Sprenger, J. 2014. Disagreement behind the veil of ignorance. Philosophical Studies 170(3), 377394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakeshott, M. 1965. Rationalism in Politics and other Essays. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Ostrom, E. 2008 a. Tragedy of the commons. In The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics (2nd edn), ed. Durlauf, S.N. and Blume, L.E.. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Ostrom, V. 2008 b. The Intellectual Crisis in American Public Administration. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.Google Scholar
Poincaré, H. 1920. Science et Méthode. Paris: Ernest Flammarion, Éditeur. Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2008. Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2009. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Robert, N. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Rubinstein, A. 1982. Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model. Econometrica 50, 97109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schmidtz, D. 1990. Justifying the state. Ethics 101(1), 89102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A.J. 1979. Moral Principles and Political Obligations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Southwood, N. 2009. Moral contractualism. Philosophy Compass 4(6), 926937.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thrasher, J. 2019. Constructivism, representation, and stability: path-dependence in public reason theories of justice. Synthese 196(1), 429450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vanderschraaf, P. 2006. War or peace? A dynamical analysis of anarchy. Economics and Philosophy 22(2), 243279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, C. and Lehrer, K. 1981. Rational Consensus in Science and Society. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Wit, J. 1998. Rational choice and the Condorcet jury theorem. Games and Economic Behavior 22(2), 364376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar