Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T23:32:03.282Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Paternalism and Public Policy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Bill New
Affiliation:
London School of Economics

Extract

Wherever a government or state is concerned with the welfare of its citizens, there will probably also exist policies which compel the individual citizen to undertake or abstain from activities which affect that citizen alone. The set of theories behind such policies is collectively known as ‘paternalism’. It is not hard to understand why this term has developed strong pejorative overtones. Policies of this type appear to offend a fundamental tenet of liberal societies: namely, that the individual is best placed to know what is in his or her interests. Paternalistic policies imply, and are concerned with correcting, failures of precisely this kind of judgement. And yet, at the same time, there is a popular consensus that compelling people to wear a seat belt when driving a car is a reasonable restriction of personal liberty. Paternalism may be difficult to accept in principle, but it is equally difficult to avoid in practice.

Not surprisingly, the literature reveals a long heritage of debate in a wide range of academic disciplines. This debate reveals a failure to make progress in two areas in particular. First, analyses of paternalism often confuse policies which are actually concerned with correcting failures of market exchange — in particular, those concerned with insufficient or imperfect information — with those which are genuinely paternalistic. One objective of this paper will be to clarify the difference between these two kinds of policy.

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Archard, David. 1993. ‘Self-justifying paternalism’, Journal of Value Inquiry, 27:341–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, Michael, Butler, Eammon, Marsland, David and Pirie, Madsen. 1994. The End of the Welfare State. Adam Smith Institute, LondonGoogle Scholar
Brennan, Geoffrey. 1990. ‘Why There Is a Coherent ‘Merit Goods’ Argument’. Rationality, Individuality and Public Policy. In Brennan, G. and Walsh, Cliff (eds.). Centre for Research on Federal Financial Relations, CanberraGoogle Scholar
Burrows, Paul. 1993. ‘Patronising paternalism’. Oxford Economic Papers, 45:542–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burrows, Paul. 1995. ‘Analysing legal paternalism’. International Review of Law and Economics, 15:489508CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. Harper & RowGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Gerald. 1979. ‘Paternalism’. In Philosophy, Politics and Society: Fifth Series. Laslett, Peter and Fishkin, James (eds.). Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Gerald. 1981. ‘Paternalism and welfare policy’. In Income Support: Conceptual and Policy Issues. Brown, Peter, Johnson, Conrad, and Vernier, Paul (eds.). Rowman and LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1989. ‘Liberal community’. California Law Review, 77:479504CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1983. ‘Legal Paternalism’. In Paternalism. Sartorius, R. (ed.). University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to Self. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Gert, Bernard and Culver, Charles. 1976. ‘Paternalistic behavior’. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6:4557Google ScholarPubMed
Goodin, Robert. 1993. ‘Democracy, preferences and paternalism’. Policy Sciences, 26:229–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, Robert. 1995a. ‘Liberalism and the Best-Judge Principle’. In Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy. Goodin, Robert (ed.). Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, Robert. 1995b. ‘Laundering preferences’. In Utilitarianism As A Public Philosophy. Goodin, Robert (ed.). Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gravelle, Hugh and Rees, Ray. 1981. Microeconomics. LongmanGoogle Scholar
Hart, Herbert L. A. 1963. Law, Liberty, and Morality. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelman, Steven. 1981. ‘Regulation and paternalism’. Public Policy, 29:219–54Google ScholarPubMed
Kleinig, John. 1983. Paternalism. Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar
Le Grand, Julian. 1995. ‘The Market, the State, and the Distribution of Life Cycle Income’. In The Dynamic of Welfare: The Welfare State and the Life Cycle. Falkingham, Jane and Hills, John (eds.). Prentice Hall/Harvester WheatsheafGoogle Scholar
McLean, Iain. 1987. Public Choice: An Introduction. Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1974. On Liberty. Penguin BooksGoogle Scholar
Niskanen, William. 1971. Bureaucracy and Representative Government. Aldine-AthertonGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State and Utopia. Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1977. ‘Rational Fools: a critique of the behavioral foundations of economic theory’. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 6:317–44Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1988. ‘Freedom of choice: concept and content’. European Economic Review, 32:269–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Damiel. 1982. ‘Judgement Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases’. In Judgement Under Uncertainty. Slovic, Kahneman, and Tversky, (eds.). Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
VanDeVeer, Donald. 1986. Paternalistic Intervention: The Moral Bounds of Benevolence. Princeton University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weale, Albert. 1978. ‘Paternalism and social policy’. Journal of Social Policy, 7:157–72CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Williamson, Oliver. 1985. The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting. The Free PressGoogle Scholar