Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-18T21:20:18.711Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Fair equality of chances for prediction-based decisions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 November 2023

Michele Loi*
Affiliation:
Politecnico di Milano, Milano, MI, Italy
Anders Herlitz
Affiliation:
Institute for Futures Studies, Stockholm, Sweden Department of Philosophy, Lund University, Lund, Sweden
Hoda Heidari
Affiliation:
Machine Learning Department, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA, USA
*
Corresponding author: Michele Loi; Email: [email protected]; URL: www.micheleloi.eu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article presents a fairness principle for evaluating decision-making based on predictions: a decision rule is unfair when the individuals directly impacted by the decisions who are equal with respect to the features that justify inequalities in outcomes do not have the same statistical prospects of being benefited or harmed by them, irrespective of their socially salient morally arbitrary traits. The principle can be used to evaluate prediction-based decision-making from the point of view of a wide range of antecedently specified substantive views about justice in outcome distributions.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

In his biography of Thelonious Monk, the celebrated historian Robin D.G. Kelley told of a dream he once had that has become stock and trade in the conversations of jazz musicians. Apparently, Kelley, whose stepfather was a professional sax player and who played bass and piano as a young man, spent months trying to imitate Monk’s sound, which was famous for its up-tempo and dissonant style. Then, one day, Monk appeared to Kelley in the infamous dream and uttered the words every professional jazz player has heard at least once in their lifetime: ‘you are making the wrong mistakes’ (Kelley Reference Kelley2010).

Similar to jazz in Monk’s view, fairness is sometimes concerned with avoiding the ‘wrong’ mistakes, not with avoiding mistakes altogether. This is especially true of decisions based on statistical predictions. This idea of avoiding the wrong mistakes requires building a new type of theory, which involves two layers. In the first layer, wrong mistakes are characterized as mistakes, that is, as morally unjust outcomes. In the second, they are characterized as unfair mistakes, that is, morally unjust outcomes of procedures that have the tendency to affect socially salient groups in unequal ways. We have two goals in this article: first, to present a principle that can identify those mistakes that are unfair toward groups, and second, to show that this principle can guide the choice of some statistical fairness constraints, discussed mainly in the computer science community, in a way that is sensitive to some specific moral features of the decision context.

The principle we present is fair equality of chances, or FEC. The principle characterizes – in a formal and general way – how different (just or unjust) decisions must impact groups defined by socially salient characteristics in order for a decision rule to be unfair. In a nutshell, the principle requires that no inequality between groups emerges after conditioning on the feature, or set of features, that provides a valid moral justification of outcome inequality in the morally relevant outcomes produced by the procedure.

FEC applies to procedures, such as predictive procedures, that are not pure. Pure procedures do not rely on any prior definition of just outcomes (Rawls Reference Rawls1999). For example, a fair electoral procedure does not presuppose that justice will be achieved by electing a Democratic or Republican president. By contrast, the procedures to which FEC applies are used to make imperfect decisions as a means to achieve a just or justifiable distribution, where a definition of a just (or justified) distribution is given in advance. On one possible view, procedures that are a means to (independently defined) just outcome distributions are maximally just when they maximize the proportion of justly distributed outcomes. However, we argue that a procedure can be maximally just, in the sense just described and, at the same time, unfair toward groups. FEC specifies the conditions that must obtain in order for a procedure to count as fair toward different socially salient groups. These conditions cannot be defined by appealing to a single statistical criterion, for example, that the proportion or probability of errors must be the same for all groups, as we shall show. To identify a valid statistical criterion, a moral criterion has to be invoked.

The article is structured as follows. In section 2, we illustrate the tension between different statistical fairness criteria with an example. In section 3, we sharpen the conflict by providing some mathematical notation and a corresponding nomenclature. In section 4, we introduce the basic concepts of a new theory that provides a criterion for determining if a statistical fairness criterion is required by fairness. In section 5, we formulate the FEC principle. In section 6, we briefly present one intuitive argument for its justification – the other argument is produced by the coherence of the overall scheme. Section 7 shows that two of the most widely discussed statistical fairness criteria, that is, separation and sufficiency, correspond to mutually incompatible interpretations of the principle of FEC. This is a mathematical proof formulated in ordinary English – the formal argument is presented in the Appendix. In section 8, we apply this interpretation to two examples. There is a brief concluding section.

2. The Problem

Let us start with a concrete example. We draw this example from Long (Reference Long2021), with minimal variation. Assume that 606 students have submitted exam papers to a course. Of these, 303 are from Buddhist students and 303 from Muslim ones. There are only two grades in the course, A and B, and we suppose that final papers could have the property of being a ‘true’ A paper or a ‘true’ B paper – the property of objectively deserving an A or a B. We shall call this property the ‘true label’, indicated with Y.

You follow the recommendations of an algorithm that, just like a real teacher, is a moderately fallible grader. We shall call the grade you give the ‘predicted label’, indicated with $\hat Y$ (Table 1). We assume, for argument’s sake, that 300 Buddhist students are graded with a B, but only three Muslim students receive this grade; the group of individuals who obtained an A consists of 300 Muslims and only three Buddhists. Your accuracy as a grader is described in Tables 2 and 3. We suppose that this accuracy is measured through a hypothetically independent test that is perfectly accurate in determining the true grade of each paper.

Table 1. Confusion table and predictive accuracy

Note: Generally speaking, we use a confusion table to represent the performance and fairness of a predictor for the general population. In binary classification, separation (the condition that the prediction is independent of group membership conditioned on the true label) is equivalent to the equality of false-positive and false-negative rates (i.e. b/(b+d) and c/(c+a), respectively) across groups. This quantity is also referred to as an equality of odds (Hardt et al. Reference Hardt, Price and Srebro2016). Sufficiency (the condition that the true label is independent of the group membership conditioned on the prediction) is equivalent to the equality of positive and negative predictive values (i.e. a/(a+b) and d/(c+d), respectively) across groups; it can be thought of as a special form of calibration.

Table 2. Confusion table of the grader’s performance in the Buddhist population

Table 3. Confusion table of the grader’s performance in the Muslim population

Let us assess the performance of the same predictor on the two different groups. We start by reading the table column-wise. The true positive rate, a/(a+c), is 2/102 (approx. 0.02) for Buddhists, meaning that out of 102 students with true A papers, only two of this population are classified correctly; this is the population of Buddhist true positive papers. The proportion of correctly judged A papers, the Muslim true positive papers, is much higher in the Muslim population. In the group of Buddhist true negatives, that is, Buddhist students actually delivering true B papers, the sensitivity of the predictor is much higher: out of 201 Buddhists with true B papers, 200 are correctly classified as such (200/201, approx. 0.99). Conversely, the Muslim true negative rate is much lower – that is, more B papers are erroneously marked with an A; the fact that there is also a difference in the false positive (b/(b+d)) and false negative (c/(c+a)) rates follows from the fact that these are equal to (1−true negative rate) and (1−true positive rate), respectively.

Notice that this apparently unbalanced performance of the predictor is compatible with the predictive value of the predictor being identical for both groups. This can be shown by reading the table row-wise. The likelihood of a true positive, given a positive prediction (a/(a+b)), is ⅔ for Buddhists. The likelihood of a true negative, given a negative prediction (d/(c+d)), is also ⅔. These are the same proportions in the Muslim population; obviously, the predictor is a significant improvement on an uninformed guess.

The result is that, in spite of your grades having the same probability of being correct independently of the religion of the student, Muslim students submitting B papers are much more likely to receive an A (on average) than Buddhist students and this distinction is the same in respect of A papers. This may be seen as Muslims having an advantage over Buddhists, even though the negative and positive predictive values are the same – that is, you are equally likely to be correct when you classify a paper as a B paper and when you classify a paper as an A paper, irrespective of the religion of the student.

The example above illustrates the dilemmatic choice that must be made when one assesses the fairness of a decision rule based on statistical predictions. On the one hand, the predictor is equally accurate for both groups and for both types of errors (false positives and false negatives). On the other hand, the errors for the two groups, conditional on the true labels, are unequally distributed. Both considerations are prima facie relevant to adjudicating the fairness of a decision based on this prediction.Footnote 1 Thus, violating either seems to provide grounds for those who wish to criticize the predictor as unfair.

3. Sharpening the Conflict

Prediction-based decision-making is a two-step process (making a prediction based on some features, and then taking a decision based on the prediction). But for simplicity, we assume a direct link between positive/negative decisions, D, and the positive/negative predictions leading to those.

There are a few denominations in mathematics for the two fairness criteria at stake. Here, we shall refer to them as sufficiency and separation. Sufficiency and separation are often defined in terms of the conditional probabilities of correct and incorrect predictions relative to the true label. We choose the formulation in terms of the relation between outcomes and decisions (Barocas and Selbst Reference Barocas and Selbst2016) because we assume here that what can be fair and unfair is a decision, not a prediction in itself. We can thus simplify the discussion somewhat by stipulating that a prediction of A-paper ( $\hat Y$ =1) corresponds to a decision to provide the grade A (D=1), and vice versa (that is, $\hat Y$ =0 implies and is implied by D=0).

Sufficiency can be expressed, then, as the requirement that the group one belongs to, A, should not influence the likelihood of a true label, Y, for any individual about whom the same decision, D, is made. In our final formulation:

Sufficiency: Individuals about whom the same decision D is made have the same expectations of the true label, Y, that is, the same statistical prospects of being a true positive, regardless of their group membership, and the same statistical prospects of being a true negative, regardless of their group membership.

This is the statistical condition that the decision rule in the example in the previous section initially satisfies. The probability that a paper will be correctly graded B is the same irrespective of the group to which it belongs. The probability that a paper will be correctly graded A is also the same irrespective of the group to which it belongs.

The statistical condition of separation, on the other hand, represents the idea that individuals with the same true label (e.g. those who, according to the objective features of the paper, merit an A) are equally likely to receive the same decision (e.g. receive an A grade). In other words, one splits the population into different categories that correspond to the true labels (e.g. A papers, B papers), and then one requires that group membership (e.g. religion) is irrelevant to the statistical prospects of either decision:

Separation: Individuals with the same true label Y have the same expectations of positive or negative decision D; that is, true positives have the same statistical prospects of a positive decision, and true negatives have the same statistical prospects of a negative decision, regardless of their group membership.

If separation is met, the probability that a paper deserving an A receives an A is the same irrespective of the group to which it belongs, and the probability that a paper deserving a B receives a B is the same irrespective of the group to which it belongs.

As pointed out in the previous section, it is logically impossible for a decision process to meet both these conditions unless the decision process is perfectly accurate or the distribution of the trait of interest is equal across subgroups. That is, sufficiency and separation can both be met only if (i) the predictor with perfect accuracy identifies A and B papers or (ii) writing A papers and writing B papers is equally common among Buddhists and Muslims. In all other situations, a decision process can meet sufficiency or separation, but not both (Chouldechova Reference Chouldechova2017; Kleinberg et al. Reference Kleinberg, Mullainathan and Raghavan2017; Berk et al. Reference Berk, Heidari, Shahin, Kearns and Roth2021; Fazelpour and Danks Reference Fazelpour and Danks2021).

In the following section, we introduce a principle that provides a link between the general conception of fairness we defend – FEC – and sufficiency and separation.

Our aim is to present a conception of fairness that – considering the below-stated limitations – can (contribute to) guide policymakers in the inevitable choice between sufficiency and separation. Assuming that our theory – FEC – defines what is fair in the domain of decision rules based on statistical predictions, we show that violating sufficiency is unfair if and only if a specific set of moralFootnote 2 and prudentialFootnote 3 conditions are satisfied, while violating separation is unfair if and only if another specific set of moral and prudential conditions are satisfied. When neither set of moral and prudential conditions are satisfied, neither sufficiency nor separation can be considered to be equivalent (i.e. reducible) to the fairness principle we identify.Footnote 4

Even if it turns out that FEC rarely justifies using sufficiency or separation as criteria of fairness, we do not regard this as a weakness of our theory. FEC may most often imply that satisfying neither sufficiency nor separation is relevant for fairness. That negative conclusion is also a valuable moral insight that can be derived from it. It may be entirely coherent with the critique of small-scale ideal theorizing (Lipton and Fazelpour Reference Lipton and Fazelpour2020) and it may further support the view that current statistical criteria are not applicable (Lipton and Fazelpour Reference Lipton and Fazelpour2020).

4. Building up to Fair Equality of Chances

To achieve some terminological clarity, in what follows, we shall use the expression ‘fair’ to describe an intuitively morally desirable feature of procedures (yet to be characterized) and ‘just’ to describe outcomes that are desirable from the viewpoint of justice, when justice is defined independently of any procedural consideration. Our theory takes justice to be a distribution according to desert*, where we take desert* to be anything that justifies outcome inequality (in a procedure-independent sense). Desert* could refer to needs (Wiggins Reference Wiggins1987; Herlitz and Horan Reference Herlitz and Horan2016), responsibility (Arneson Reference Arneson1989; Roemer Reference Roemer1993), or, indeed, desert (Feldman Reference Feldman2016; Brouwer and Mulligan Reference Brouwer and Mulligan2019), depending on what your favourite view of justice happens to be. FEC is, in fact, compatible with the justification of inequalities being context-dependent (Miller Reference Miller1999).Footnote 5

Thus, the first element of our framework is:

1. Justifier. The value of J measures the degree to which the individual deserves* the good (advantage or disadvantage, measured as U) a procedure allocates to them.Footnote 6

The value of J is a function of the properties that make that individual deserving* (desert* properties), such as the individual’s needs, responsibility, and contribution, which are answers to substantive moral questions delivered by theories other than FEC.Footnote 7

Mathematically speaking, we use J to indicate potentially multidimensional, continuous random variables. For simplicity, we will restrict attention to one-dimensional, ordinal J, for example, a person’s contribution or need, as defined by a single ordinal value (e.g. any two individuals are either equally deserving, or one is more deserving than the other). When the random variable J takes the same values for two or more individuals, the individuals in question are described as being equally deserving*.

The introduction of the concept of desert*, although abstract and unsubstantiated, is necessary because FEC must operate at a different level of abstraction from most theories of justice. FEC aims to characterize a dimension of the unfairness of imperfect procedures. Imperfect procedures, by definition, aim to realize a just distribution, where justice is defined for outcomes in advance of the procedure itself (Rawls Reference Rawls1999). By specifying FEC in terms of desert* (as opposed to effort, substantive desert, or need, etc.), we are able to characterize, at an abstract level, the relation between outcome justice and procedural fairness in a way that is independent of specific (and contentious) premises about outcome justice.

If ‘unfair’ simply means ‘produces undeserved* inequalities’ (or equivalently, ‘unjust outcomes’), every procedure that is imperfect is necessarily unfair. Ideally, outcome inequalities should track desert* inequalities perfectly.Footnote 8 Yet, by definition, only a perfect procedure allocates advantages and disadvantages according to what each individual deserves*. Imperfect procedures will sometimes permit that individuals, equal in desert*, will receive unequal outcomes. For example, while the majority of guilty individuals are convicted, and the majority of innocent individuals are acquitted, some guilty individuals are acquitted, and some innocent individuals are convicted. These individuals do not have exactly the same features; for example, they may be born on different days or be judged at different moments in time. So, there will typically always be individuals (in the case of imperfect procedures) who are equal in their desert* (e.g. they are both innocent), who differ in non-desert* traits (e.g. the moment at which they are judged), and who receive different outcomes (Di Bello and O’Neil Reference Di Bello and O’Neil2020).

This is a problem because a principle of fairness for imperfect procedures should be able to say that a decision procedure that is more advantageous for White people than for Black people in the United States is unfair. And if it is to be applicable to imperfect procedures, it must also be able to say that a decision procedure that disproportionately benefits people born on uneven dates (e.g. 1st, 3rd and 5th of every month) may not be, for that reason, unfair. For example, on a need-based theory of justice, anything that is not need is not desert*. Relative to need, the fact that one is born on an odd day is as morally arbitrary as being a woman. In other words, given a theory of justice determining desert*, every feature that is not desert* is morally arbitrary and, as a matter of principle, equally so.

We introduce the concept of a morally arbitrary* property, that is, morally arbitrary with a * sign, to signify a feature that is not desert*, and that, in addition, identifies a socially salient group:

a group is socially salient if perceived membership of it is important to the structure of social interactions across a wide range of social contexts. (Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2007)

We, therefore, define a second variable, G, that takes the value of the morally arbitrary* property of an individual that corresponds to the socially salient group to which that individual belongs. When a combination of independent, morally arbitrary* properties (e.g. gender and race) is distinctively socially salient, then the relevant intersectional groups (e.g. White male) could be considered instead.Footnote 9

2. Group. The random value G indicates a property (or combination of properties) of the individual that is not desert* and that is socially salient in the society affected by the procedure under evaluation.

Again, we use G to indicate potentially multidimensional, continuous random variables. Note that categorical variables are subsumed by continuous variables, so this does not restrict the definition of G in any way. For simplicity, we will restrict attention to categorical values, for example, female or male, Black or White, and so on. When the random variable G takes the same values for two or more individuals, the individuals in question are described as belonging to the same morally arbitrary* group.

Notice further that the definition of desert* explicitly mentions U, which is the chosen metric for measuring advantageous and disadvantageous outcomes. When Definitions 2 and 3 refer to inequalities, what is intended thereby is also an inequality in the distribution of U. This gives us the third and last element in the framework:

Utility* indicated with U. The value of U measures the advantage or disadvantage of individuals resulting from the allocation of goods by the procedure in question.Footnote 10

We use utility* as shorthand for outcomes that are in any way beneficial or harmful, advantageous or disadvantageous for individuals. In the example of the grader, receiving an A could amount to one unit of utility for the individual, while receiving a B could amount to 0.5,Footnote 11 capturing the belief that the benefit of every individual from receiving an A is twice that of the benefit from receiving a B. The star in utility* indicates that utility* is not ‘utility’ in the strict sense of well-being or what is good for a person. Utility* can also be regarded as a social primary good (Rawls Reference Rawls1999) or capability (Sen Reference Sen1995), following Roemer (Reference Roemer1993).

This agnosticism is not a means to broaden the applicability of FEC in practice. It is a principled demand for a theory of imperfect procedural justice. The nature of U is implied by how just outcomes are defined, in the theory characterizing the goal of the procedure as just.Footnote 12

Morally arbitrary* properties have been defined as those properties that are not desert* and that are socially salient. Clearly, it is logically possible that a property that is not desert* is not socially salient. For example, the fact that one is born on an odd or even day does not usually justify treating people unequally. But it is also not socially salient. If a procedure is imperfect, it is possible that some inequalities emerge, by virtue of its application, among people who are equal in their deserts* but different in those traits. For example, innocent people born on an odd date are more often acquitted than those born on an even date. We shall refer to these traits as luck*. Or equivalently:

3. Luck*, anything other than G that impacts U but cannot be explained by J.

We believe that the following view of fairness is intuitively plausible. Every inequality in utility* between people who are equally deserving* is unjust. But procedures generating such inequalities are not necessarily unfair. If equally deserving members of groups, irrelevant from the point of view of social salience, have unequal expectations of utility*, an imperfect procedure may still be fair even if it is only imperfectly just. That is to say, an imperfect procedure can distribute benefits unequally between equally deserving* individuals who differ in luck* and still be fair.

The intuition modelled by FEC is that, in order to be fair, luck* has to be neutral relative to the groups that are socially salient, that is, morally arbitrary*. A procedure generating inequality due to luck* ought not to have a disposition to favour one morally arbitrary* group over any other (in the context in which it operates), where the relevant inequalities are within classes defined by equality of desert*. Yet, it is possible for some individuals to be lucky* and receive better treatment from the procedure than other equally deserving individuals. For example, it may turn out that individuals born on even days are more likely to obtain some good that they deserve*, compared with equally deserving* individuals born on odd days. This may happen if being born on an even day correlates with some indicator that is used by the procedure to make accurate predictions and efficient decisions. This can be fair if, despite the imbalance across the two birthday classes, no morally arbitrary* (that is, socially salient) group is advantaged relative to any other.

A formal definition of luck* neutrality has been offered in an attempt to characterize the ‘Rawlsian’ idea of equality of opportunity mathematically (Lefranc et al. Reference Lefranc, Pistolesi and Trannoy2009). The label of luck* neutrality to denote this condition of statistical independence is indeed such a proposal:

Luck* neutrality: Luck* is neutral if and only if for individuals with the same desert* value, J, expectations of utility, U, do not statistically depend on their G.

The mathematical formulation of luck* neutrality assumes E to be the expectation value given a known probability distribution of utility* (U). Luck* is neutral if and only if ∀(g,g′) ∀ j, E(U|g,j)=E(U|g′,j). The expected value of U is allowed to covary with J. But, keeping J fixed (i.e. when J is at a given value j), utility is required not to covary with G.Footnote 13 This is what makes luck* neutral.

So far, we have presented the following building blocks for a theory of (imperfect) prediction-based decisions:

  1. 1. Justifier (J). The value of J measures the degree to which the individual deserves* the advantage or disadvantage a procedure allocates to him or her.

  2. 2. Group (G). The random value G indicates a property (or combination of properties) of the individual that is not desert* and that is socially salient in the society affected by the procedure under evaluation.

  3. 3. Utility* (U). The value of U measures the advantage or disadvantage of individuals resulting from the allocation of goods by the procedure in question.

  4. 4. Luck*.Footnote 14 Anything other than G that impacts U but cannot be explained by J.

The theory assumes that the desert* properties, morally arbitrary* group membership, and utility* distributed to individuals by a procedure can be described by possible values of the variables J, G and U. Even if one allows these variables to be multidimensional, continuous random variables, quantification itself may be thought to involve a radical simplification or gross approximation of the relevant moral facts. We suppose that there may be cases in which such approximation is plausible and justifiable;Footnote 15 to some extent, it is hardly avoidable if one is attempting to make sense of statistical fairness definitions expressed in mathematical language from the moral point of view.

5. Fair Equality of Chances

It is now possible to succinctly express our view of the fairness of imperfect procedures. We defend a view of imperfect procedural fairness which, loosely stated, claims that a procedure is unfair if it allocates advantages and disadvantages to the predictable advantage or disadvantage of certain groups, across classes of equally deserving* individuals. Let us clarify this definition.

First, we defend a principle that is a necessary but not sufficient condition of procedural fairness. Several philosophers have discussed procedural justice by invoking criteria whose justification is independent of the value attached to the goals the procedure is intended to achieve.Footnote 16 Our theory is agnostic with respect to the question of whether the procedural justice of imperfect procedures ought to be sensitive to any procedural consideration that can be expressed fully independently from an already given conception of distributive (outcome) justice. Since the existence of other necessary conditions of procedural fairness cannot be ruled out a priori, however, our account of fairness (FEC) will not be defended as a necessary and sufficient condition of procedural justice. Thus, we only claim that FEC represents a necessary condition for the fairness of imperfect procedures. That is:

T1 (necessary condition for procedural fairness): an imperfect procedure (including an imperfect prediction-based decision rule) is fair only if it satisfies the FEC principle.

T2 (definition of FEC): an imperfect procedure satisfies FEC if and only if luck* is neutral,

which can be rewritten as:

T2’: an imperfect procedure satisfies FEC if and only if ∀(g,g′) ∀ j, E(U|g,j)=E(U|g′,j)),

or equivalently:

T2”: an imperfect procedure satisfies FEC if and only if individuals equal in their values for J have the same expectations of having U, irrespective of their G values.Footnote 17

If one replaces the variables J, U and G, with the vocabulary introduced above, what we get is the informal statement of FEC:

T2’”: an imperfect procedure satisfies FEC if equally deserving* individuals have the same expectations of utility*, irrespective of their morally arbitrary* traits.

One implication of T2 is that, no matter its other virtues, an imperfect procedure that does not satisfy FEC counts as necessarily (procedurally) unfair. This provides us with an empirically testable condition of the fairness of a procedure given settled values for features in J, G and U (at least, for a particular context). In particular, when the relevant type of data exists for J, G and U, it may allow one to test a statistical procedure for its fairness. The fairness of prediction-based decisions does not require perfectly just outcomes: this is a plausible contention if justice ideally requires perfect predictions, since statistical methods are rarely, if ever, perfectly accurate.

One implication of this theory is that outcome justice and procedural fairness are related but distinct. The theory applies, in a way that we find plausible, to decision-making procedures other than those based on statistical predictions. For example, a random lottery is procedurally fair according to FEC no matter what counts as morally arbitrary*. Yet, FEC is compatible with claiming that lotteries typically promote injustice (individuals end up with advantages or disadvantages that are clearly undeserved*). Conversely, a procedure may minimize the amount of injustice and be unfair, in so far as it tends to produce undeserved* advantages for (members of) some morally arbitrary* groups in imbalanced proportions. A fair prediction-based decision rule may be feasible, at least when considering a limited number of morally arbitrary* groups. For example, if gender is the only morally arbitrary* property, a prediction-based decision is only required to generate no statistically significant inequalities between equally deserving* men and women. This procedure may generate a greater proportion of unjust outcomes than the most just (but unfair) feasible procedure, but a smaller proportion of unjust outcomes than a purely random one.

Let us now deal with two distinct objections that can be raised against our account. Our definition of FEC, as shown, builds on Lefranc et al.’s (Reference Lefranc, Pistolesi and Trannoy2009) idea of ‘neutral luck’, something which neither justifies inequality morally nor has to be corrected for the outcome to be fully just.Footnote 18

The idea of the fair distribution of chances is of course not new in ethics and political philosophy. But the widely discussed approach of John Broome (Reference Broome1984), for example, implies a far stronger requirement, than either sufficiency or separation. Broome conceives fairness to require equal chances of X among those individuals who have equally strong claims to X, when it is impossible to distribute X equally. Thus, Broome’s idea is satisfied by lotteries, which give every individual who participates in them, exactly the same chances, at the individual level. According to Sune Holm (Reference Holm2023) sufficiency and separation can be justified when they realize Broomean conditions of fairness.

If Holm’s view is correct, however, there is little hope that fairness consists in either. Broomean fairness is far stronger than equality in the true positive or false positive rate, for example (Castro and Loi Reference Castro and Loi2023). In the example provided at the beginning of this article, Broomean fair chances require that all individuals with a ‘true A’ paper have, individually, the same chances of ending up with an A. But this is not guaranteed by equality in the false positive rate or even by equality in the false positive and in the false negative rate. These are compatible with individuals having very different chances of receiving an A, provided that these inequalities compensate each other at the group level (Castro and Loi Reference Castro and Loi2023).

The Broomean account is very unlikely to bridge the gap between the statistical measures of group fairness in use and our intuitions about what is just or fair. After all, most algorithmic decisions are not randomized but deterministic, given individual (input) features (Castro and Loi Reference Castro and Loi2023). So, our non-Broomean approach, which relies on a different conceptualization of fair chances,Footnote 19 provides an interesting alternative.

Second, it may be objected that FEC is too strong to count as a necessary condition for imperfect procedural fairness. Consider the case discussed in section 1, in which the unequal false positive rate is due to the proportion of true A papers among young Buddhist students being lower than the proportion of true A papers among young Muslim students. In our account, this is not an instance of neutral luck, even if the unequal (average) prospects of the two types of students are not caused by their religious-group memberships. For example, suppose that the grader is less able to adequately rate the papers of young students compared with older students, and the age distribution of the two religious groups differs. This leads to a difference in the proportion of objectively good ‘A’ papers that are classified as ‘B’ papers (Beigang Reference Beigang2023). The non-neutrality of the grader (given the distribution of age in the different religious groups) is morally significant, provided that the correlation between age and the socially salient trait ‘religion’ is a robust, structural fact about the society in which the grader lives.Footnote 20 As the groups are morally arbitrary*, and therefore socially salient, this non-neutrality may produce inequalities between the two groups that are reasons for moral concern, as we discuss next.

6. The Intuitive Justification of FEC

It is important to stress that FEC requires equal expectations of utility among equally deserving* individuals who belong to different morally arbitrary* groups, where groups that are morally arbitrary* are also socially salient by definition. The justification of FEC is that when groups are socially salient, group inequality matters, at least pro tanto. It is not the purpose of this article to provide a foundational argument for the view that group inequality matters as such, from the moral point of view. The justification we offer here is rather minimalist, and it involves two different modes of justification:

  1. (a) an appeal to intuitions;

  2. (b) coherence in wide reflective equilibrium (Rawls Reference Rawls1999: 199) between this view and plausible intuitions about the cases of prediction-based decisions discussed in sections 7 and 8.

Here we provide the intuitive argument; the reflective equilibrium argument is delivered by the article as a whole. The intuitive argument is as follows. Suppose that we have two groups that are socially salient, for example, in the US, White people and Black people. It turns out that there is an avoidable unjustified inequality in the distribution of some goods between the two. Notice that we are not implying that the distribution is due to race. Simply, there is an inequality between the two races, as groups, that, by hypothesis, is not justified. For example, the rate at which innocent Black men are convicted is 30 per cent, while the rate at which innocent White men are convicted is 20 per cent. We maintain that, intuitively, this inequality is unfair, at least pro tanto. The same intuition of pro tanto unfairness concerns other cases. For example, suppose that 80 per cent of the male children in need receive welfare assistance, but only 70 per cent of female needy children receive welfare assistance. We maintain that such intuitions persist even when we are told that race or gender are not the causes of the inequality but something else is (something else that is non-ephemerally correlated with gender and race).Footnote 21 Provided that the association is robust, the inequality is felt to be morally problematic, morally objectionable and unfair. This inequality is identified by determining the statistical prospects of an individual qua generic member of the reference class of the socially salient group to which that individual belongs, and comparing generic members of one group to members in a different group who are equal in J.

We believe that the intuition generalizes to all cases in which inequality between individuals equal in their desert* correlates with morally arbitrary* groups. We speculate that it is a distinguishing characteristic of socially salient groups that a procedure generating undeserved* inequalities between them feels, at least pro tanto, unfair. It is also felt to be more unfair than one generating the same amount of undeserved* inequalities but without any correlation with such groups.

7. Interpreting Statistical Fairness Constraints

In this section, we use FEC to interpret separation and sufficiency. We show that separation and sufficiency are special forms of our notion of fairness that correspond to a specific relation between the variables U (utility*), G (morally arbitrary* traits) and J (desert*). According to T2”:

Prediction-based decisions (an example of imperfect procedures) satisfy FEC if and only if individuals with the same J have the same expectations of having U, irrespective of their values for G.

Let us recall the informal definitions of sufficiency and separation and compare them with the above definition of FEC:

Sufficiency: Individuals about whom the same decision, D, is made have the same expectation of having the same true label, Y, that is, the same statistical prospects of being a true positive, regardless of their group membership, and the same statistical prospects of being a true negative, regardless of their group membership.

FEC can be turned into sufficiency by substituting ‘the same J’ with ‘about whom the same decision, D, is made’ and ‘U’ with ‘the same true label, Y’.Footnote 22 That is, prediction-based decisions that satisfy sufficiency, satisfy FEC if and only if:

  1. (a) that which harms and benefits individuals is the future true outcome (or true label), Y,

  2. (b) that which justifies inequality is the decision, D, and

  3. (c) G is group membership in the sense that is meant in separation and sufficiency.

Let us now consider the following:

Separation: Individuals with the same true label, Y, have the same expectations of receiving the positive and negative decisions, D, that is, true positives have the same statistical prospects of a positive decision, and true negatives have the same statistical prospects of a negative decision, regardless of their group membership.

In order to obtain separation from FEC, one must simply substitute ‘J’ with ‘true label, Y’ and ‘having U’ with ‘receiving the positive and negative decisions, D’Footnote 23 . Thus, a prediction-based decision that satisfies separation satisfies FEC if and only if:

  1. (a) that which harms and benefits individuals is the decision, D,

  2. (b) that which justifies inequality is the future true outcome (or true label), Y, and

  3. (c) G is group membership.

This result can be used as a guide to choose which fairness criterion, separation or sufficiency, is more appropriate in a given context.

However, it is possible that one variable can be both a harm and a benefit, or a benefit is regarded as a function of both the decision and group membership. Our theory entails that, when this is the case, FEC is satisfied by neither separation nor sufficiency. In other words, the cases in which separation or sufficiency are required by fairness are highly special ones, those in which decisions can be identified with predictions and either the decision or the true label capture the utility* or justifiers of a decision but not both.

Notice that sufficiency and separation refer to the (historically) true labels, indicated with Y. Thus, it is normally possible to determine if FEC was satisfied, retrospectively, by procedures that have already been used to make decisions and when salient outcomes of different decisions on heterogeneous types of individuals can be observed. Decision-makers typically cannot know the future outcomes of individuals about which they make decisions at the moment in which they have to make the decision. It is only possible to know if a procedure has been fair retrospectively, when observations of the actual values of Y become available.Footnote 24

8. Applications

In this section, we discuss two cases in which the principle of FEC plausibly provides clear advice on whether separation or sufficiency is required in a statistical-prediction-based decision rule. In the first case, FEC implies separation because – we argue – it is plausible that J=Y and U=D. In the second case, FEC implies sufficiency because it is plausible that J=D and U=Y. Hopefully, the moral analysis of these cases illustrates the insights that can be gained from FEC.

Case 1: Distributing cash assistance to keep children in school

Suppose a city is developing a statistical model to allocate cash assistance designed to keep children in school. The true label, Y, specifies whether the child leaves school before completing secondary education.

First step: Identify the just outcomes. The first analytical step is to identify the just outcome distribution that the decision-based procedure intends to achieve. At least for the sake of argument, let us assume that an ideally just outcome distribution is the one giving cash assistance to all and only the children who otherwise leave school prematurely. This theory identifies two classes of unjust outcomes: (a) when a child who leaves school prematurely does not receive cash assistance; and (b) when a child who does not leave school prematurely receives cash assistance.

Second step: Identify the conceptions of utility* and desert* implied by the characterization of just outcomes. Assuming the validity of the above account of just outcomes, the benefit is cash assistance, which, for simplicity, we assume to be equal in every case and equally beneficial to every recipient. Given this simplification, it is correct that, when cash is provided U takes the value of 1 and 0 otherwise. In the theory of just outcomes, which is assumed to be valid, what justifies receiving cash assistance is, uniquely, being a child who leaves school prematurely.Footnote 25 Thus, in this special case, J* = Y, the true label ‘the child has left school’ (assuming our observations of Y are not biased in favour of either group).

Third step: Identify the relevant groups. Finally, we assume for the sake of simplicity that the only socially salient difference between the two groups of children is their race. So G, in this case, is race, which is the same variable used in the statistical criteria of sufficiency and separation and in the FEC principle.

In these circumstances, FEC corresponds to separation. Separation involves two claims, one for positive and the other for negative cases. First, all children who have actually left school (Y=1) should have had the same probability of receiving cash assistance (D=1), irrespective of their race. Second, all children who do not need cash assistance (Y=0) should have the same expectation of receiving assistance (D=1) as a beneficial side-effect of being misclassified, irrespective of their race.

The counterintuitive side-effect of this choice could be the following: if Black children are more likely as a group to leave school prematurely than White children and separation is satisfied, the White children receiving the cash benefit will be less likely, on average as a group, to leave school prematurely; conversely, Black children who are not selected for cash assistance will be more likely to leave school prematurely, on average, than the White children who are not selected. This may seem to advantage White children over Black children, but, in fact, it is the result of achieving separation. This consequence makes the recommendation of our theory somewhat counterintuitive; however, since every violation of separation or sufficiency is, to some extent, counterintuitive, we believe that this is the best argument that can be provided for one of the two counterintuitive results being the morally appropriate one.

Case 2: Recommendations to take risks

A company (F1 company) promotes the opportunity of experiencing a Formula 1 race for amateur drivers. The client is permitted to race alone and to compete with others in a challenge to set the fastest racing time (as an F1 qualifier). For safety reasons, only drivers sufficiently likely to avoid fatal crashes are recommended to race. For this reason, they assess the risk of a fatal crash based on the data points collected after 10 hours of lone driving.

First step: Identify the just outcomes. In order to illustrate a case that supports sufficiency, we will select a somewhat unusual moral theory – hoping that the example retains at least some intuitive plausibility.

We suppose that those who have been recommended to avoid racing due to its high risk have no moral claim to avoid death by accident in the race, while all those who have been given the recommendation to race morally deserve to survive. This formulation is rough, but it may capture, with significant simplifications, the core intuition of Scanlon’s (Reference Scanlon1998: 257) view on the moral relevance of warnings.Footnote 26

Let us now unpack the corresponding assumptions about utility* and desert*. First, we notice that the only benefit considered in this account of outcome justice is surviving the race. That is to say, we ignore the utility derived from the enjoyment of the race. Possibly, if our account of the just distribution had considered that element too, it would not have supported sufficiency but a different statistical criterion instead. Our choice of a theory of just outcomes is ad hoc, in the sense that it is meant to illustrate the logical possibility of selecting sufficiency as a fairness criterion. But, as argued next, it cannot be considered a weakness of FEC itself.

Second step: Identify the conceptions of utility* and desert* implied by the characterization of just outcomes. Let us suppose that it is justifiable to ignore damage suffered from a less-than-fatal crash. This assumption is implied by the moral theory of just outcomes we characterized at the outset, which was chosen for its simplicity. This theory of justice describes the possible outcomes in such a way that it is only possible to pair them with two utility* values: U=0 for a fatal crash and U=1 for every other outcome. Clearly, the theory is not sufficiently fine-grained to provide guidance in real life. For that reason, it is not fully plausible. We imposed this further simplification because we also aim to illustrate sufficiency as fulfilled by a binary classifier, thus keeping the formal element to a minimum.Footnote 27

For simplicity’s sake, we assume that it is justifiable to simplify our observations about the observed outcomes. We assume Y=0 indicates the event of a fatal crash and Y=1 its avoidance. Again, these observations are, by assumption, not biased against any morally arbitrary* group. Thus, in this case, plausibly, U=Y.

Let us now turn to desert*. One must ask whether, according to this theory, all individuals have an equally strong claim to U, where the values of U correspond to the two possible outcomes of the race in our ultra-simplified account of the case. The theory of justice described at the outset denies this. It maintains that all individuals, and only those, receiving the recommendation to race equally deserve* to survive, and those who were told to abstain from the race do not deserve* to survive to a comparable degree; the strength of the moral claim of individuals to receive the good ‘survival’ after racing depends on the recommendation received before the race. Thus, this theory treats the recommendation received by the individual as the justifier of inequality. Since the recommendation an individual receives is the decision D (e.g. the outputs of the procedure are such warnings), this can be described as a case in which J=D.

If all these conditions are met, FEC requires that one considers sufficiency as the relevant standard for this case. That is to say, the tool should be considered fair if and only if clients who are recommended to race are equally likely to survive, irrespective of their socially salient group, and if clients who are allowed to race are equally likely to die, irrespective of their socially salient group. FEC implies that violating sufficiency is unfair.

This judgement seems sufficiently intuitive to us. To the extent that one focuses on a fair distribution of the risk of death, sufficiency is indeed an appropriate criterion for this case. This risk may be allowed to vary systematically between groups of individuals who have been given opposite recommendations. But, among those individuals, it should not vary systematically across the socially salient groups to which they belong.

Notice that the plausibility of FEC always needs to be determined relative to some theory of the just outcome distribution that is not implied by it. Evidently, the moral assertions FEC supports are only as good as the account of just outcomes one assumes to be valid.

Admittedly, it is hard to provide a persuasive illustration of a context in which sufficiency realizes FEC, given a fully morally plausible theory of outcome justice, in a few pages. We do not believe that all possible cases in which sufficiency is supported by FEC must rely on implausible theories of outcome justice.Footnote 28 We also do not believe that, if that were the case, it would imply that FEC is fundamentally misguided; after all, we could live in a moral world in which sufficiency is not a valid criterion of fairness. It could be the case that no valid theory of just outcomes implies the validity of sufficiency in circumstances that actually obtain, or that could plausibly be taken to obtain. Even in this scenario, FEC retains its utility as a tool to determine what would have to be the case (morally speaking) for sufficiency to be morally relevant to imperfect procedural justice. However, we believe that the opposite is the case, and the exploration of contexts and moral theories supporting sufficiency seems to support this conjecture.

9. Conclusions

In this article, we have illustrated the complications that arise when one attempts to evaluate the fairness of different decision rules based on statistical predictions with everyday normative concepts and moral-philosophical theories. Both everyday language and moral-philosophical theories turn out to be vague at best when one turns to evaluations of predictive models, and this creates significant challenges since the alternative mathematical translations of the fairness criteria provide us with a genuine dilemma: several fairness criteria appear plausible, but it is impossible to satisfy them at the same time.

However, we have argued that this apparent impossibility theorem for decision rules based on predictions can, in some cases, be dissolved by a better understanding of: first, the relevant harms and benefits generated by the predictions; second, the factors that justify inequalities (referred to as “justifiers”, or “desert*”) and those that should not align with them (termed “arbitrary* traits”); and third, the unjust inequalities that are not unfair – namely, those relating to unjust outcomes in a statistically neutral way (defined as “luck*”).

We have argued that the FEC principle is supported in reflective equilibrium by its coherence with two statistical fairness criteria (separation and sufficiency) and with the intuition that inequality between groups matters morally when the groups are socially salient.Footnote 29 FEC implies that an (imperfect) procedure resulting in unjustified inequalities robustly correlated with socially salient groups is not fair. By contrast, an imperfect procedure can be fair even if it generates inequalities correlated with socially salient groups when this inequality in statistical prospects disappears for groups consisting of individuals with the same desert* characteristics.Footnote 30

Our hope is that this approach enables philosophers and stakeholders to articulate moral arguments in favour of or against sufficiency and separation as relevant fairness constraints when modelling statistical predictors through machine learning, at least in those contexts in which these statistical criteria are appropriate. Indeed, our demonstration reveals that as Fair Equality of Chances (FEC) establishes a necessary condition within instances of imperfect procedural justice, there are circumstances where fairness necessitates the adoption of separation or sufficiency principles.

To the best of our knowledge, FEC is the only framework that works out the implications of treating questions of predictive or statistical fairness as questions of imperfect procedural justice. This is a dimension of fairness irreducible to either outcome justice or pure procedural justice. Our theory does not provide an answer to the question, ‘is this decision-making procedure fair?’ alone. FEC must always be supplemented by an account of outcome justice. For clearly, imperfect procedural justice can only be defined relative to the (perfect) conception of outcome justice that the (imperfect) procedure is supposed to bring about. However, FEC is compatible with a large class of such theories. Our theory necessitates the introduction of new theoretical concepts, desert*, utility* and luck*. FEC characterizes procedural fairness as a mathematical relation between the ideally just outcome distribution and the one actually achieved by the procedure. The concepts with the * sign enable a purely formal description of the relation between procedural fairness and outcome justice while sidestepping all commitments to specific accounts of the latter.

Moreover, fairness might not be the only ethical desideratum of imperfect procedures. Achieving a socially optimal decision rule may require balancing efficiency and fair equality of chances, as these objectives may sometimes be in conflict with each other (Corbett-Davies et al. Reference Corbett-Davies, Pierson, Feller, Goel and Huq2017). Moreover, we have assumed the egalitarian idea that fairness consists of some kind of equality. However, it is also worth exploring a maximin version of the first principle of a theory of imperfect procedural justice, which is satisfied when the greatest utility is produced for the group with the lowest utility among those with equal desert*.Footnote 31

Acknowledgements

The project leading to this publication has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Sklodowska-Curie grant agreement No. 898322, ‘Fair Predictions in Health’. We also acknowledge support by the Swiss National Science Foundation, NRP 77 project 407740_1187473, ‘Socially acceptable AI and fairness trade-offs in predictive analytics’. The authors would like to express their gratitude to Sune Holm, all the participants of the 2020 Copenhagen Workshop on Algorithmic Fairness, and two unnamed reviewers for their valuable contributions and insights.

Technical Appendix

Let the random variable $G$ specify an individual’s group membership, $J$ his/her moral claim to utility, and $U$ his/her obtained utility. In this section we will formally show that separation and sufficiency are special-cases of Fair Equality of Chances (FEC) under certain conditions.

1 Separation as FEC

Proposition 1 (Separation as FEC) Consider the binary classification task where ${\cal Y} = \left\{ {0,1} \right\}$ . Suppose $U = D$ (that is, utility $U$ is the same as the decision $D$ ), and $J = Y$ (i.e., the justifier $J$ is the same as the true label $Y$ ). Then the conditions of FEC are equivalent to those of separation.

Proof Recall that FEC requires that $\forall g,g{\rm{'}} \in {\cal G},\forall j \in {\cal J}$ , and for all possible utility levels $u$ :

$${\mathbb{P}}(U \le u|G = g,J = j) = {\mathbb{P}}(U \le u|G = g{\rm{'}},J = j).$$

Replacing $U$ with $D$ and $J$ with $Y$ , the above is equivalent to

$$\begin{align*}\forall g,g{\rm{'}} \in {\cal G},\forall j \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}{\rm{\;}}\forall u \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}\\ &\quad\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!:{\mathbb{P}}\left[ {D \le u\left| {G = g,Y = j\left] { = \mathbb{P}} \right[D \le u} \right|G = g{\rm{'}},Y = j} \right]\end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}\Leftarrow \forall g,g{\rm{'}} \in {\cal G},\forall y \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}{\rm{\;}}\forall d \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}\\ &\quad\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!:{\mathbb{P}}\left[ {D = d\left| {G = g,Y = j\left] { = \mathbb{P}} \right[D = d} \right|G = g{\rm{'}},Y = y} \right]\end{align*}$$

where the last line is identical to the conditions of separation for binary classification.

2 Sufficiency as FEC

Proposition 2 (Sufficiency as FEC) Consider the binary classification task where ${\cal Y} = \left\{ {0,1} \right\}$ . Suppose $U = Y$ and $U ={\hat Y}$ (the justifier for an individual is assumed to be the same as their predicted label). Then the conditions of FEC are equivalent to those of sufficiency.

Proof Recall that FEC requires that $\forall g,g{\rm{'}} \in {\cal G},\forall j \in \left[ {0,1} \right]$ , and $\forall u \in \mathbb{R}$ :

$$P\left[ {U \le u\left| {G = g,J = j\left] { = P} \right[U \le u} \right|G = g{\rm{'}},J = j} \right].$$

Replacing $U$ with $Y$ , $J$ with $D$ , the above is equivalent to

$$\begin{align*}\forall g,g{\rm{'}} \in {\cal G},\forall j \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}{\rm{\;}}\forall u \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}\\ &\quad\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!:{\mathbb{P}}\left[ {Y \le u\left| {G = g,D = j\left] { = \mathbb{P}} \right[Y \le u} \right|G = g{\rm{'}},D = j} \right]\end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}\Leftarrow \forall g,g{\rm{'}} \in {\cal G},\forall y \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}{\rm{\;}}\forall d \in \left\{ {0,1} \right\}\\ &\quad\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!:{\mathbb{P}}\left[ {Y = y\left| {G = g,D = d\left] { = \mathbb{P}} \right[Y = y} \right|G = g{\rm{'}},D = d} \right]\end{align*}$$

where the last line is identical to sufficiency.

Michele Loi is a Marie Skłodowska-Curie Individual Fellow at Politecnico Milano, with a strong publication profile in analytic philosophy, enriched by contributions to top-tier computer science venues. His prolific interdisciplinary scholarship spans over 50 publications on key topics such as fairness, trust and transparency in AI. URL: www.micheleloi.eu

Anders Herlitz is Associate Professor of Practical Philosophy at Lund University and Researcher at the Institute for Futures Studies in Stockholm. He is, together with Henrik Andersson, the editor of Value Incommensurability: Ethics, Risk, and Decision-Making (Routledge, 2022). His current scholarship centres on distributive ethics, comparability problems and justified choice, with a special focus on topics in population-level bioethics and climate ethics. Email: . URL: https://www.iffs.se/en/research/researchers/anders-herlitz/

Hoda Heidari is the K&L Gates Career Development Assistant Professor in Ethics and Computational Technologies at Carnegie Mellon University, with joint appointments in Machine Learning and Societal Computing. She is also affiliated with the Human-Computer Interaction Institute, CyLab, the Block Center for Technology and Society, and the Institute for Politics and Strategy. Her research is broadly concerned with the social, ethical and economic implications of Artificial Intelligence, and in particular, issues of fairness and accountability through the use of Machine Learning in socially consequential domains. Her work in this area has won a best paper award at the ACM Conference on Fairness, Accountability, and Transparency (FAccT), an exemplary track award at the ACM Conference on Economics and Computation (EC) and a best paper award at IEEE Conference on Secure and Trustworthy Machine Learning (SAT-ML). Email: . URL: https://www.cs.cmu.edu/∼hheidari/

Footnotes

1 Hedden (Reference Hedden2021), Long (Reference Long2021) and Beigang (Reference Beigang2023) all object to treating separation as a criterion of fairness. However, Hedden and Long merely show the existence of fair algorithms that violate separation across non-socially salient groups. This is logically compatible with the impossibility of fairness for an algorithm that violates separation relative to two groups that are socially salient. Beigang argues that intuitively fair algorithms can violate separation. His alleged example is an algorithm that has a higher rate of false positives in one ethnic group, but this is entirely explained by the fact that the algorithm is biased against young people and there are more young people in that ethnic group. We object that the algorithm is, indeed, unfair against one ethnic group, even if it is because of an age bias, not because of an ethnic bias.

2 By moral, we mean concerning the justification of inequalities.

3 By prudential, we mean concerning what benefits or harms individuals.

4 This guidance abstracts away from different types of bias introduced via the data pipeline (Fazelpour and Danks Reference Fazelpour and Danks2021). While we offer a proof that sufficiency or separation may, when specific conditions obtain, guarantee a distribution satisfying FEC, these conditions may rarely be satisfied in the real world. For example, the real world may never offer a label Y that satisfies the conditions that have to obtain in order for separation to be a morally appropriate criterion of predictive fairness. This may be due to the biases affecting Y or to the fact that the relevant normative considerations do not align neatly with any observable in the dataset (Lipton and Fazelpour Reference Lipton and Fazelpour2020). Moreover, in most contexts algorithmic procedures produce effects only in combination with other algorithmic procedures. For the sake of simplicity, we also ignore here the question of algorithmic fairness under composition (Dwork and Ilvento Reference Dwork and Ilvento2018) and the problem of performative predictions; see note 24.

5 Desert* is not limited to those, and only those, properties that are deemed important by philosophers in relation to the moral justification of inequality. Whenever a procedure is expected to produce just outcomes according to some definition Λ, the satisfaction of FEC can be tested relative to Λ.

6 It may be objected that it is not clear what desert* means here, since this is so heterogeneous. But remember that desert* is a mere placeholder for the criterion of outcome justice that one assumes to be relevant to the case. So the reference of desert* will be determined on a case-by-case basis by including the feature or features that (we assume) are deemed relevant to the justification of outcome inequality.

7 The desert* properties imply a value of J for the individual, given a context and a type of benefit or harm.

8 Since desert* inequalities are by definition inequalities in that feature or those features justifying outcome inequality, this is trivially true.

9 We concede that this is barely a gesture towards a methodology for dealing with questions posed by intersectionality. A deeper analysis falls outside the scope of this article.

10 As becomes clearer in the examples, U does not include all possible benefits and harms, but only those whose distribution is regarded as a matter of (equal or unequal) desert* in the relationship with the algorithm provider, in the context in which the procedure operates.

11 We assume that utility can be measured with a ratio scale, here, for the sake of illustration.

12 See note 5 concerning just outcome definitions that do not have a philosophical grounding.

13 Small capital variables indicate the actual value of a given (random) variable, while capital letters indicate variables that may take different values when sampling randomly.

14 Luck* does not correspond to any variable in the mathematical formulation of the principle, but it is a useful explanatory concept.

15 How much approximation is compatible with fairness may vary from context to context, depending on the moral properties of the case. In order to make small-scale ideal theorizing bear to real-world questions (Lipton and Fazelpour Reference Lipton and Fazelpour2020) some degree of approximation in the observation and measure of morally salient property has to be tolerated.

16 For example, democratic procedures to achieve just policies may have a procedural justification that is entirely independent of the outcomes of democratic political deliberation being just. Some procedural elements may be justified as realizations of equal participation, which in turn may be considered constitutive of equal respect, which is independently morally required (by justice, or some other moral value) (Ceva Reference Ceva2016).

17 The use of the capital letters J, U and G in FEC, as opposed to lowercase j, u and g in the mathematical formula relates to the fact that lower case letters represent the specific values that the random variables J, U and G correspond to for a given individual, for example G = religion, g = Muslim, where g is the religion of the person named John.

18 Notice that their account of luck does not draw a distinction between outcome justice and procedural fairness. According to the definition of luck* in FEC, luck* has to be corrected for the outcome to be fully just. But it does not have to be corrected for the procedure to be fair. The repurposing of the idea of neutral luck to characterize the relation between outcome justice and its imperfect procedural realization is a distinct conceptual innovation in the philosophy of justice.

19 Incidentally, related to a concept of luck discussed within economics.

20 For example, the correlation between age and religion is brought about by a structurally robust common cause.

21 Also, this ‘something else’ is not J, something which justifies the inequality. This is excluded by FEC formally.

22 We provide a formal proof in the Appendix of this article.

23 We provide a formal proof in the Appendix of this article.

24 When the future performance of a procedure is evaluated on the basis of historical data, however, other biases may enter the picture. For example, the distribution of historical true labels Y recorded in the past 10 years may not be a good statistical indicator for the future fairness of the algorithm in the next 10 years, when social circumstances change (Lipton and Fazelpour Reference Lipton and Fazelpour2020; Fazelpour and Danks Reference Fazelpour and Danks2021), or because the prediction itself causally influences the distribution outcome to be predicted, a phenomenon known as performativity of predictions (Grunberg and Modigliani Reference Grunberg and Modigliani1954; Perdomo et al. Reference Perdomo, Zrnic, Mendler-Dünner and Hardt2020). How to account for the biases emerging due to a mismatch between historically observed statistical trends, future trends and the effects of performativity is not a question our theory intends to solve.

25 Philosophically, this may be regarded as special case of the theory of justice in which desert* is identified with need. This is not necessary for the application of FEC to the case at hand, in which a more concrete description of the just outcome distribution is the starting point of the procedure set in place.

26 Scanlon (Reference Scanlon1998: 257) claims that individuals who were injured due to the transportation of hazardous material cannot hold the city officials liable if those officials took all necessary precautions during the operation and if the injured parties were adequately warned but chose to ignore the warning.

27 For an instance in which FEC supports sufficiency defined over continuous variable see Loi and Baumann (Reference Loi and Baumann2023), where the mathematical apparatus is more substantial.

28 Loi and Heitz (Reference Loi and Heitz2022) argue in detail for the claim a score used for recommending movies only avoids prima facie morally wrongful discrimination between two genders if between-group calibration (mathematically equivalent to what we here call sufficiency, if one takes the communicated risk score r to be the recommendation D) between the two gender obtains. Remarkably, this suggests that sufficiency could be generally relevant to fairness when the decisions of the algorithms (which do not have to be binary) are the recommendations it delivers to individuals. Loi and Baumann (Reference Loi and Baumann2023) argue that insurance is one case in which sufficiency is plausible. To uphold this idea, Fair Equality of Chances (FEC) requires that individuals paying the same premium should have equal expected claims regardless of their morally arbitrary group memberships. This aligns with a reasonable interpretation of FEC for insurance, wherein (a) those paying higher premiums deserve greater benefits from insurers compared with those with lower premiums and (b) individuals reporting higher claims receive greater benefits from the insurer after their claims are paid.

29 Or, equivalently, between individuals whose statistical prospects are defined by taking their socially salient groups as reference classes.

30 We write ‘can be’ because the procedure may still be unfair for other reasons.

31 The approach developed by Heidari et al. (Reference Heidari, Loi, Gummadi and Krause2019) can be considered an attempt in this direction, but is limited to treating accountability as the only possible justification of inequality.

References

Arneson, R.J. 1989. Equality and equality of opportunity for welfare. Philosophical Studies 56, 7793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barocas, S. and Selbst, A.D. 2016. Big Data’s disparate impact. California Law Review 104, 671732.Google Scholar
Beigang, F. 2023. Reconciling algorithmic fairness criteria. Philosophy & Public Affairs 51, 166190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berk, R., Heidari, H., Shahin, S., Kearns, M. and Roth, A. 2021. Fairness in criminal justice risk assessments: the state of the art. Sociological Methods & Research 50, 344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 1984. Selecting people randomly. Ethics 95, 3855.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brouwer, H. and Mulligan, T. 2019. Why not be a desertist? Philosophical Studies 176, 22712288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castro, C. and Loi, M. 2023. The fair chances in algorithmic fairness: a response to Holm. Res Publica 29, 331337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ceva, E. 2016. Interactive Justice: A Proceduralist Approach to Value Conflict in Politics. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chouldechova, A. 2017. Fair prediction with disparate impact: a study of bias in recidivism prediction instruments. Big Data 5, 153163.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Corbett-Davies, S., Pierson, E., Feller, A., Goel, S. and Huq, A. 2017. Algorithmic decision making and the cost of fairness. In Proceedings of the 23rd ACM SIGKDD International Conference on Knowledge Discovery and Data Mining, 797–806. New York, NY: ACM.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Di Bello, M. and O’Neil, C. 2020. Profile evidence, fairness, and the risks of mistaken convictions. Ethics 130, 147178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dwork, C. and Ilvento, C. 2018. Fairness under composition. In 10th Innovations in Theoretical Computer Science Conference (ITCS 2019), ed. A. Blum, 33:1–33:20. https://doi.org/10.4230/LIPIcs.ITCS.2019.33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fazelpour, S. and Danks, D. 2021. Algorithmic bias: senses, sources, solutions. Philosophy Compass 16, e12760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, F. 2016. Distributive Justice: Getting what we Deserve from our Country. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grunberg, E. and Modigliani, F. 1954. The predictability of social events. Journal of Political Economy 62, 465478.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardt, M., Price, E. and Srebro, N. 2016. Equality of opportunity in supervised learning. In Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems, 3315–23.Google Scholar
Hedden, B. 2021. On statistical criteria of algorithmic fairness. Philosophy & Public Affairs 49, 209231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidari, H., Loi, M., Gummadi, K.P. and Krause, A. 2019. A moral framework for understanding fair ML through economic models of equality of opportunity. In Proceedings of the Conference on Fairness, Accountability, and Transparency, 181–190. New York, NY: ACM.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herlitz, A. and Horan, D. 2016. Measuring needs for priority setting in healthcare planning and policy. Social Science and Medicine 157, 96102.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Holm, S. 2023. The fairness in algorithmic fairness. Res Publica 29, 265281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelley, R. 2010. Thelonious Monk: The Life and Times of an American Original. New York, NY: Free Press.Google Scholar
Kleinberg, J., Mullainathan, S. and Raghavan, M. 2017. Inherent trade-offs in the fair determination of risk scores. In 8th Innovations in Theoretical Computer Science Conference (ITCS 2017), ed. C.H. Papadimitriou, 43:1–43:23. Dagstuhl: Schloss Dagstuhl–Leibniz-Zentrum fuer Informatik.Google Scholar
Lefranc, A., Pistolesi, N. and Trannoy, A. 2009. Equality of opportunity and luck: definitions and testable conditions, with an application to income in France. Journal of Public Economics 93, 11891207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 2007. Nothing personal: on statistical discrimination. Journal of Political Philosophy 15, 385403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, Z.C. and Fazelpour, S. 2020. Algorithmic fairness from a non-ideal perspective. In Proceedings of the AAAI/ACM Conference on AI, Ethics, and Society (AIES 20), ed. A.N. Markham, J. Powles, T. Walsh and A.L. Washington, 57–63.Google Scholar
Loi, M. and Heitz, C. 2022. Is calibration a fairness requirement? An argument from the point of view of moral philosophy and decision theory. In 2022 ACM Conference on Fairness, Accountability, and Transparency, 2026–2034. Seoul: ACM.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loi, M. and Baumann, J. 2023. Fairness and risk: an ethical argument for a group fairness definition insurers can use. Philosophy and Technology 36. doi: 10.1007/s13347-023-00624-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, R. 2021. Fairness in machine learning: against false positive rate equality as a measure of fairness. Journal of Moral Philosophy 19, 4978.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D. 1999. Principles of Social Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Perdomo, J., Zrnic, T., Mendler-Dünner, C. and Hardt, M. 2020. Performative prediction. In Proceedings of the 37th International Conference on Machine Learning, PMLR 119, 7599–7609.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999. A Theory of Justice, 2nd edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roemer, J.E. 1993. A pragmatic theory of responsibility for the egalitarian planner. Philosophy & Public Affairs 22, 146166.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A.K. 1995. Inequality Reexamined. New York, NY: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1987. Claims of need. In Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value, 158. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Confusion table and predictive accuracy

Figure 1

Table 2. Confusion table of the grader’s performance in the Buddhist population

Figure 2

Table 3. Confusion table of the grader’s performance in the Muslim population