Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-20T01:51:35.122Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The epistemic division of labour in markets: knowledge, global trade and the preconditions of morally responsible agency

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 July 2019

Lisa Herzog*
Affiliation:
TUM School of Governance, Richard-Wagner-Strasse 1, 80333 München, Germany

Abstract

Markets allow for the processing of decentralized information through the price mechanism. But in addition, many markets rely on other mechanisms in markets, or non-market institutions, that provide and manage other forms of knowledge. Within national economies, these institutions form an ‘epistemic infrastructure’ for markets. In global markets, in contrast, this epistemic infrastructure is very patchy, undermining the preconditions for morally responsible agency. New technologies might help to improve the epistemic infrastructure of global markets, but they require conceptualizing knowledge not only as a tradable good, but also as a precondition of morally responsible agency.

Type
Article
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akerlof, G.A. 1970. The market for lemons: quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. Quarterly Journal of Economics 84, 488500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, E. 2012. Epistemic justice as a virtue of social institutions. Social Epistemology 26, 163173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G.E.M. 1963. Intention (2nd edn). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Appiah, A.K. 2011. The Honor Code: How Moral Revolutions Happen. New York, NY: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Barry, C. and Reddy, S. 2008. International Trade and Labour Standards: A Proposal for Linkage. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Çalışkan, K. 2010. Market Threads. How Cotton Farmers and Traders Create a Global Commodity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Calvert-Minor, C. 2011. ‘Epistemological communities’ and the problem of epistemic agency. Social Epistemology 25, 341360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, S. 2013. Collectives’ duties and collectivization duties. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91, 231248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, S. and Lawford-Smith, H. 2016. The transfer of duties: from individuals to states and back again. In The Epistemic Life of Groups, ed. Brady, M. and Fricker, M., 150172. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Bruin, B. 2015. Ethics and the Global Financial Crisis: Why Incompetence is Worse than Greed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diekmann, A. and Przepiorka, W. 2018. Trust and reputation in markets. In The Oxford Handbook of Gossip and Reputation, ed. Giardini, F. and Wittek, R.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, D. 2001. Preference Pollution. How Markets Create the Desires We Dislike. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goff, S.C. 2018. Fair trade: global problems and individual responsibilities. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 21, 521543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S.C. 2015. Should have known. Synthese 194, 28632894.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Granovetter, M. 1985. Economic action and social structure: the problem of embeddedness. American Journal of Sociology 91, 481510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Guardian 2014. This cry for help on a Primark label can’t be ignored. 25 June, https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/jun/25/primark-label-swansea-textile-industry-rana-plaza.Google Scholar
von Hayek, F.A. 1945. The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review 35, 519530.Google Scholar
Herzog, L. 2016. Who should prevent sweatshops? Duties, excuses, and the moral division of labour in the global economy. In Die Philosophie des Marktes [The Philosophy of the Market] Deutsches Jahrbuch Philosophie 7, ed. Schmidt am Busch, H.-Chr., 255278. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Herzog, L. and Walton, A. 2014. Qualified market access and interdisciplinarity (research note). Ethics & Global Politics 7, 8394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, T. 2007. Numerous ways to be an open-minded organization: a reply to Lahroodi. Social Epistemology 21, 439448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking Fast and Slow. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Kreps, D.M. 1990. Cooperate culture and economic theory. In Perspectives on Positive Political Economy, ed. Alt, J. and Shepsle, K., 90143. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kutz, C. 2000. Complicity. Ethics and Law for a Collective Age. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lahroodi, R. 2007. Collective epistemic virtues. Social Epistemology 21, 281297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, C. and Pettit, P. 2011. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackenzie, D.A. 2008. An Engine, Not a Camera: How Financial Models Shape Markets. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Ruggie, J.G. 1982. International regimes, transactions, and change: embedded liberalism in the postwar economic order. International Organizations 36, 379415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sher, G. 2009. Who Knew? Responsibility without Awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siamwalla, A. 1978. Farmers and middlemen: aspects of agricultural marketing in Thailand. Economic Bulletin for Asia and the Pacific 29, 3850.Google Scholar
Smith, H. 1983. Culpable ignorance. Philosophical Review 92, 543571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, H. 2014. The subjective moral duty to inform oneself before acting. Ethics 125, 1138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spillman, L. 2012. Solidarity in Strategy. Making Business Meaningful in American Trade Associations. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Srivastava, M. and Shannon, S. 2013. Ninety cents buys safety on $22 jeans in Bangladesh, 2013. http://www.bloomberg.com/news/2013-06-05/ninety-cents-buys-safety-on-22-jeans-in-bangladesh.html.Google Scholar
Stedman Jones, D. 2012. Masters of the Universe: Hayek, Friedman, and the Birth of Neoliberal Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Toffler, A. 1970. Future Shock. New York, NY: Random House.Google Scholar
Van Horn, R., Mirowski, P. and Stapleford, T.A., eds 2011. Building Chicago Economics: New Perspectives on the History of America’s Most Powerful Economics Program. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watts, S. and Wyner, G. 2011. Designing and theorizing the adoption of mobile technology-mediated ethical consumption tools. Information Technology & People 24, 257280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, I.M. 2011. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar