Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T16:14:22.936Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CALCULATING QALYS: LIBERALISM AND THE VALUE OF HEALTH STATES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2017

Douglas MacKay*
Affiliation:
Department of Public Policy, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, Abernethy Hall 217, CB 3435, 131 S. Columbia St., Chapel Hill, NC 27599USA. E-mail: [email protected]; URL: http://dmackay.web.unc.edu.

Abstract:

The value of health states is often understood to depend on their impact on the goodness of people's lives. As such, prominent health states metrics are grounded in particular conceptions of wellbeing – e.g. hedonism or preference satisfaction. In this paper, I consider how liberals committed to the public justification requirement – the requirement that public officials choose laws and policies that are justifiable to their citizens – should evaluate health states. Since the public justification requirement prohibits public officials from appealing to controversial conceptions of the good life, liberals committed to this principle face a significant puzzle.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Arneson, R. 1999. Human flourishing versus desire satisfaction. Social Philosophy and Policy 16: 113142.Google Scholar
Bird, C. 2014. Coercion and public justification. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 13: 189214.Google Scholar
Bleichrodt, H. and Quiggin, J.. 2013. Capabilities as menus: a non-welfarist basis for QALY evaluation. Journal of Health Economics 32: 128137.Google Scholar
Brandt, R. 1998. A Theory of the Good and the Right. New York, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Brock, D. 2002. The separability of health and well-being. In Summary Measures of Population Health: Concepts, Ethics, Measurement and Applications, ed. Murray, C. J. L., Salomon, J. A., Mathers, C. D. and Lopez, A. D., 115120. Geneva: World Health Organization.Google Scholar
Carter, I. 1999. A Measure of Freedom. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coast, J., Kinghorn, P. and Mitchell, P.. 2015. The development of capability measures in health economics: opportunities, challenges and progress. Patient 9: 119126.Google Scholar
Cookson, R. 2005. QALYs and the capability approach. Health Economics 14: 817829.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Crisp, R. 2006. Hedonism reconsidered. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73: 619645.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. 2015. Well-being. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, E. N.. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/well-being/.Google Scholar
Daniels, N. 1985. Just Health Care. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dolan, P. and Kahneman, D.. 2008. Interpretations of utility and their implications for the valuation of health. The Economic Journal 118: 215234.Google Scholar
Dorsey, D. 2011. The hedonist's dilemma. Journal of Moral Philosophy 8: 173196.Google Scholar
Feldman, F. 2004. Pleasure and the Good Life: Concerning the Nature, Varieties, and Plausibility of Hedonism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. F. 2003. Contemporary Theories of Liberalism: Public Reason as a Post-Enlightenment Project. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. F. 2009. The moral foundations of liberal neutrality. In Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy, ed. Christiano, T. and Christman, J. P., 8198. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. F. 2011. The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goldstein, I. 1989. Pleasure and pain: unconditional, intrinsic values. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50: 255276.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. 1986. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. 2006. Valuing health. Philosophy and Public Affairs 34: 246274.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. 2010. Hedonism and welfare economics. Economics and Philosophy 26: 321344.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. 2015. Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. and McPherson, M. S.. 2009. Preference satisfaction and welfare economics. Economics and Philosophy 25: 125.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 1996a. The Sources of Normativity. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 1996b. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Larmore, C. 1996. The Morals of Modernity. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lauinger, W. 2011. Dead Sea apples and desire-fulfillment welfare theories. Utilitas 23: 324343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. 1991. Equality and Partiality. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nord, E. 1999. Cost-Value Analysis in Health Care: Making Sense Out of QALYs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1975. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 2001. Women and Human Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2011. On What Matters: Volume One, ed. Scheffler, S.. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Quong, J. 2011. Liberalism Without Perfection. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rachels, S. 2000. Is unpleasantness intrinsic to unpleasant experiences? Philosophical Studies 99: 187210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, P. 1986. Facts and values. Philosophical Topics 14: 531.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Revised edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Kelly, E.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ruger, J. P. 2010. Health and Social Justice. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Seligman, D. B. 1970. Masochism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48: 6775.Google Scholar
Shiffrin, S. V. 2012. Harm and its moral significance. Legal Theory 18: 357398.Google Scholar
Simon, J., Anand, P., Gray, A., Rugkåsa, J., Yeeles, K. and Burns, T.. 2013. Operationalising the capability approach for outcome measurement in mental health research. Social Science and Medicine 98: 187196.Google Scholar
Sobel, D. 1994. Full information accounts of well-being. Ethics 104: 784810.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, D. 2009. Subjectivism and idealization. Ethics 119: 336352.Google Scholar
Sumner, L. W. 1996. Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Torrance, G. W. 1986. Measurement of health state utilities for economic appraisal: a review. Journal of Health Economics 5: 130.Google Scholar
Ubel, P. A., Richardson, J. and Menzel, P.. 2000. Societal value, the person trade-off, and the dilemma of whose values to measure of cost-effectiveness analysis. Health Economics 9: 127136.Google Scholar
Vallier, K. 2011. Consensus and convergence in public reason. Public Affairs Quarterly 25: 261279.Google Scholar
Vallier, K. and D'Agostino, F.. 2014. Public justification. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, E. N.. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justification-public/.Google Scholar
Venkatapuram, S. 2011. Health Justice: An Argument from the Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Wolff, J., Edwards, S., Richmond, S., Orr, S. and Rees, G.. 2012. Evaluating interventions in health: a reconciliatory approach. Bioethics 26: 455463.Google Scholar