Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:31:42.191Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Signification et action

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 March 2010

Candida de sousa Melo*
Affiliation:
University of California, Berkeley

Abstract

ABSTRACT: In the logical tradition of analytical philosophy, to understand the meaning of an utterance is to understand its truth conditions. In the tradition of natural language analysis, meaning is related to language use. Since Grice, meaning is linked to speakers’ attitudes and actions. Following Austin, Searle, and Vanderveken, to mean is to use words with the intention of performing illocutionary acts. Such acts have felicity conditions instead of truth conditions. The aim of my work is to clarify the nature of meaning in the second tradition. In my view, to mean something is mainly to attempt to perform illocutionary acts. Any attempt is an intentional action rather than an attitude.

RÉSUMÉ : Dans la tradition logique de la philosophie analytique, comprendre la signification d’un énoncé, c’est comprendre ses conditions de vérité. Dans la tradition du langage naturel, la signification est liée à l’usage du langage. Depuis Grice, elle est liée aux attitudes et aux actions des interlocuteurs. Selon Austin, Searle et Vanderveken, signifier c’est utiliser des mots avec l’intention d’accomplir des actes illocutoires. Pareils actes ont des conditions de félicité plutôt que des conditions de vérité. Selon nous, signifier c’est essentiellement tenter d’accomplir des actes illocutoires. Et comme toute tentative est une action intentionnelle plutôt qu’une attitude, signifier c’est agir intentionnellement.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Références bibliographiques

Austin, John L. 1962 How to Do Things with Words, Oxford, Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. 1971 «La pensée», dans Écrits Logiques et Philosophiques, traduction de Imbert, C., Paris, Seuil.Google Scholar
Grice, P. 1957 «Meaning», Philosophical Review, vol. 66, p. 677688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W.G. 1999 «Philosophy of Language», dans Audi, R., dir., The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2eédition, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, p. 673676.Google Scholar
Searle, J.R. 1969 Speech Acts, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J.R. 1979 Expression and Meaning, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J.R. 1983 Intentionality, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J.R. et Vanderveken, D. 1985 Foundations of Illocutionary Logic, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vanderveken, D. 2005 «Attempt, Success and Action Generation: A Logical Study of Intentional Action», dans Vanderveken, D., dir., Logic, Thought and Action, Dordrecht, Springer, p. 315342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar