Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T07:50:26.819Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Origin of Moral Norms: A Moderate Nativist Account

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 October 2011

Jessy Giroux*
Affiliation:
Université de Montréal

Abstract

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I distinguish between two families of theories which view moral norms as either “inputs” or “outputs.” I argue that the most plausible version of each model can ultimately be seen as the two sides of the same model, which I call Moderate Nativism. The difference between these two apparently antagonistic models is one of perspective rather than content: while the Input model explains how emotional dispositions constrain the historical evolution of moral norms, the Output model explains how these same dispositions naturally give rise to corresponding moral judgments in individuals.

RÉSUMÉ: Dans cet article, je distingue deux familles théoriques qui conçoivent les normes morales comme des «intrants» (inputs) ou des «extrants» (outputs). Je soutiens que l’on peut ultimement unifier la meilleure version de ces deux modèles en un seul modèle théorique que je nomme l’Innéisme Modéré. La différence entre ces deux modèles apparemment antagonistes en est une de perspective plutôt que de contenu : alors que le modèle des intrants analyse l’impact de dispositions émotionnelles sur l’évolution historique des normes morales, le modèle des extrants s’intéresse plutôt au rôle de ces mêmes dispositions dans le développement de jugements moraux individuels.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abarbanell, L. and Hauser, M. C. 2010Mayan Morality: An Exploration of Permissible Harms.” Cognition 115: 207–24.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brown, D. 1991 Human Universals. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1986 Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
De Waal, F. B. M. 1996 Good Natured: The Origin of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dwyer, S. 1999 “Moral Competence.” In Philosophy and Linguistics, ed. Murasugi, K. and Strainton, R.. Boulder: Westview, 169–90.Google Scholar
Dwyer, S. 2006 “How Good is the Linguistic Analogy?” Vol. 2 of The Innate Mind, ed. Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., and Stich, S.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dwyer, S. 2008 “How Not to Argue That Morality Isn’t Innate: Comments on Prinz.” Vol. 2 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 407–18.Google Scholar
Fiske, A. P. 1991 Structures of Social Life: The Four Elementary Forms of Human Relations. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Foot, P. 1978 “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect.” In Virtues and Vices, ed. Foot, P.. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Haidt, J. and Joseph, C. 2004Intuitive Ethics: How Innately Prepared Intuitions Generate Culturally Variable Virtues.” Daedalus: On Human Nature 133: 55–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J. and Bjorklund, F. 2008 “Social Intuitionists Answer Six Questions about Moral Psychology.” Vol. 2 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 181–217.Google Scholar
Haidt, J. and Graham, J. 2007When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions That Liberals May Not Recognize.” Social Justice Research 20 (1): 98–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 2008“Using a Linguistic Analogy to Study Morality.” Vol. 1 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 344–51.Google Scholar
Hauser, M. D. 2006 Moral Minds: How Nature Designed Our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong. New York: Ecco Press.Google Scholar
Hauser, M. D., Young, L., and Cushman, F. 2008 “Reviving Rawls’s Linguistic Analogy: Operative Principles and the Causal Structure of Moral Actions.” Vol. 2 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 107–43.Google Scholar
Hauser, M. D., Cushman, F., Young, L., Jin, R. K.-X., and Mikhail, J. 2006A Dissociation between Moral Judgment and Justifications.” Mind and Language 22: 1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mallon, R. 2008 “Reviving Rawl’s Linguistic Analogy Inside and Out.” Vol. 2 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 145–55.Google Scholar
Mikhail, J. 2000 Rawls’ Linguistic Analogy: A Study of the ’Generative Grammar’ Model of Moral Theory Described by John Rawls in ’A Theory of Justice.’ Ph.D. diss., Cornell University.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mikhail, J. 2008 “The Poverty of the Moral Stimulus.” Vol. 1 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 353–59.Google Scholar
Mikhail, J., Sorrentino, C., and Spelke, E. 1998 “Toward a Universal Moral Grammar.” In Proceedings, Twentieth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, ed. Gernsbacher, M. A. and Derry, S. J.. Mahwah NJ: Earlbaum, 1250.Google Scholar
Morris, R. C. 1996Anthropology in the Body Shop: Lords of the Garden, Cannibalism, and the Consuming Desires of Televisual Anthropology.” American Anthropologist 98 (1): 137–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. 2004 Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. 2008 “Sentimentalism Naturalized.” Vol. 2 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.Boston: MIT Press, 255–74.Google Scholar
Pinker, S. 2002 The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. New York: Viking Penguin.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2007 The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2008 “Is Morality Innate?” Vol. 1 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 367–406.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2008 “Reply to Dwyer and Tiberius.” Vol. 1 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 427–39.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2008 “Resisting the Linguistic Analogy: A Commentary on Hauser, Young, and Cushman.” Vol. 2 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 157–70.Google Scholar
Rosaldo, M. Z. 1980 Knowledge and Passion: Llongot Notions of Self and the Social Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1930 The Right and the Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schwartz, S. H. and Bilsky, W. 1990Toward a Theory of the Universal Content and Structure of Value: Extensions and Cross-Cultural Replications.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 58: 878–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sekhar Sripada, C. 2008 “Nativism and Moral Psychology: Three Models of the Innate Structure that Shapes the Contents of Moral Norms.” Vol. 2 of Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Boston: MIT Press, 319–43.Google Scholar
Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., and Park, L. 1997 “The ’Big Three’ of Morality (Autonomy, Community, Divinity), and the ’Big Three’ Explanations of Suffering.” In Morality and Health, ed. Rozin, P. and Brandt, A.. New York: Routledge, 119–69.Google Scholar
Smetana, J. G. 1995 “Morality in Context: Abstractions, Ambiguities and Applications.” Vol. 10 in Annals of Child Development, ed. Vasta, R.. London: Jessica Kingsley, 83–130.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. 1994 “The Modularity of Thought and the Epidemiology of Representations.” In Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture, ed. Hirschfeld, L. A. and Gelman, S. A.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 39–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, D. and Hirschfeld, L. A. 2004The Cognitive Foundation of Cultural Stability and Diversity.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8: 40–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sterelny, K. 2010Moral Nativism: A Skeptical Response.” Mind and Language 25 (3): 279–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. 2006Is Morality an Elegant Machine or a Kludge?Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1–2): 181– 9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turiel, E. 1983 The Development of Social Knowledge: Morality and Convention. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Turiel, E. 1998 “The Development of Morality.” Vol. 3 of Handbook of Child Psychology, ed. Eisenberg, N.. New York: Wiley, 863–932.Google Scholar
Turiel, E. 2002 The Culture of Morality: Social Development, Context, and Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, G. 2005 “Responsibility and the Limits of Evil: Variation on a Strawsonian Theme.” In Free Will: Critical Concepts in Philosophy, ed. Fisher., J. M.New York: Routledge, 206–37.Google Scholar
Wielenberg, E. T. 2010On the Evolutionary Debunking of Morality.” Ethics 120 (3): 441–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar