Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T14:59:02.229Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hume's Hurdle

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 June 2010

Stanley G. French
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario

Extract

The subject of this paper is the relationship between factual beliefs and moral beliefs, between is-statements and ought-statements. Hume recognizes that a problem exists concerning this relationship. He states the problem in an oft-quoted passage from his Treatise. In their writings, moral philosophers pass imperceptibly from is-statements to ought-statements; and this change is “of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, 'tis necessary that it shou'd be observ'd and explain'd; and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it”.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1963

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature. Selby-Bigge edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1958. III-I-iGoogle Scholar. Though it appears in this passage that Hume's criticism is directed only at the moral theories of moral philosophers, it is obvious that what Hume says applies to anyone using an argument involving is-statements and ought-statements.

2 Hare, R. M., The Language of Morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952. p. 29ff.Google ScholarPrior, A. N., Logic and the Basic Of Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949. pp. 3233.Google ScholarNowell-Smith, P. H., Ethics. Pelican, 1959. pp. 3638.Google Scholar

3 MacIntyre, A. C., “Hume On ‘Is’ And ‘Ought’,” Philosophical Review. 1959. pp. 451468.CrossRefGoogle ScholarHampshire, S., “Fallacies in Moral Philosophy”, Mind. 1949. p. 466ff.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

4 I have purposely chosen not to define such words as belief and statement, for I am content with their ordinary usage. I should point out, however, that I am not using belief in Hume's technical sense, (Treatise, I-3-vii, passim).

5 Kant, Critique Of Pure Reason. Norman Kemp Smith, trans. B375.

6 See Kant, , Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals. Beck, trans. New York: Liberal Arts, 1959. p. 59ff.Google Scholar

7 Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica. Cambridge: University Press, 1960. p. 9ff.Google Scholar

8 Other Intuitionists, like Sir W. David Ross and A. C. Ewing, follow Moore in asserting Hume's hurdle. The word intuition itself is usually used to mean that we cannot or do not reason in arriving at moral decisions.

9 The school of meta-ethics often referred to as ‘Emotivism’, represented by such philosophers as Stevenson and Ayer, is also asserting the unbridgeable gap when it refers to ought-statements as solely or primarily emotive.

10 De Morgan, Augustus, A Budget of Paradoxes. London: Longmans, Green, 1872. p. 2.Google Scholar

11 I should, perhaps, point out that in this paper I am concerned with ought-statements expressing ends (rather than means). I am concerned with what Kant called categorical imperatives, as distinct from hypothetical imperatives. Statements like If you want to be happy, you ought not to commit adultery are, so far as I can see, purely factual, and their truth-values are discoverable empirically. But people do say ϒou ought not to commit adultery, regarding abstention from adultery as an end in itself.

12 I think, though the philosophers concerned may not agree, that Nowell-Smith argues in this way, especially in passages about “logical oddness”, and that Stephen Toulmin tries to do the same thing when talking about “limiting questions”. Toulmin, , The Place of Reason in Ethics. Cambridge: University Press, 1960.Google Scholar

13 Mandelbaum, M., “On the Use of Moral Principles”, Journal of Philosophy. 1956. pp. 662670.CrossRefGoogle ScholarDemos, R., “Is Moral Reasoning Deductive?”, Journal of Philosophy. 1958. pp. 153159. By the end of his paper, Demos is virtually admitting that moral reasoning does not fit the inductive pattern.CrossRefGoogle Scholar