Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T14:50:38.283Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

COMPANION TO PLOTINUS REVISITED - (L.P.) Gerson, (J.) Wilberding (edd.) The New Cambridge Companion to Plotinus. Pp. xxiv + 471, figs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022. Paper, £26.99, US$34.99 (Cased, £79.99, US$105). ISBN: 978-1-108-72623-8 (978-1-108-48834-1 hbk).

Review products

(L.P.) Gerson, (J.) Wilberding (edd.) The New Cambridge Companion to Plotinus. Pp. xxiv + 471, figs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022. Paper, £26.99, US$34.99 (Cased, £79.99, US$105). ISBN: 978-1-108-72623-8 (978-1-108-48834-1 hbk).

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 November 2023

Anna Motta*
Affiliation:
University of Naples “Federico II”
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association

This New Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, edited by Lloyd P. Gerson and James Wilberding, comes 25 years after The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, edited by Gerson. The publication of a new Companion devoted to Plotinus stems from the need not only to address fundamental philosophical issues in the Enneads (as in the case of the earlier volume), but also to do so in the light of new findings concerning ancient texts and neglected topics.

Like the previous volume, this new one includes sixteen contributions by specialists in the Platonist tradition, who outline the main problems in a clear manner. The work is preceded by an introduction by Gerson, who has not authored any of the chapters, and by the list of the Enneads, both as arranged by Porphyry and in their chronological order. The chapters are divided into five thematic sections (Part 1: ‘Historical Context’; Part 2: ‘Metaphysics and Epistemology’; Part 3: ‘Psychology’; Part 4: ‘Natural Philosophy’; Part 5: ‘Ethics’). Rather than providing a systematic treatment, these thematic sections offer a selection of specific topics that are thoroughly discussed, showing that it is impossible to separate any aspect of Plotinus’ philosophy from his metaphysical thought and historical background. Moreover, the book clearly points to the need to read Plotinus by tackling the difficulties related to the structure of the dialogues, the enigmatic nature of certain Platonic statements, and the importance of Aristotle and of Plotinus’ criticism of Aristotelian metaphysical positions, as well as Plotinus’ polemics against the Stoics, Epicureans and Peripatetics.

The volume is well balanced and provides a convincing outline of Plotinus’ philosophy, even though the structure of the contributions varies: some discuss long textual excerpts, while others opt for a broader reassessment of specific topics in the light of new doctrinal acquisitions, preferring to focus the analysis on a few textual examples. The book's chapters, both individually and as a whole, succeed in demonstrating the strength of the arguments presented and the complexity of Plotinus’ exegetical world. All the chapters support their arguments with substantial notes, located at the end of each, which helps ensure a smooth textual flow. The index locorum allots approximately nine pages to thinkers other than Plotinus and about thirteen to Plotinus. While there are no glaring inconsistencies, cross-references are almost absent.

In the introduction, rather than stressing that the volume serves as a reference work for students who are new to Plotinus and non-specialists who will benefit from clear and lucid remarks, Gerson correctly emphasises the usefulness of a new Companion especially in relation to the considerable increase in studies on Neoplatonism: this is demonstrated by the 33-page final bibliography (vs the 22-page one in the previous volume), which is not only up to date but also carefully laid out for each chapter. At the same time, the volume is not meant to replace a direct reading of Plotinus; rather, it is designed to serve as a valuable guide to the Enneads with all its details, obscurities and contradictions, especially because Plotinus’ writings can hardly be regarded as systematic: the Plotinian ‘system’ ultimately concerns basic entities, principles of operation and the effort to develop a unified explanation of the world.

The first part emphasises the need to place Plotinus in a historical context that, nevertheless, remains limited to the exegesis of Plato and Aristotle, Gnosticism and Christianity, and later Platonism. E.D. Perl, ‘Plato and Aristotle in the Enneads’, opens the first section by reflecting on Plotinus’ complex relationship with Plato and Aristotle. Interestingly, Perl detects an early tendency in Plotinus to harmonise Plato and Aristotle. So – if I understand correctly – Perl is not arguing that Plotinus was truly responsible for the integration of Plato and Aristotle, but rather highlighting the fact that in Plotinus we can detect a Platonic use of Aristotle to refute certain theories, based on an acknowledgement of certain points of continuity between Plato and Aristotle. S. Gertz, in ‘Plotinus, Gnosticism, and Christianity’, offers an interesting analysis of the relationship between Plotinus and the major religious movements of his time, namely Christianity and Gnosticism. Gertz shows that it would be possible to read Plotinus’ criticism of the Gnostics as an indirect attack on Christians too, since the philosopher may have seen the Gnostics as a Christian splinter group. While familiar with Plato, the Gnostics turned to esoteric texts, published under the guise of Eastern wisdom and purporting to be divine revelations concerning the intelligible world and the origin and destiny of the universe and the human soul. M. Martijn's chapter, ‘From Plotinus to Proclus’, discusses the relationship between Plotinus and the other Neoplatonists, showing that the Neoplatonists share certain common assumptions and proceed by gradually developing seeds already present in Plotinus. G. Aubry's chapter, ‘The One as First Principle of All’, is devoted to Plotinus’ main innovation, namely the postulation of an absolutely transcendent first principle. One of the problems related to this postulation, and discussed in the chapter, is the possibility (or rather almost the contradiction) of only being able to reach this principle through an experience of complete absorption into the One, i.e. a mystical experience.

Part 2 delves into the conceptual framework of Plotinus’ metaphysics. It opens with a chapter by M. Bonazzi, ‘Plotinus and the Theory of Forms’, reconstructing Plotinus’ view of Plato's theory of Forms. He rediscusses the Middle Platonic effort to define the causal role of the Forms and Aristotle's theory of Intellect according to a perspective that supports the notion of the coincidence between knowledge and being, and consequently between epistemology and ontology. S. Slaveva-Griffin's chapter, ‘Plotinus on Number’, concerns the essential role of number in the Neoplatonic model of the universe. The chapter demonstrates that Plotinus is not interested in quantitative and arithmetical numbers. Slaveva-Griffin explains why number, which is an ontological unity, is ‘substantial’ for Plotinus by reinterpreting Aristotle's understanding of the quantitative production of number in light of the generation of Intellect and the one–many structure of the intelligible world. M.J. Griffin, in ‘Plotinus on Categories’, presents Plotinus’ categories for intelligible being and sensibles, elucidating the philosopher's criticism not only of Aristotle's categories, but also of the Stoic ones. C. Tornau, in ‘Plotinus on Knowledge’, points out that the Plotinian theory of knowledge overcomes certain problems raised by Scepticism. Even if the Sceptics’ point about sense perception is granted, the cognition of Intellect is infallible because it is immediate and non-representative: Intellect knows its objects simply by knowing itself; hence, Plotinus’ great epistemological paradox may be seen to lie in the fact that all knowledge is fundamentally self-knowledge.

Part 3 deals with the topics of the union of soul and body, the powers of the soul, the passions of the soul, sensitive perception, memory and imagination, and the theory of individuality. Each of these points is investigated with great precision. D. Caluori, in ‘The Embodied Soul’, reconstructs Plotinus’ account of body–soul relations and operations as a synthesis of Platonic theories, Aristotelian principles and Galen's anatomical discoveries. He then discusses the rational form of the soul by explaining how this soul is active in relation to the body even though its activities do not take place in the body. In particular, he shows that Plotinus interprets and generalises a statement in the Timaeus that the body of the world is in the World-Soul. P. Remes's chapter, ‘Self-Knowledge and Self-Reflexivity’, analyses the problem of self-knowledge as part of Plotinian epistemology. Remes demonstrates that Plotinus addresses both the issue of the structural characteristics of self-reflexivity and self-consciousness and that of ethically purposed self-conversion.

Like the other sections, Part 4 presents contributions that also engage with Plotinus’ philosophical background and his knowledge of Aristotle's treatises. R. Chiaradonna's ‘Eternity and Time’ is the first of only two chapters that had the same title in the earlier Companion. It deals with an issue that is not only fascinating, but also puzzling. A. Smith, the author of the chapter on eternity and time in the earlier Companion, had certainly stressed this point, but without grasping an interesting feature of the Enneads as a whole, namely the use of the first-person plural ‘we’, which Chiaradonna analyses in depth. D.M. Hutchinson, in ‘Composition of Sensible Bodies’, sets out to re-evaluate Plotinus’ natural philosophy, by outlining Plotinus’ attempt to show that Aristotle's theory of primary substance is incomplete and incoherent (also by comparison to Plato's Timaeus). J. Wilberding, in ‘Nature: Plotinus’ Fourth Hypostasis?’, discusses the idea that with Plotinus we can start talking about the ‘metaphysics of nature’. This chapter also demonstrates the importance of placing a precise topic in a broader theoretical framework: to examine Plotinus’ account of Nature, it is necessary to take his theory of procession and reversion into consideration.

The fifth and last part is a well-reasoned attempt to examine how Plotinus incorporates the world, the problem of evil and fate into his ethical framework. The subject of J. Opsomer's chapter, ‘Matter and Evil’, had already been addressed in the earlier Companion by D. O'Brien, who had reached the conclusion that Plotinus was able to preserve the idea of non-being as a ‘contrary’ by circumventing Aristotle's Categories. For his part, Opsomer emphasises how Plotinus assimilates ‘true non-being’ with evil and matter, that is evil itself and the principle of evil. He therefore highlights how Plotinus uses Plato's Sophist to explain that evil is a special kind of non-being. However, evil is not non-being as absolute non-being, because that simply does not exist, nor is it non-being as otherness. Rather, it is non-being as ‘a kind of form, that is, of what is not’, namely ‘the part of the nature of the other that is opposed to the being of each thing’ (p. 346). M. Tuominen, in ‘Virtue and Happiness’, analyses the treatises On Virtues and On Happiness to show that ethics is not an entirely theoretical affair. She offers insightful observations on the Plotinian way of proceeding, which entails criticism of other philosophical schools. C.I. Noble, in ‘Plotinus on Providence and Fate’, interestingly shows that Plotinus’ discussions of providence and destiny are influenced by Timaeus’ non-literal exegesis of the cosmological account and are largely directed at resolving the apparent tensions within Platonism regarding the goodness and teleological orientation of the cosmos.

The picture that emerges from this new Companion is highly interesting, useful and almost complete, despite the divergent research perspectives and approaches adopted by the various authors. The only shortcoming of the volume arguably lies in the absence of a discussion concerning the literary form used to convey Plotinus’ innovative way of doing philosophy in the classroom, a topic whose importance scholars tend to underestimate.