Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T09:27:20.601Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Eyxomai EyxΩ9Bh and EyxoΣ in Homer

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 February 2009

A. W. H. Adkins
Affiliation:
University of Reading

Extract

This paper will discuss the behaviour of and in the Homeric poems. These words are allotted a variety of different ‘meanings’ by the lexicographers. For example, LSJ s.v. I. pray, II. vow, III. profess loudly, boast, vaunt; s.v. I. prayer, II. boast, vaunt, or object of boasting, glory; s.v. I. thing prayed for, object of prayer, II. boast, vaunt. I shall, of course, discuss the whole range of these words; but I begin with some observations on ‘prayer’.

It may appear at first sight that ‘prayer’ is a simple word, with only one conceivable ‘meaning’, which must have that ‘meaning’ in any language. We might suggest that ‘request addressed to a god’ is an adequate representation of that ‘meaning’, and that when we have rendered (say) by ‘pray’ in what appear to us to be appropriate contexts we have conveyed the full sense of the original.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 1969

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 21 note 1 Aeschylus' gods can certainly hear from a great distance, Supp. 100 ff.,Google ScholarEum. 292 ff., 397 f. However, it seems to be necessary to make the point even in the fifth century.Google Scholar

page 21 note 2 For arguments in support of these sweeping statements, see Adkins, , Merit and Responsibility, Chapter III;Google ScholarHonour and Punishment in the Homeric Poems’, B.I.C.S. vii (1960), pp. 3 ff.;Google ScholarFriendship and Self-Sufficiency in Homer and Aristotle’, C.Q., N.s. xiii (1963), 30 ff.Google Scholar

page 22 note 1 This last is a theodicy; cf. Merit and Responsibility, 24 f.Google Scholar

page 23 note 1 Not ‘dear’, ‘beloved’; cf. Friendship and Self-sufficiency in Homer and Aristotle’, C.Q. N.S. xiii (1963), 30 ff.Google Scholar

page 23 note 2 Note the occurrence of again, in what lexicographers treat as quite a different sense, just two lines after in the usage they translate by ‘pray’.

page 25 note 1 Zeus' protection of suppliants does not imply a concern for the well-being of mankind in general, and can be regarded as a function or aspect of his Once he has accepted suppliants under his protection, it would be for him not to defend them successfully, just as the human protects accepted suppliants against potential enemies, for it would be to fail in protecting anyone admitted as a member, permanent or transient, of one's own (It is against the human himself that the suppliant particularly needs Zeus' protection, for it would not be for the to harm the suppliant.) The need for a belief in a god of suppliants is evident: the society possesses no readily transportable wealth, so that anyone who travels far, particularly by land, needs the hospitality of others; it has no belief in human rights as such, only in rights derived from membership of a particular group, so that the unaccepted suppliant has no rights at all in the society into which he has come; and news travelled slowly, and a man on a journey could easily vanish without trace. Neither Zeus nor the human need entertain any friendly emotion towards the suppliant: what is needed is protective action (cf. Friendship and Self-Sufficiency in Homer and Aristotle’, C.Q. N.S. xiii [1963], 30 ff.).Google Scholar