Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-03T07:53:58.244Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Tribal Traditions and European-Western Political Ideologies: The Dilemma of Canada's Native Indians

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 November 2009

Menno Boldt
Affiliation:
University of Lethbridge
J. Anthony Long
Affiliation:
University of Lethbridge

Abstract

Native Indian leaders in Canada have embraced the European-Western doctrine of sovereignty as the political-legal instrumentality for achieving their version of “the good society.” This article analyzes the appropriateness and feasibility of sovereign statehood for Canada's Indians. Indian aspirations to sovereign statehood run aground on at least two counts: key ideas contained in the European-Western doctrine of sovereignty are incompatible with core values comprising traditional Indian culture: also, the Canadian government is implacably opposed to relinquishing its sovereignty over Indians. This study explores alternative models of self-determination for Canada's Indians and concludes that stateless nationhood offers the best basis on which Indians may be able to negotiate internal self-determination.

Résumé

Les dirigeants amérindiens du Canada ont épousé la doctrine europo-occidentale de souveraineté comme moyen politique légitime pour réaliser leur modèle de « la bonne société ». Cette analyse examine l'à-propos et la possibilité pour les Amérindiens du Canada de réaliser un état souverain. Les aspirations des Amérindiens à l'état de souveraineté butent contre deux obstacles majeurs: les idées maîtresses contenues dans la doctrine europo-occidentale de souveraineté sont incompatibles avec les valeurs essentielles de la culture amérindienne traditionnelle: d'autre part, le gouvernement canadien est implacablement opposé à se dessaisir du droit de souveraineté dont il dispose à l'égard des Amérindiens. Après avoir examiné différents modèles d'auto-détermination pour les Amérindiens du Canada, cette étude conclue que le concept de nation et non pas d'état-nation souverain offre aux Amérindiens la meilleure base de négotiations pour obtenir leur auto-détermination.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association (l'Association canadienne de science politique) and/et la Société québécoise de science politique 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 The claim to tribal sovereignty is regularly asserted by Indian leaders in Canada and is virtually always explicit in the written representations that provincial and national Indian organizations have made to the Canadian government. For example, see Assembly of First Nations, “Memorandum Concerning the Rights of First Nations and the Canadian Constitution,” June 16, 1982: Federation of Saskatchewan Indians. “Indian Nationhood and Indian Government,” 1977; Proceedings of the Indian Government Development Conference (Ottawa: National Indian Brotherhood, 1979): Union of British Columbia Indian Chiefs, “Indian Nations: Determination or Termination,” October 1980; and Assembly of First Nations, “Opening Remarks for Presentation by David Ahenakew, National Chief, Assembly of First Nations to the First Ministers' Conference on Aboriginal Rights,” March 15, 1983. The consensus among Indian leaders at the band level regarding inherent sovereignty was also strongly evidenced in the testimony of 567 witnesses, representing Indian bands from every province, before the Special Committee on Indian Self-Government of the House of Commons. The Committee has stated that witnesses unanimously rejected the federal government's proposed band-government bill principally because that proposal involved a delegation of power rather than a recognition of the sovereignty of Indian First Nations' governments. See Indian Self-Government in Canada, report of the Special Committee on Indian Self-Government. House of Commons. October 20. 1983, 24.Google Scholar

2 Boldt, Menno, “Intellectural Orientations and Nationalism Among Indian Leaders in an Internal Colony: A Theoretical and Comparative Perpsective,” British Journal of Sociology 33 (1982), 484510;CrossRefGoogle ScholarEnlightenment Values, Romanticism and Attitudes Toward Political Status: A Study of Native Indian Leaders in Canada,” Canadian Review of Sociology and Anthropology 18 (1981), 545–65.Google Scholar

3 Lurie, Nancy Oestreich, “The Contemporary American Indian Scene,” in Leacock, Eleanor B. and Lurie, Nancy Oestreich (eds.), American Indians in Historical Perspective (New York: Random House, 1971), 443–46.Google Scholar

4 Youngblood-Henderson, James. “Comment,” in Swagerty, W. R. (ed.). Indian Sovereignty: Proceedings of the Second Annual Conference on Problems and Issues Concerning American Indians Today (Chicago: Newberry Library, 1979). 7172.Google Scholar

5 JrMerriam, Charles E., History of the Theory of Sovereignty Since Rousseau (New York: AMS Press, 1968), 83Google Scholar; and Sir Barker, Ernest, Essays on Government (2nd ed.; Oxford: Clarendon, 1960), 100.Google Scholar

6 Merriam, , History of the Theory of Sovereignty Since Rousseau, 65.Google Scholar

7 See Stankewicz, W. J., “Sovereignty as Political Theory,” Political Studies 24 (1966), 142.Google Scholar

8 Easton, David, “The Perception of Authority and Political Change,” in Friedrich, Carl J. (ed.), Authority (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1958), 184.Google Scholar

9 See A Basic Call to Consciousness: The Hau de no sau nee Address to the Western World (Rooseveltown, N.Y.: Akwesasne Notes, 1977): and Alfonso Ortiz, “Summary,” in W. R. Swagerty (ed.), Indian Sovereignty.Google Scholar

10 Laslett, Peter, “The Face to Face Society,” in Laslett, Peter (ed.). Philosophy. Politics and Society (Oxford: Blackwell, 1963), 167.Google Scholar

11 Svensson, Frances, “Liberal Democracy and Group Rights: The Legacy of Individualism and Its Impact on American Indian Tribes,” Political Studies 27 (1980). 421–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 Youngblood-Henderson, , in Swagerty, W. R. (ed.), Indian Sovereignty, 77.Google Scholar

13 Ibid., 58.

14 It is worth noting that many of the values termed “enlightenment” values have been found by various students of native Indian society to be indigenous, in approximate form and in varying degrees, to the cultures of many native tribes in North America. See for example, Hamilton, C. E., Cry of the Thunderbird: The American Indian's Own Story (New York: Macmillan, 1950)Google Scholar; MacKenzie, J. B., The Six Nations Indians in Canada (Toronto: Hunter Rose, 1896), 35Google Scholar; Forbes, J. D., The Indians in American Past (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1964)Google Scholar; Catlin, George, in Ross, M. (ed.), Episodes From Life Among the Indians and Last Rambles (Norman, Oklahoma, 1959Google Scholar) Smith, M. W., Indians of the Urban North-West (New York: Columbia University Press, 1949), 13Google Scholar; and JrJosephy, A. M., The Indian Heritage of America (New York: Bantam Books, 1968), 119Google Scholar. See also, in this connection, Boldt, Menno, “Social Correlates of Romanticism: A Study of Leadership in an Internal Colony,” Ethnic Groups 3 (1981), 307–32Google Scholar. It is a matter of historical record that philosophers from Montaigne to Rousseau were influenced by what they understood to be the enlightened state of North American Indians. Egalitarianism was the most prevalent, though not the universal, model. See, for exceptions, Drucker, Philip, Indians of the Northwest Coast (Garden City, N.Y.: Natural History Press, 1963), chap. 4. For such exceptional tribes sovereignty does not hold all of the cultural contradictions that we identify in this article.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Miller, Walter B., “Two Concepts of Authority,” American Anthropologist 57 (1955), 271–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 Ibid.

17 In European-Western society we have something akin to this notion of authority in what Friedrich has called “procedural authority.” Somewhat along this same line, the Americans substituted the impersonal authority of the Constitution for the personal authority of George III. Friedrich, Carl J., “Authority, Values, and policy.” in Friedrich, (ed.). Authority, 54.Google Scholar

18 Rees, W. J., “The Theory of Sovereignty Restated,” in Peter Laslett (ed.). Philosophy, Politics and Society, 58.Google Scholar

19 Merriam, History of the Theory of Sovereignty Since Rousseau, 138.

20 Lowie, R. H, “Property Rights and Coercive Powers of Plains Indians,” Journal of Legal and Political Sociology 1 (1943), 5971.Google Scholar

21 Arendt, Hannah, “What Was Authority?” in Friedrich, C. J. (ed.), Authority, 102–04.Google Scholar

22 Dorris, Michael, “Twentieth Century Indians: The Return of the Natives,” in Hall, Raymond L. (ed.), Ethnic Autonomy, Comparative Dynamics: The Americas, Europe and the Developing World (New York: Pergamon Press, 1979), 71.Google Scholar

23 Simon, Yves R., “Sovereignty in Democracy,” in Stankiewicz, W. J. (ed.), In Defense of Sovereignty (New York: Oxford University Press, 1969), 244.Google Scholar

24 This is possible only in face-to-face societies such as the Indian tribes were. See Laslett in Peter Laslett (ed.), Philosophy. Politics and Society, 158. for a discussion of the characteristics of such societies.

25 Merriam, History of the Theory of Sovereignty Since Rousseau, 202-03.

26 Hinsley, Frances F., Sovereignty (London: C. A. Walls. 1966), 16.Google Scholar

27 Quoted in Werhan, Keith W., “The Sovereignty of Indian Tribes: A Reaffirmation and Strengthening in the 1970's,” Notre Dame Lawyer 54 (1978), 525.Google Scholar

28 Melody, Michael E., “Lakota Myth and Government: The Cosmos as the State,” American Indian Culture and Research Journal 4 (1980), 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29 Laslett characterizes this de-emphasis of territoriality as one of the defining characteristics of the political form of a face-to-face society, because geographically defined borders are not suited for nor capable of giving a sense of political consciousness or identity to the members of such groups. That is why Indians retained their sense of nationhood even during the forced mass-migrations. They carried their concept of “nationhood” on their backs. See Laslett, in Peter Laslett (ed.), Philosophy, Politics and Society.

30 Ahenakew, David. “Aboriginal Title and Aboriginal Rights: The Impossible and Unnecessary Task of Identification and Definition.” 1984.Google Scholar

31 A Basic Call to Consciousness, and Saskatchewan Federation of Indians. “Indian Nationhood and Indian Government.” 1977.

32 We are not here advocating the reconstructionist anthropologists' position that Indians should change into what they once were. But, neither should they be forced to adopt alien political ideas that distort what they value most in their cultural heritage. They should be free to adopt a model of government that will preserve what they value in their cultural traditions.

33 Government of Canada, “Opening Statement by the Prime Minister of Canada, The Right Honourable Pierre Elliott Trudeau to the Constitutional Conference of First Ministers on the Rights of Aboriginal Peoples,” March 15, 1983, 16.

34 McRae, Kenneth D., “The Plural Society and the Western Political Tradition,” this JOURNAL 12 (1979), 677–78.Google Scholar

35 For a discussion of consociationalism in Canada see Bakvis, Herman, Federalism and the Organization of Political Life: Canada in Comparative Perspective (Kingston: Institute of Intergovernmental Relations, Queen's University, 1981), 62189Google Scholar: and McRae, Kenneth D. (ed.). Consociational Democracy: Political Accommodation in Segmented Societies (Toronto: McClelland and Stewart, 1974), 253–99.Google Scholar

36 See Van Dyke, Vernon. “Human Rights and the Rights of Groups.” American Journal of Political Science 18 (1974), 725–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar: Justice as Fairness: For Groups?”, American Political Science Review 69 (1975), 607–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar; The Individual, the State, and Ethnic Communities in Political Theory,” World Politics 29 (1977). 343–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar: Collective Entities and Moral Rights: Problems in Liberal-Democratic Thought.” Journal of Politics 44 (1982), 2140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

37 Van Dyke, “Human Rights and the Rights of Groups.”

38 Nisbet, Robert A., Community and Power (New York: Oxford University Press, 1962), 224.Google Scholar

39 Additionally, a major treaty has been in force for Canada since August 1979. Article of the Covenant on Civil and Political Rights provides that:

1. All peoples have the right of self-determination. By virtue of that right they freely determine their political status and freely pursue their economic, social and cultural development.

2. All peoples may, for their own ends, freely dispose of their natural wealth and resources without prejudice to any obligations arising out of international economic cooperation, based upon the principle of mutual benefit, and international law. In no case may a people be deprived of its own means of subsistence.

3. The States Parties to the present Covenant… shall promote the realization of the right of self-determination and shall respect that right, in conformity with the provisions of the Charter of the United Nations.

As a party to this covenant, Canada is obliged to report on the “measures… adopted which give effect to the rights recognized” (Article 40[l]) to a body set up under the treaty called the Human Rights Committee.

40 See also, Bell, Wendell, Jamaican Leaders: Political Attitudes in a New Nation (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1964)Google Scholar; The Democratic Revolution in the West Indies: Studies in Nationalism, Leadership and the Belief in Progress (Cambridge, Mass.: Schenkman, 1967)Google Scholar; “New States in the Caribbean: A Grounded Theoretical Account,” in Eisenstadt, S. N. and Rokkan, Stein (eds.), Building States and Nations: Analysis by Region, Vol. 2 (Beverly Hills: Sage, 1975)Google Scholar; and Equality and Social Justice: Foundations of Nationalism in the Caribbean,” Caribbean Studies 20 (1980), 536.Google Scholar

41 The European colonizer's position on Indian sovereignty has been inconsistent and opportunistic; see F. Jennings, “Sovereignty in Anglo-American History,” in W. R. Swagerty (ed.), Indian Sovereignty, and Keith W. Werhan, “The Sovereignty of Indian Tribes,”5-25. Initially, to avoid conflict amongst themselves, Euopean powers introduced the doctrine of “discovery” to regulate competition for colonial territory. Subsequently, this doctrine was used as justification for declaring sovereignty over Indians on grounds that they were savages, they did not work the land, and had no civil government: see Keller, A. S., Lissitzyn, O. J. and Mann, F. J., Creation of Rights of Sovereignty Through Symbolic Acts 1400-1800 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1958). At the same time, in order to avoid war and risk defeat, the British ostensibly recognized Indian tribes as sovereign nations and negotiated treaties with them. It is important to note that British claims to sovereignty over Indians were never based on “consent of the people.” Even today, although they live in a “representative democracy,” so far as Indians in Canada are concerned, the Canadian government does not derive its powers to govern Indians from the consent of the Indian people.Google Scholar

42 Connor, Walker, “Ethnic Nationalism as a Political Force,” World Affairs 133 (1970), 9197Google Scholar: Nation-Building or Nation-Destroying,” World Politics 24 (1972). 319–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar: and A Nation is a Nation, is a State, is an Ethnic Group is a …Ethnic and Racial Studies, 1 (1978). 377400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

43 Connor. “A Nation is a Nation…,” 379.

44 Connor. “Ethnic Nationalism as a Political Force.” 93.

45 Piano, Jack C. and Olton, Ray, The International Relations Dictionary (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1969).Google Scholar

46 Emerson, Rupert, “Self-Determination,” American Journal of International Law 65 (1971), 459–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

47 Barker asserts that on moral and practical grounds sovereignty cannot exist for a “nation” which is a minority within a state. Because, if every national group in the world were assumed to be entitled to sovereign statehood it would create chaos and threaten the authority of existing sovereign states. See Sir Barker, Ernest, Principles of Social and Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1951), 139. Furthermore, the claim that Indian tribes existed as “sovereign states” is vulnerable to the argument that if ever they had such a status, they have now suffered a total loss of sovereignty because their paramount legislative authority has been effectively usurped by another state. The claim that they existed, and continue to exist, as “nations” is not as vulnerable to such an argument.Google Scholar

48 Boldt, Menno, “Philosophy, Politics and Extralegal Action: Native Indian Leaders in Canada,” Ethnic and Racial Studies 4 (1981), 205–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar