Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T00:44:08.217Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Non-mereological pluralistic supersubstantivalism: an alternative perspective on the matter/spacetime relationship

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Travis Dumsday*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy & Religious Studies, Concordia University of Edmonton, Edmonton, Canada

Abstract

In both the historical and contemporary literature on the metaphysics of space (and, more recently, spacetime), a core dispute is that between relationism and substantivalism. One version of the latter is supersubstantivalism, according to which space (or, again, spacetime) is the only kind of substance, such that what we think of as individual material objects (electrons, quarks, etc.) are actually just parts of spacetime which instantiate certain properties. If those parts are ontologically dependent on spacetime as a whole, then we arrive at an ontology with only a single genuinely independent substance, namely the entire spacetime manifold. This is monist supersubstantivalism. A view on which the parts of spacetime are ontologically prior to the whole has been called pluralistic supersubstantivalism. As currently formulated, supersubstantivalism (in either its monist or pluralistic forms) carries significant advantages and encounters major difficulties. I argue that some of the latter motivate an alternative formulation, non-mereological pluralistic supersubstantivalism, according to which spacetime is a real substance, but what we think of as material objects are also real substances, irreducible to and numerically distinct from that larger spacetime manifold and any of its parts. Yet, the underlying nature of those material objects is ultimately the same type as that of spacetime: at bottom, a particle is just a smaller quantity of spacetime embedded in or contained by or co-located with the larger whole that we would normally think of as ‘spacetime, ’ capable both of genuine movement within/across the larger spacetime manifold and (at least in principle) independent existence from it.

Type
Critical Notice
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, David. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Arntzenius, Frank. 2012. Space, Time, and Stuff. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, John. 1951. Mathematics: Queen and Servant of Science. New York: Mathematical Society of America.Google Scholar
Bennett, Jonathan. 1999. “Space and Subtle Matter in Descartes’s Metaphysics.” In New Essays on the Rationalists, edited by Gennaro, R. and Heunemann, C., 325. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dumsday, Travis. 2010. “Natural Kinds and the Problem of Complex Essences.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88: 619634.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis. 2015a. “Some Ontological Consequences of Atomism.” Ratio: An International Journal of Analytic Philosophy 28: 119134.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis. 2015b. “Atoms Vs. Extended Simples: Towards a Dispositionalist Reconciliation.” Philosophia: Philosophical Quarterly of Israel 43: 1023-1033.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellis, Brian. 2001. Scientific Essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian. 2002. The Philosophy of Nature: A Guide to the New Essentialism. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, Hartry. 1989. Realism, Mathematics, and Modality. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gilmore, Cody. 2014. “Building Enduring Objects out of Spacetime.” In Mereology and the Sciences, edited by Calosi, C. and Graziani, P., 534. Dodrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Grant, Sarah. 2013. “The Metaphysics of Space-Time Substantivalism: A Methodological Study of the Structure of Space-Time in the Context of General Relativity.” Doctoral Dissertation, University of Otago.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary. 1997. Substance: Its Nature and Existence. London: Routledge. 10.4324/9780203296707CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleinschmidt, Shieva, ed. 2014. Mereology and Location. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehmkuhl, Dennis. forthcoming. “The Metaphysics of Super-Substantivalism.” Pre-print available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/11528/Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Loux, Michael. 1974. “Kinds and the Dilemma of Individuation.” Review of Metaphysics 27: 773784.Google Scholar
Loux, Michael. 1978. Substance and Attribute: A Study in Ontology. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loux, Michael. 2002. Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction. 2nd ed. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 1989. Kinds of Being: A Study of Individuation, Identity, and the Logic of Sortal Terms. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 1994. “Primitive Substances.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 531552. 10.2307/2108580CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 1998. “Form without Matter.” Ratio 11: 214234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2000. “Locke, Martin, and Substance.” Philosophical Quarterly 50: 499514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2006. The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2012. “A Neo-Aristotelian Substance Ontology: Neither Relational Nor Constituent.” In Contemporary Aristotelian Metaphysics, edited by Tahko, Tuomas, 229248. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Macdonald, Cynthia. 2005. Varieties of Things: Foundations of Contemporary Metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C. B. 1980. “Substance Substantiated.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58: 310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreland, J. P. 1998. “Theories of Individuation: A Reconsideration of Bare Particulars.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79: 251263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morganti, Matteo. 2011. “Substrata and Properties: From Bare Particulars to Supersubstantivalism?Metaphysica 12: 183195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oderberg, David. 2007. Real Essentialism. London: Routledge. 10.4324/9780203356753Google Scholar
Oderberg, David. 2011. “Essence and Properties.” Erkenntnis 75: 85111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. 1981. “Things and Their Place in Theories.” In Theories and Things, edited by Quine, W. V. O., 123. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2009. “Spacetime the One Substance.” Philosophical Studies 145: 131148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skow, Brian. 2005. Once upon a Spacetime. Doctoral Dissertation, New York University.Google Scholar
Sider, Ted. 2001. Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Ted. 2006. “Bare Particulars.” Philosophical Perspectives 20: 387397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simons, Peter. 1994. “Particulars in Particular Clothing: Three Trope Theories of Substance.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 553575. 10.2307/2108581CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smolin, Lee. 2013. Time Reborn: From the Crisis in Physics to the Future of the Universe. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter. 2011. “Relational vs. Constituent Ontologies.” Philosophical Perspectives 25: 389405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar