Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T05:08:30.189Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The New Puzzle of Moral Deference

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2020

Max Lewis*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, The University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA, USA

Abstract

Philosophers think that there is something fishy about moral deference. The most common explanation of this fishiness is that moral deference doesn’t yield the epistemic states necessary for certain moral achievements (e.g., acting with moral worth or being virtuous). First, I argue that this explanation overgeneralizes. It entails that using many intuitively kosher belief-formation methods (e.g., abduction, reductio ad absurdum, and intuition) should be off-putting. Second, I argue that moral deference is sometimes superior to these other methods because it puts one in a better position to gain the relevant moral achievements.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2020. Published by Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Audi, Robert. 2004. The Good in the Right. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bedke, Matthew. 2008. “Ethical Intuitions: What They Are, What They Are Not, and How They Justify.” American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (3): 253–70.Google Scholar
Boyd, Kenneth. 2016. “Peirce on Assertion, Speech Acts, and Taking Responsibility.” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 52: 2146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandom, Robert. 1983. “Asserting.” Noûs 17 (4): 637–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making It Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Callahan, Laura. 2018. “Moral Testimony: A Re-Conceived Understanding Explanation.” The Philosophical Quarterly 68 (272): 437–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, Richmond, and Kumar, Victor. 2012. “Moral Reasoning on the Ground.” Ethics 122 (2): 273312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, Roger. 2014. “Moral Testimony Pessimism: A Defence.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary 88 (1): 129–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davia, Cory, and Palmira, Michele. 2015. “Moral Deference and Deference to an Epistemic Peer.” The Philosophical Quarterly 65 (261): 605–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dummett, Michael. 1981. Frege: Philosophy of Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, David. 2014. “A Defense of Moral Deference.” Journal of Philosophy 111 (5): 229–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fletcher, Guy. 2016. “Moral Testimony: One More Time with Feeling.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 11, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, 4573. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Jane. 2019. Inquiry and Belief. Noûs 53 (2): 296315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford. 2006. “Reductionism and the Distinctiveness of Testimonial Knowledge.” In The Epistemology of Testimony, edited by Lackey, Jennifer and Sosa, Ernest, 127–44. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford. 2015. Assertion: On the Philosophical Significance of Assertoric Speech. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Groll, Daniel, and Decker, Jason. 2014. “Moral Testimony: One of These Things Is Just Like the Others.” Analytic Philosophy 55 (1): 5474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, Alison. 2009. “Moral Testimony and Moral Epistemology.” Ethics 120 (1): 94127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, Alison. 2010. The Beloved Self. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, Alison. 2013. “Moral Testimony.” Philosophy Compass 8 (6): 552–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, Alison. 2016. “Understanding Why.” Noûs 50 (4): 661–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hopkins, Robert. 2007. “What Is Wrong with Moral Testimony?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (3): 611–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howarth, David. 1955. We Die Alone. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Howell, Robert. 2014. “Google Morals, Virtue, and the Asymmetry of Deference.” Noûs 48 (3): 389415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, Michael. 2005. Ethical Intuitionism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kelly, Thomas. 2005. “The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement.” In Oxford Studies in Epistemology Vol 1, edited by Gendler, Tamar Szabó and Hawthorne, John, 167–96. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2008. Learning from Words. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, Max. Forthcoming. “A Defense of the Very Idea of Moral Deference Pessimism.” Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
Lord, Errol. 2018. “How to Learn about Aesthetics and Morality through Acquaintance and Deference.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 13, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, 7197. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, John. 2011. “What Is Assertion?” In Assertion: New Philosophical Essays, edited by Brown, Jessica and Cappelen, Herman, 7996. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marsili, Neri. 2014. “Normative Accounts of Assertion: From Peirce to Williamson, and Back Again.” Special issue of Rivista Italiana di Filosofia del Linguaggio, edited by Leonardi, Paolo and Paolucci, Claudio, 112–30.Google Scholar
McGrath, Sarah. 2009. “The Puzzle of Pure Moral Deference.” Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1): 321–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, Sarah. 2011. “Skepticism about Moral Expertise as a Puzzle for Moral Realism.” Journal of Philosophy, 108 (3): 111–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinnon, Rachel. 2015. The Norms of Assertion: Truth, Lies, and Warrant. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMyler, Benjamin. 2011. Testimony, Trust, and Authority. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMyler, Benjamin. 2013. “The Epistemic Significance of Address.” Synthese 190 (6): 1059–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mogensen, Andreas. 2017. “Moral Testimony Pessimism and the Uncertain Value of Authenticity.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (3): 124.Google Scholar
Moran, Richard. 2005. “Getting Told and Being Believed.” Philosopher’s Imprint 5 (5): 129.Google Scholar
Nickel, Philip. 2001. “Moral Testimony and Its Authority.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4 (3): 253–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rescorla, Michael. 2009. “Assertion and Its Constitutive Norms.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (1): 98130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defence. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, Lionel. 2019. “Commitment Accounts of Assertion.” In The Oxford Handbook of Assertion, edited by Goldberg, Sanford. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sliwa, Paulina. 2012. “In Defense of Moral Testimony.” Philosophical Studies 158 (2): 175–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sliwa, Paulina. 2017. “Moral Understanding as Knowing Right from Wrong.” Ethics 127 (April): 521–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stratton-Lake, Philip. 2016. “Intuition, Self-Evidence, and Understanding.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 11, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, 2844. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, Gary. 2004. “Asserting and Promising.” Philosophical Studies 117 (1/2): 5777.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woollard, Fiona. 2013. “If This Is My Body … : A Defence of the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94: 315–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar