Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T19:51:08.196Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Neoliberalism versus distributional autonomy: the skipped step in rawls’s the law of peoples

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

William A. Edmundson
Affiliation:
Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA, USA
Matthew R. Schrepfer
Affiliation:
Brown University, Providence, RI, USA

Abstract

Debates about global distributive justice focus on the gulf between the wealthy North and the impoverished South, rather than on issues arising between liberal democracies. A review of John Rawls’s approach to international justice discloses a step Rawls skipped in his extension of his original-position procedure. The skipped step is where a need for the distributional autonomy of sovereign liberal states reveals itself. Neoliberalism denies the possibility and the desirability of distributional autonomy. A complete Rawlsian account of global justice shows the necessity and possibility of a charter between liberal states, assuring each a proper minimum degree of distributional autonomy

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Andrews, D. M., 1994. “Capital Mobility and State Autonomy: Toward a Structural Theory of International Monetary Relations.” International Studies Quarterly, 38 (2): 193218. doi:10.2307/2600975.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A., 2000. “Rawls’s Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World.” Ethics, 110 (4): 697721. doi:10.1086/233370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A., 2004. Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Christiano, T., 2006. “Political Equality and the Independent Power of Private Property.” In Problems for Democracy, edited by Kultgen, J. and Lenzi, M., 119138. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
Farrell, H. F., and Newman, A.. 2015. “Structuring Power: Business and Authority beyond the Nation-State.” Business and Politics, 17 (3): 527552. doi:10.1515/bap-2015-0007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, K., 1982. Attlee. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.Google Scholar
Heath, J., 2005. “Rawls on Global Distributive Justice: A Defence.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 35 (1): 193226. doi:10.1080/00455091.2005.10716854.Google Scholar
Holland, S., and Tostevin, M.. 2017 November 10. “Trump Brings Tough Trade Message in Vision for Asia.” Reuters, Accessed. https://www.reuters.com/article/us-trump-asia-vietnam/trump-bringstough-trade-message-in-vision-for-asia-idUSKBN1DA0KR?il=0Google Scholar
Pogge, T., 1994. “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23 (3): 195224. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.1994.tb00011.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polanyi, K., 2018. Economy and Society: Selected Writings. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J., 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J., and Phillipe, V. P.. 2003. “Three Letters on the Law of Peoples and the European Union.” Revue de Philosophie Économique, 8: 720.Google Scholar
Rodrik, D., 2012. The Globalization Paradox: Democracy and the Future of the World Economy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sengupta, K., 2017 May 2. “Russia’s Grip on Europe’s Oil Supply Threatens Ukraine’s Energy Independence.” Independent, Accessed. http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/europe/russia-ukraine-gasenergy-supply-solution-putin-holds-key-a7714141.html.Google Scholar
Slobodian, Q., 2018. The Globalists: The End of Empire and the Birth of Neoliberalism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stiglitz, J. E., 2003. Globalization and Its Discontents. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar