Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T18:31:39.571Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Misinformation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Peter Godfrey-Smith*
Affiliation:
University of California-San Diego, La Jolla, CA92093, U.S.A.

Extract

It is well known that informational theories of representation have trouble accounting for error. Informational semantics is a family of theories attempting a naturalistic, unashamedly reductive explanation of the semantic and intentional properties of thought and language. Most simply, the informational approach explains truth-conditional content in terms of causal, nomic, or simply regular correlation between a representation and a state of affairs. The central work is Dretske (1981), and the theory was largely developed at the University of Wisconsin by Fred Dretske, Dennis Stampe, and Berent Enc. Recently, informational semantics has roamed far beyond its Wisconsin home, and built a sizeable collection of followers. Converts include Jerry Fodor (1987), Robert Stalnaker (1984) and, less faithfully, Paul and Patricia Churchland (1983) and Hartry Field (1986). But for some years informational semantics has been hounded by a problem with error – the classic presentation is Fodor (1984) – and no other problem has hounded the theory so persistently.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Editor’s Note: Readers will be interested to know that this paper is a greatly compressed version of another paper, ‘The Problem of Error in Informational Theories of Representation,’ that won the Rutgers International Prize in Philosophy in 1987. The Rutgers Prize is for an undergraduate essay in philosophy, and is organized by Rutgers University.

References

Armstrong, D. Belief, Truth, and Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1973)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigelow, J. and Pargetter, R.Functions,’ Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987), 181-96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N.Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’ in French, P. et al., eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Studies in the Philosophy of Mind (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1986)Google Scholar
Brownell, P.Prey Detection by the Sand Scorpion,’ Scientific American 251, 6 (1984), 94-105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P.S. and Churchland, P.A.Stalking the Wild Epistemic Engine,’ Nous 17, 1 (1983), 5-18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D.Evolution, Error, and Intentionality,’ in The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books 1987)Google Scholar
Dretske, F. Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Blackwell 1981)Google Scholar
Dretske, F.Misrepresentation,’ in Bogdan, R. ed., Belief: Form, Content and Function (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1986)Google Scholar
Enc, B.Intentional States of Mechanical Devices,’ Mind 91 (1982), 161-82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H.Stalnaker on Intentionality ,’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 67 (1986),98-112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A.Semantics, Wisconsin Style, ’ Synthese 59 (1984), 231-50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A. ‘ Psychosemantics,’ unpublished manuscriptGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A. Psychosemantics (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books 1987)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garcia, J. McGowan, B. and Green, K.Biological Constraints on Conditioning,’ in Black, A. and Prokasy, W. eds., Classical Conditioning Vol. II, Current Research and Theory (New York: Appleton-Century Crofts 1972)Google Scholar
Ginet, C.Four Difficulties With Dretske’s Theory of Knowledge,’ Behavioural and Brain Sciences 6 (1983), 69-70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge,’ Journal of Philosophy 73, 20 (1976), 771-91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. and Lewontin, R. ‘The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: a Critique of the Adaptationist Program,’ 1978; reprinted in Sober (1984)Google Scholar
Kripke, S. Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1972)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, D.Mental Representation from the Bottom Up,’ Synthese 70 (1987), 23-78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mattews, R.Troubles with Representationalism,’ Social Research 51, 4 (1984 ), 1065-97Google Scholar
Millikan, R. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories ( Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books 1984)Google Scholar
Millikan, R.Thought Without Laws; Cognitive Science with Content,’ Philosophical Review 95, 1 (1986), 47-80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. ‘ Biosemantics,’ forthcomingGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S.Stalnaker’s Problem of Intentionality,’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 67 ( 1986), 87-97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. ed. Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology: An Anthology (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books 1984)Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. Inquiry (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books 1984)Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R.Replies to Schiffer and Field,’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 67 (1986 ), 113-23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stampe, D.Towards a Causal Theory of Linguistic Representation,’ in French, P. et al., eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy II: Studies in the Philosophy of Language (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1977)Google Scholar
Stampe, D.Verificationism and a Causal Account of Meaning,’ Synthese 69 (1986), 107-37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. Review of Dretske’s Knowledge and the Flow of Information, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61, 2 (1983), 211-17Google Scholar
Stich, S.Could Man be an Irrational Animal? Some Notes on the Epistemology of Rationality, ’ Synthese 64 ( 1985), 115-35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. The Fragmentation of Reason, forthcomingGoogle Scholar
Taylor, K.Belief, Information, and Semantic Content: A Naturalist’s Lament,’ Synthese 71 (1987), 97-124CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, L. ‘Functions, ’ 1973; reprinted in Sober (1984)Google Scholar