Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T17:49:22.511Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Meaning Holism and De Re Ascription

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Daniel Whiting*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, School of Humanities, University of Southampton, Southampton, SO17 1BJ, UK

Extract

According to inferential role semantics (IRS), for an expression to have a particular meaning or express a certain concept is for subjects to be disposed to make, or to treat as proper, certain inferential transitions involving that expression. Such a theory of meaning is holistic, since according to it the meaning or concept any given expression possesses or expresses depends on the inferential relations it stands in to other expressions.

It is widely recognised that this holism leads to two prima facie problems for IRS. First, since no two speakers share the same beliefs, they will inevitably be disposed to make, or treat as correct, different inferential transitions involving an expression. Hence, according to IRS, the same word in different mouths will possess a different meaning and be understood in different ways. It seems to follow that communication is impossible.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beaney, M. ed. 1997. The Frege Reader. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Block, N. 1995. ‘An Argument for Holism.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95: 151 -69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. 1993. ‘Does an Inferential Role Semantics Rest Upon a Mistake?Mind and Language 8: 2740.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. 1994. ‘Inferential Role Semantics and the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction.Philosophical Studies 73: 109–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. 1997. ‘Analyticity.’ In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Hale, B. and Wright, C. eds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P. 2003. ‘Epistemic Analyticity: A Defence.Grazer Philosophische Studien 66: 1535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandom, R. 1994. Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. 2000a. Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. 2000b. ‘Facts, Norms, and Normative Facts: Reply to Habermas.European Journal of Philosophy 8: 356–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. and Lepore, E. 1991. ‘Why Meaning (Probably) isn't Conceptual Role.Mind and Language 6: 329–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. and Lepore, E.. 1992. Holism. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. and Lepore, E.. 2001. ‘Brandom's Burdens: Compositionality and Inferentialism.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68: 465–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frege, G. 1892. ‘On Sinn and Bedeutung.’ Reprinted in Beaney, 1997.Google Scholar
H-J., Glock 2003. Quine and Davidson on Thought, Language, and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grice, P. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Grice, P. and Strawson, P. 1956. ‘In Defense of Dogma.’ Reprinted in Grice, 1989.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1993. ‘Meaning Holism Defended.Grazer Philosophische Studien 46: 163–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, A. 2003. ‘Making it Implicit: Brandom on Rule Following.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66: 419–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. 1992. ‘Quine versus Chomsky on the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 92: 95108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. 1998. Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. 2005. Reflections on Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laurier, D. 2005. ‘Pragmatics, Pittsburgh Style.Pragmatics and Cognition 13: 141–60.Google Scholar
Lepore, E. 1994. ‘Conceptual Role Semantics.’ In A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, Guttenplan, S. ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. 2000. Philosophy of Language. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McCullagh, M. 2005. ‘Motivating Inferentialism.Southwest Philosophy Review 21: 7784.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. 2005. ‘Motivating Inferentialism.Pragmatics and Cognition 13: 121140.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1992. A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1997. ‘Holism.’ In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Hale, B. and Wright, C. eds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1991. Representation and Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. 1951. ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism.’ Reprinted in Quine 1980.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. 1980. From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. 2006a. ‘Conceptual Role Semantics.’ In The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, J. Fieser and B. Dowden, eds. http://www.iep.utm.edu/Google Scholar
Whiting, D. 2006b. ‘Between Primitivism and Naturalism: Brandom's Theory of MeaningActa Analytica 21: 322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, D. 2007. ‘Fregean Sense and Anti-Individualism.Philosophical Books 48: 233–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar