Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T01:03:53.711Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Representationalism, perceptual distortion and the limits of phenomenal concepts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

David Bourget*
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario, London, ON, Canada

Abstract

This paper replies to objections from perceptual distortion (blur, perspective, double vision, etc.) against the representationalist thesis that the phenomenal characters of experiences supervene on their intentional contents. It has been argued that some pairs of distorted and undistorted experiences share contents without sharing phenomenal characters, which is incompatible with the supervenience thesis. In reply, I suggest that such cases are not counterexamples to the representationalist thesis because the contents of distorted experiences are always impoverished in some way compared to those of normal experiences. This can be shown by considering limit cases of perceptual distortion, for example, maximally blurry experiences, which manifestly lack details present in clear experiences. I argue that since there is no reasonable way to draw the line between distorted experiences that have degraded content and distorted experiences that do not, we should allow that an increase in distortion is always accompanied by a degradation in content. I also discuss the prospects for a positive account of the contents specific to distorted experiences. I argue that the prospects for such an account are dim, but that this is due to limitations of our phenomenal concepts, not to the falsity of the representationalist thesis.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allen, K. 2013. “Blur”;. Philosophical Studies 162(2): 257273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. A., and Velleman., J. D. 1989. “Color as a Secondary Quality”;. Mind 98: 81103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourget, D. 2010a. “Consciousness Is Underived Intentionality”;. Noûs 44(1): 3258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourget, D. 2010b. “The Representational Theory of Consciousness”;. PhD thesis, Australian National University.Google Scholar
Bourget, D., and Mendelovici., A. 2014. “Tracking Representationalism”;. In Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers, edited by Bailey, Andrew 209235. London:Continuum.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. 2002. “Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?”; In Conceivability and Possibility, edited by Gendler, T. S. and Hawthorne, J. 145200. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. 2004. “The Representational Character of Experience”;. In The Future for Philosophy, edited by Leiter, B. 153181. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 2003. “Experience as Representation”;. Philosophical Issues 13(1): 6782.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 1990. “The Intrinsic Quality of Experience”;. Philosophical Perspectives 4: 3152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 1977.Perception: A Representative Theory. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jagnow, R. 2009. “How Representationalism Can Account for the Phenomenal Significance of Illumination”;. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(4): 551572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, U. 2011.The Sources of Intentionality. Oxford:Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuczynski, J. -M. M. 2004. “Some Arguments Against Intentionalism”;. Acta Analytica 19(32): 107141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. G. 1996.Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA:MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. 2000. “Representational Theories of Consciousness”;. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, Edward N. 6669. Stanford:Metaphysics Research Lab.Google Scholar
Mendelovici, A. 2010. “Mental Representation and Closely Conflated Topics”;. PhD thesis, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Mendelovici, A. 2013. “Reliable Misrepresentation and Tracking Theories of Mental Representation”;. Philosophical Studies 165(2): 421443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendelovici, A. 2014. “Pure Intentionalism About Moods and Emotions”;. In Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind, edited by Kriegel, Uriah 135157. London:Routledge.Google Scholar
Millar, B. 2010. “Peacocke’s Trees”;. Synthese 174(3): 445461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millar, B. 2013. “Colour Constancy and Fregean Representationalism”;. Philosophical Studies 164(1): 219231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pace, M. 2007. “Blurred Vision and the Transparency of Experience”;. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88(3): 328354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1983.Sense and Content: Experience, Thought, and Their Relations. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, S. 2008. “The Situation-Dependency of Perception”;. Journal of Philosophy 105(2): 5584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroer, R. 2002. “Seeing It All Clearly: The Real Story on Blurry Vision”;. American Philosophical Quarterly 39(3): 297301.Google Scholar
Seager, W. E., and Bourget., D. 2007. “Representationalism About Consciousness”;. In The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, edited by Velmans, M. and Schneider, S. 589604. Malden, MA:Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smith, A. D. 2008. “Translucent Experiences”;. Philosophical Studies 140(2): 197212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, B. J. 2006. “Color Constancy and Russellian Representationalism”;. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84(1): 7594.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 1996. “Perceptual Experience Is a Many-Layered Thing”;. Philosophical Issues 7: 117126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2003. “Blurry Images, Double Vision, and Other Oddities: New Problems for Representationalism?”; In Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Smith, Quentin and Jokic, Aleksandar 220272. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Google Scholar