Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T19:04:04.790Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reasons for emotion and moral motivation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Reid Blackman*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Colgate University, Hamilton, NY, USA
*
Reid Blackman [email protected]

Abstract

Internalism about normative reasons is the view that an agent’s normative reasons depend on her motivational constitution. On the assumption that there are reasons for emotion I argue that (a) externalism about reasons for emotion entails that all rational agents have reasons to be morally motivated and (b) internalism about reasons for emotion is implausible. If the arguments are sound we can conclude that all rational agents have reasons to be morally motivated. Resisting this conclusion requires either justifying internalism about reasons for emotion in a way hitherto unarticulated or giving up on reasons for emotion altogether.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Brandt, R. 1979. A Theory of the Good and the Right. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 2010. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199581405.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D’Arms, Justin, and Jacobson, Daniel. 2000. “The Moralistic Fallacy: On the ‘Appropriateness’ of Emotion.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61: 6590. 10.2307/2653403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D’Arms, Justin, and Daniel, Jacobson. 2006. “Anthropocentric Constraints on Human Value.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics. vol. 1, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, 99126. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, Jonathan. 1993. Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dancy, Jonathan. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, Jonathan. 2014, July. “Intuition and Emotion.” Ethics 124: 787812. 10.1086/675879CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., and Smylie, John. 1983. “Reason, Judgment, and the Desire to be Rational.” Journal of Philosophy 80 (9999): 652653.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deigh, John. 1994. “Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions.” Ethics 104 (4): 824854. 10.1086/293657CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. 2006. “Agency, Shmagency: Why Normativity Won’t Come from What is Constitutive of Agency.” Philosophical Review 115: 169198. 10.1215/00318108-115-2-169CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011. “Shmagency Revisited.” In New Waves in Metaethics, edited by Brady, Michael, 208233. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, Stephen, and Schroeder, Mark. 2017. “Reasons for Action: Internal vs. External.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), edited by Zalta, Edward N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/reasons-external/Google Scholar
Finlay, S. 2009. “The Obscurity of Internal Reasons.” Philosophers’ Imprint 9 (7): 122.Google Scholar
Garner, R. T. 1990. “On the Genuine Queerness of Moral Properties and Facts.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (2): 137146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gert, Johsua. 2016. “The Distinction between Justifying and Requiring: Nothing to Fear.” In Weighing Reasons, edited by Maguire, Barry and Lord, Errol, 157172. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199315192.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, R. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 1986. “Skepticism about Practical Reason.” The Journal of Philosophy 83 (1): 5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Maguire, Barry. 2017. “There Are No Reasons for Affective Attitudes.” Mind.Google Scholar
Manne, Kate. 2014. “Internalism about Reasons: Sad but True?Philosophical Studies 167 (1): 89117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markovits, Julia. 2011a. “Internal Reasons and the Motivating Intuition.” In New Waves in Metaethics, edited by Brady, Michael, 141165. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. 10.1057/9780230294899CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markovits, Julia. 2011b. “Why Be an Internalist about Reasons? ” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics. vol. 6, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, 255279. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199606375.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mason, Michell. 2003, January. “Contempt as a Moral Attitude.” Ethics 113: 234272. 10.1086/342860CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. 1995. “Might There Be External Reasons.” Reprinted in Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1970. The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Railton, Peter. 1986. “Facts and Values.” Philosophical Topics 14 (2): 531. 10.5840/philtopics19861421CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter. 1997. “On the Hypothetical and Non-Hypothetical in Reasoning about Belief and about Action.” In Ethics and Practical Reason, edited by Cullity and Gaut, 5379. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Salmela, Mikko. 2006. “True Emotions.” The Philosophical Quarterly 56 (224): 382405. 10.1111/phiq.2006.56.issue-224CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2007. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199299508.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, Nishi, and Velleman, J. David. 2005. “Doxastic Deliberation.” Philosophical Review 114 (4): 497534. 10.1215/00318108-114-4-497CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skorupski, John. 2010a. “Sentimentalism: Its Scope and Limits.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (2): 125136. 10.1007/s10677-009-9210-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skorupski, John. 2010b. The Domain of Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199587636.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, David. 2001. “Explanation, Internalism, and Reasons for Action.” Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2): 218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Michael. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. 2009. How We Get along. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511808296CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David 1996. “The Possibility of Practical Reason.” Ethics 106 (4): 694726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogelstein, Eric. 2011. “Morality, Reasons, and Sentiments.” Philosophical Studies 155: 421432. 10.1007/s11098-010-9579-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogelstein, Eric. 2016. “A New Moral Sentimentalism.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 46 (3): 346368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1981a. “Internal and External Reasons.” Reprinted in Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981b. 10.1017/CBO9781139165860CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1989. “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame.” Reprinted in Making Sense of Humanity, and Other Philosophical Papers, 3545. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.Google Scholar