Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T22:40:59.436Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Rashness of Traditional Rationalism and Empiricism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Extract

I was brought up to believe that, in the “great debate” with the Rationalists, the Empiricists had largely won, particularly in view of Quine's holistic conception of justification, whereby even the claims of logic, though remote from experience, are indirectly tested by it. But some years ago I awoke to the possibility that there was something fishy in all this, and that the fallibilistic banalities that have played such a large role in driving the Quinean conception couldn't plausibly have such dramatic consequences. “Everything can be revised in the light of experience” is good advice for someone who hasn't noticed just how rich, complex and indirect our reasonings about any issue, including logic and mathematics, can be; but does it really tell against what Kant and the others had in mind when they believed that there were some claims whose justification needn't appeal to experience (which, it's crucial to remember, is how he and others thought of it, until the Positivists and Quine revised it to “unrevisability“)?

Type
Part B: Language and Mind
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bonjour, L. 1998. In Defense of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bonjour, L. 2001. Replies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3): 673-98.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.” In Midwest Studies in Philosophy IV, ed. French, P.Uehling, T. and Wettstein, H.Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1986. Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. New York: Praeger Publishers.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 2000. New Horizons in the Study of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 2003. “Reply to Rey.” In Chomsky and His Critics, ed. Antony, L. and Hornstein, N.105-39. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. New York: Little Brown.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 1996. Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 1997. “Replies.” In The Maribor Papers in Naturalized Semantics, ed. Jutronic, D.353411. Maribor: Pedagoska Fakulteta Maribor.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. forthcoming. Ignorance of Language.Google Scholar
Dwyer, S. and Pietroski, P. 1996. “Believing in Language.Philosophy of Science 63: 338-73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ewing, A. 1947. The Definition of Good. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1983. The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1987. Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1990. A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1998. Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 2004. “Having Concepts: A Brief Refutation of the 20th Century.Mind and Language 19: 2947.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettier, E. 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Analysis 23: 121-23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H.P. 1965. “The Causal Theory of Perception.” In Perceiving, Sensing and Knowing, ed. Swartz, R.J.New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Heim, H. 1989. The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases in English. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
Hornsby, J. 1997. Simple Mindedness: In Defense of Naive Naturalism in Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Katz, J. 1972. Semantic Theory. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Katz, J. 1981. Language and Other Abstract Objects. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Katz, J. 1998. A Realistic Rationalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Larson, R. and Segal, G. 1995. Knowledge of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, B. and Rey, G., eds. 1991. Meaning in Mind. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1991. The Problem of Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Myers, D. 2004. Intuition. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1992. A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1996. “Can Possession Conditions Individuate Concepts?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56: 433-60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1998. “Implicit Conceptions, Understanding and Rationality.” In Concepts, ed. Villanueva, E.4388. Atascadero: Ridgeview.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1962 I 75. “The Analytic and the Synthetic.” In Philosophical Papers Vol. II, 3369. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975. Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers. Vol. I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. 1953a. “On What There Is.” In From a Logical Point of View and Other Essays, 119. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Quine, W. 1953b. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”. In From a Logical Point of View and Other Essays, 2046. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Quine, W. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. 1970. Philosophy of Logic. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Quine, W. 1986. “Reply to Henryk Skolimowski.” In The Philosophy of WV Quine, ed. Hahn, L. and Schilpp, P.492-93. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Quine, W. and Ullian, J. 1970/78. The Web of Belief New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. 1993. Direct Reference. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rey, G. 1993. “The Unavailability of What We Mean: a Reply to Quine, Fodor and LePore.” In Grazer Philosophica (Special Edition), ed. J. Fodor and E. LePore, 61101.Google Scholar
Rey, G. 1994. “Dennett's Unrealistic Psychology.Philosophical Topics 22 (1-2): 259-89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, G. 1995. “Keeping Meaning More in Mind.Intellectica 2 (21) :65-80.Google Scholar
Rey, G. 1996. “Resisting Primitive Compulsions.” Contribution to symposium on C. Peacocke, A Study of Concepts. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LVI (2): 419-24. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. Margolis, E. and Laurence, S.Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Rey, G. 1997. Contemporary Philosophy of Mind: A Contentiously Classical Approach. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Rey, G. 1998. “What Implicit Conceptions Are Unlikely To Do.” Commentary on Chistopher Peacocke, “Implicit Conceptions, Understanding and Rationality.” Philosophical Issues 9: Concepts, ed. Villanueva, E.8992. Atascadero: Ridgeview Press.Google Scholar
Rey, G. 2001a. “Digging Deeper for the A Priori.” (Commentary on Laurence Bonjour, In Defense of Pure Reason.) Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 63: 649-56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, G. 2001b. “Physicalism and Psychology: A Plea for Substantive Philosophy of Mind.” In Physicalism and Its Discontents, ed. Gillet, Carl and Loewer, Barry99128. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, G. 2003. “Intentional Content and a Chomskian Linguistics.” In Epistemology of Language, ed. Barber, Alex140186. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rey, G. 2004. “The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction.” Stanford On-Line Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Rey, G. forthcoming-a. “The Intentional Inexistence of Language-But Not Cars.” In Debates in Cognitive Science, ed. Stainton, R.Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rey, G. forthcoming-b. Representing Nothing: Intentional Inexistents in Cognitive Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Ziff, P. 1959. “The Feelings of Robots.” Analysis 19: 6468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar