Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T20:47:09.607Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Knowing Your Own Beliefs

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Extract

How do you know your own beliefs? And how well do you know them? The two questions are related. I'll recommend a pluralist answer to the first question. The answer to the second question, I'll suggest, varies depending on features of the case.

Self-scanning. Shaun Nichols and Stephen Stich (2003) say this: You have in your mind a functionally defined “belief box.” To believe some propositionP is just to have a representation with the content “P” in the belief box. You also have a monitoring mechanism that can scan the contents of the belief box. Normally, you come to know what you believe by deploying that scanner, creating a new belief in the belief box, a belief with the content “I believe thatP.” Self-scanning accounts admit of many possible variations and complications (e.g., Armstrong 1968, 1981, 1999; Lycan 1996; Goldman 2006), but the basic idea is that people have one or more interior monitors or scanners that detect the presence of beliefs and produce, as output, beliefs about those beliefs (or judgments about those beliefs, or representations of those beliefs).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arendt, Hannah. 1963. Eichmann in jerusalem. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of Mind. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1981. The Nature of Mind and Other Essays. Ithaca, NY: Cornell.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1999. The Mind-Body Problem. Boulder, CO: Westview.Google Scholar
Bar-On, Dorit. 2004. Speaking My Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartlett, Frederic C. 1932. Remembering. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bem, Daryl J. 1967. “Self-Perception: An Alternative Interpretation of Cognitive Dissonance Phenomena.Psychological Review 74: 183200.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boyle, Matthew. 2011. “Transparent Self-Knowledge.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 85: 223–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braithwaite, R.B. 1932-33. “The Nature of Believing.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 33: 129-46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, Alex. 2005. “Introspection.Philosophical Topics 33, 1: 79104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, Peter. 2009. “How We Know Our Own Minds: The Relationship between Mindreading and Metacognition.Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32: 121–82.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carruthers, Peter. forthcoming. The Opacity of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Evans, Gareth. 1982. Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 2006. Simulating Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, Alison. 1993a. “How We Know Our Own Minds: The Illusion of First-Person Knowledge of Intentionality.Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16: 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, Alison. 1993b. “Psychopsychology.Consciousness and Cognition 2: 264–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gordon, Robert M. 2007. “Ascent Routines For Proposition:al Attitudes.Synthese 159: 151–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John. 1988. “Privileged Access.Mind 97: 238–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunter, David. 2011. “Alienated Belief.” Dialectica 65: 221-40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurlburt, Russell T., and Eric Schwitzgebel. 2011. “Presuppositions and Background Assumptions.Journal of Consciousness Studies 18 (1): 206–33.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1979. “A Puzzle about Belief.” In Meaning and Use, ed. Margalit, A., 239-83. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawlor, Krista. 2008. “Knowing Beliefs, Seeking Causes.American Imago 65: 335–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1980. “Mad Pain and Martian Pain.” In Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, vol. 1, ed. Block, N., 216-22. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Marcus, Ruth B. 1990. “Some Revisionary Proposals about Belief and Believing.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50: 132–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGeer, Victoria. 2007a. “The Moral Development of First-Person Authority.European Journal of Philosophy 16: 81108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGeer, Victoria. 2007b. “The Regulative Dimension of Folk Psychology.” In Folk Psychology Re-Assessed, eds. Hutto, D. and Ratcliffe, M., 137-56. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGeer, Victoria, and Pettit, Philip. 2002. “The Self-Regulating Mind.Language and Communication 22: 281–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Richard. 2001. Authority and Estrangement. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nichols, Shaun, and Stich, Stephen P.. 2003. Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, H.H. 1969. Belief London: George Allen.& Unwin.Google Scholar
Roediger, Henry L., III.1980. “Memory Metaphors in Cognitive Psychology.Memory and Cognition 8: 234–46.Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The Concept of Mind. New York: Barnes & Noble.Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 1999. “Gradual Belief Change in Children.Human Development 42: 283–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2001. “In-Between Believing.Philosophical Quarterly 51: 7682.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2002. “A Phenomenal, Dispositional Account of Belief.Nous 36: 249–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2006/2010. “Belief.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief.Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2010. “Acting Contrary to Our Professed Beliefs, or the Gulf between Occurrent Judgment and Dispositional Belief.Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91: 531–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. Forthcoming. “Mad Belief?” Neuro Ethics. ·Google Scholar
Shah, Nishi, and Velleman, David J.. 2005. “Doxastic Deliberation.Philosophical Review 114: 497534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney. 1996. The First-Person Perspective and Other Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney. 2009. “Self-Intimation and Second Order Belief.Erkenntnis 71: 3551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sutton, John. 1998. Philosophy and Memory Traces. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tye, Michael. 2000. Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vazire, Simine. 2010. “Who Knows What About a Person? The Self-Other Knowledge Asymmetry (SOKA) Model.Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 98: 281300.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed