Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T07:04:13.117Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Homological approximations in persistence theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 December 2022

Benjamin Blanchette
Affiliation:
Départment de Mathématiques, Université de Sherbrooke, Sherbrooke, QC J1K 2R1, Canada e-mail: [email protected]
Thomas Brüstle*
Affiliation:
Départment de Mathématiques, Université de Sherbrooke, Sherbrooke, QC J1K 2R1, Canada Department of Mathematics, Bishop’s University, Sherbrooke, QC J1M 1Z7, Canada e-mail: [email protected]
Eric J. Hanson
Affiliation:
LACIM, Université du Québec à Montréal, Montréal, QC H2L 2C4, Canada e-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We define a class of invariants, which we call homological invariants, for persistence modules over a finite poset. Informally, a homological invariant is one that respects some homological data and takes values in the free abelian group generated by a finite set of indecomposable modules. We focus in particular on groups generated by “spread modules,” which are sometimes called “interval modules” in the persistence theory literature. We show that both the dimension vector and rank invariant are equivalent to homological invariants taking values in groups generated by spread modules. We also show that the free abelian group generated by the “single-source” spread modules gives rise to a new invariant which is finer than the rank invariant.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Mathematical Society

1 Introduction

When taken at face value, a finite set of points in Euclidean space has no interesting topological features. There are many cases, however, where such a set of points can be seen as approximating something more interesting. For a simple example, we can imagine a set of points in $\mathbb {R}^2$ which are randomly sampled from the unit circle. In such a context, one may wish to speak of the “topology of the points” as the topology of this approximated space. The theory of persistent homology, which originated in the 1990s (see [Reference Barannikov and ArnoldBar94, Reference Delfinado and EdelsbrunnerDE93, Reference FrosiniFro90, Reference RobinsRob99], and 10 years later [Reference Edelsbrunner, Letscher and ZomorodianELZ02]), gives a formalization of this concept. The core idea is to construct a series of topological spaces (often simplicial complexes) which begins as a discrete set of points and ends as a contractible space. This series of topological spaces, often called a filtration, comes equipped with inclusion maps. The homological features which “persist” under several subsequent inclusions are considered to be those “of interest.”

The homology, often with field coefficients, of these topological spaces and the induced maps between them form what is called a persistence module. These objects can also be formulated abstractly. Motivated by works such as [Reference Botnan and Crawley-BoeveyBCB20, Reference Bubenik and ScottBS14, Reference Chambers, Letscher, Chambers, Fasy and ZiegelmeierCL18], let $\mathcal {P}$ be a poset and K a field. We consider $\mathcal {P}$ as a category, with a unique morphism $a \rightarrow b$ whenever $a \leq b \in \mathcal {P}$ . A persistence module over  $\mathcal {P}$ is then defined to be a functor M from $\mathcal {P}$ to the category of K-vector spaces. We adopt the standard convention of denoting by $M(a)$ the result of applying M to the object $a \in \mathcal {P}$ and by $M(a,b)$ the result of applying M to the unique morphism $a \rightarrow b$ in $\mathcal {P}$ . If $\dim M(a) < \infty $ for all $a \in \mathcal {P}$ , the persistence module M is said to be pointwise finite-dimensional (pfd). All of the persistence modules considered in this paper will be assumed to have this property unless otherwise stated.

Let us now restrict to the case where $|\mathcal {P}| < \infty $ . Then the incidence algebra of $\mathcal {P}$ is the finite-dimensional K-algebra $I(\mathcal {P}):= KQ/J$ , where Q is the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ and J is the two-sided ideal generated by all commutativity relations. Moreover, it is well known that the category $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ of finite-dimensional (right) $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules is isomorphic to that of pfd persistence modules over $\mathcal {P}$ . As such, we will freely move between these categories throughout this paper. We refer to [Reference Auslander, Reiten and SmaløARS95, Reference Assem, Simson and SkowrońskiASS06] for more details about finite-dimensional algebras and their module categories, to [Reference SimsonSim92] for more details about incidence algebras, and to [Reference StanleySta11, Chapter 4] for more details about general poset theory.

When $\mathcal {P}$ is totally ordered, the category $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ is very well behaved. Indeed, in this case, the category $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ contains finitely many indecomposable objects, indexed by pairs $a \leq b \in \mathcal {P}$ . These are the so-called “interval modules” (see Definition 2.4). Every persistence module can then be uniquely written as a direct sum of these indecomposables, yielding what is often referred to as the “barcode” of the persistence module. When viewed in this way, the parameters a and b describing the ends of a “bar” can be seen as the “birth” and “death” of some topological feature. For additional details on this topic, readers are referred to [Reference OudotOud15, Chapter 1], [Reference Crawley-BoeveyCB19], and [Reference Igusa, Rock and TodorovIRT22]. In Section 7.1, we will also explicitly describe how barcodes are related to the invariants introduced in this paper.

In both applications and theory, the natural next step is to ask what happens when the poset $\mathcal {P}$ is no longer totally ordered. This gives rise to the theory of “multiparameter persistence” [Reference Carlsson and ZomorodianCZ09], in which the poset $\mathcal {P}$ is often taken to be a closed interval in the lattice $\mathbb {Z}^n$ . Except in small cases, this amounts to studying algebras of “wild representation type,” i.e., algebras for which a complete description of all indecomposable modules is impossible. Since it is no longer computationally feasible to describe arbitrary persistence modules in terms of direct sums of indecomposables in this setting, one instead can turn to the study of invariants. The invariants we consider are maps $p:\mathsf {mod} I(\mathcal {P}) \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^n$ which are constant on isomorphism classes. We further assume that our invariants are additive, meaning that $p(M\oplus N) = p(M) + p(N)$ . See Definition 4.10 for precise definitions.

Perhaps the most natural invariant to consider is the dimension vector, also known as the Hilbert function. Given a persistence module M, the dimension vector is defined by

$$ \begin{align*}\underline{\mathrm{dim}} M = (\dim M(a))_{a \in \mathcal{P}}.\end{align*} $$

As discussed in Section 3, for each $a \in \mathcal {P}$ , there is an indecomposable projective $I(\mathcal {P})$ -module $P_a$ which satisfies

$$ \begin{align*}\dim \operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(P_a,M) = \dim M(a).\end{align*} $$

(One may also refer to $P_a$ as a “free persistence module.” See Section 2 for notes on our choice of terminology.) More generally, given any finite set $\mathcal {X}$ of indecomposable $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules, one obtains an invariant $(\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(R,M))_{R \in \mathcal {X}}$ . We will call invariants of this form dim-hom invariants. These are the types of invariants we consider in this paper.

In order to motivate the study of dim-hom invariants, we return to our discussion of classical invariants. While the dimension vector is easy to compute, it is agnostic to the maps comprising the persistence module. In persistence theory, however, we are often interested in how long topological features persist through a filtration. By construction, this is precisely the information stored in the maps comprising the module. One way to incorporate this information is to use the rank invariant, defined by

(1.1) $$ \begin{align}\underline{\mathrm{rk}} M = (\operatorname{\mathrm{rk}} M(a,b))_{a\leq b \in \mathcal{P}},\end{align} $$

where $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}} M(a,b)$ denotes the rank of the linear map $M(a,b)$ in the traditional sense. This invariant was first introduced in [Reference Carlsson and ZomorodianCZ09], where it was the first invariant tailored for multiparameter persistence homology. We note the rank invariant is strictly finer than the dimension vector, since for all $a \in \mathcal {P}$ one has $\dim M(a) = \operatorname {\mathrm {rk}} M(a,a)$ . (It is straightforward to construct modules with the same dimension vector but different rank invariants.)

When $\mathcal {P}$ is totally ordered, the rank invariant is equivalent to the barcode (see [Reference Carlsson and ZomorodianCZ09, Theorem 12]). This in particular means that the rank invariant is complete in this case; i.e., the isomorphism class of a persistence module can be recovered from its barcode. For more general posets, however, there exist nonisomorphic persistence modules with the same rank invariant. See, e.g., Example 7.6.

In the recent preprint [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO], the rank invariant is shown to be a dim-hom invariant. While an interesting result on its own, the authors further give a new interpretation of the rank invariant using relative homological algebra. More precisely, let M be a module. The authors show that $\underline {\mathrm {rk}} M$ is equivalent to the representative $[M]_{\mathcal {X}}$ of M in the relative Grothendieck group of $\mathsf {mod} I(\mathcal {P})$ with respect to some exact structure. See Section 4 for background and definitions pertaining to relative Grothendieck groups and Theorem 7.2 for the precise statement proven in [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO]. In particular, the representative $[M]_{\mathcal {X}}$ can be interpreted as a “signed approximation” of M by the “relative projective” objects in the exact structure. In this paper, we take the reverse approach: we first develop a theoretical framework using homological algebra, and then we build new invariants using it. We refer to those invariants which fit into this framework as homological invariants.

We show that the dimension vector, the rank invariant, and, when the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ is Dynkin type A, the barcode are all examples of homological invariants. We also concretely describe a new homological invariant for persistence modules over an arbitrary finite poset. Unless the poset satisfies a very restrictive condition, slightly more general than being totally ordered, this new invariant is strictly finer than the rank invariant. Finally, we compare the approximations coming from our homological invariants to other notions of approximation from the persistence theory literature. See Section 3 for additional details and motivation.

1.1 Organization and main results

The contents of this paper are as follows.

In Section 2, we fix notation and terminology for use in the later sections. As we are mainly drawing intuition from the representation theory of finite-dimensional algebras, this terminology sometimes diverges from that in the persistence theory literature. In particular, we define spread modules (Definition 2.4), which are typically referred to as “interval modules” in the persistence theory literature.

In Section 3, we provide motivation for our study of homological invariants. We first discuss the many ways one can interpret the dimension vector of a persistence module, with an emphasis on those interpretations which are rooted in homological algebra. We then discuss how similar interpretations are used to understand more complicated invariants. We focus in particular on the recent works [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb, Reference Bubenik and ScottBOO, Reference Kim and MémoliKM21].

In Section 4, we give a brief overview of relative homological algebra following Auslander and Solberg [Reference Auslander and SolbergAS93]. We work in this section with an arbitrary finite-dimensional algebra $\Lambda $ and a finite set $\mathcal {X}$ of indecomposable modules. In Section 4.1, we define the notions of approximations and resolutions by $\mathcal {X}$ , and use these to define the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ (Definition 4.4). We then define an “exact structure” $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ on $\mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , which in particular contains all short exact sequences ending with an approximation by $\mathcal {X}$ . Using these short exact sequences, we define the relative Grothendieck group $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ (Definition 4.7). In Section 4.2, we define the dim-hom invariants and homological invariants relative to $\mathcal {X}$ (Definition 4.12), which are the main objects of study in this paper. Finally, in Section 4.3, we use the theory of projectivization to give a sufficient condition for when the relative Grothendieck group $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ is free abelian (Proposition 4.19). As a consequence, we obtain the following result.

Theorem 1.1 (Theorem 4.22)

Let $\Lambda $ be a finite-dimensional algebra, and let $\mathcal {X}$ be a finite set of indecomposable $\Lambda $ -modules which contains the indecomposable projectives. If the algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_\Lambda (\bigoplus _{R \in \mathcal {X}} R)^{\mathrm{op}}$ has finite global dimension, then the dim-hom invariant relative to $\mathcal {X}$ and the homological invariant relative to $\mathcal {X}$ are equivalent.

In Section 5, we study spread modules in more detail. The main result of this section is a concrete description of the Hom-space between spread modules (Proposition 5.5).

In Section 6, we specialize the results of Section 4 to the case of persistence (and more specifically spread) modules. In particular, we prove our first main theorem.

Theorem 1.2 (Theorem 6.2)

Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a finite poset, and let $\mathcal {X}$ be a set of connected spread modules over $I(\mathcal {P})$ which contains the indecomposable projectives.

  1. (1) If every spread in $\mathcal {X}$ has a unique source, then the association $M \mapsto [M]_{\mathcal {X}}$ is a homological invariant.

  2. (2) If every spread in $\mathcal {X}$ is supported on an upset of $\mathcal {P}$ , then the association $M \mapsto [M]_{\mathcal {X}}$ is a homological invariant.

If $\mathcal {X}$ is the set of all spread modules which contain a unique source, then we call the association $[M] \mapsto [M]_{\mathcal {X}}$ the single-source homological spread invariant. Furthermore, we note that a special case of Theorem 1.2(2) can also be deduced from [Reference MillerMil, Theorem 6.12]. See Remark 6.3.

We then show that allowing $\mathcal {X}$ to contain spread modules with multiple sources sometimes leads to invariants which are not homological (Example 6.4). It remains an open question whether taking $\mathcal {X}$ to be the set of all connected spread modules yields a homological invariant, even in the case where $\mathcal {P}$ is a two-dimensional grid. Finally, in Section 6.2, we discuss the existence of algorithms for computing our homological invariants and which aspects of the theory can be extended to infinite posets.

In Section 7, we compare our new homological invariants to other invariants used in persistence theory. We first show that, if the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ is Dynkin type A, then the barcode is a homological invariant (Proposition 7.1). Likewise, we use Theorem 1.2, together with results from [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO], to show that the rank invariant (Theorem 7.2) is a homological invariant. We then prove our second main theorem.

Theorem 1.3 (Theorem 7.4)

Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a finite poset. Then the single-source homological spread invariant is finer than the rank invariant on $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ . Moreover, these invariants are equivalent if and only if for all $a \in \mathcal {P}$ the subposet $\{x \in \mathcal {P} \mid a \leq x\}$ is totally ordered.

We also explicitly explain why the signed barcode of [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO] and the homological invariant relative to the set of interval modules do not coincide, even though both take values in the same Grothendieck group. See Remark 7.7. Finally, we show that the generalized persistence diagram of [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21], which yields signed approximations of arbitrary persistence modules by spread modules, is not homological with respect to the set of spread modules. We conjecture that more generally it is also not homological relative to any set of indecomposables. See Corollary 7.10 and Conjecture 7.11.

2 Notation and terminology

In this section, we fix notation and terminology for use in the remainder of this paper. We first recall some notation from the introduction. Fix a field K. The notation $\dim (-)$ will always mean $\dim _K(-)$ . We denote by $\mathcal {P}$ a poset, which we will assume to be finite unless otherwise stated. We denote by $I(\mathcal {P})$ the (K-)incidence algebra of $\mathcal {P}$ and by $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ the category of finitely generated (right) $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules. Unless otherwise stated, the phrase “an $I(\mathcal {P})$ -module” will always refer to an object of $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ . Given M and N two $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules, a “morphism” $f:M \rightarrow N$ refers to an $I(\mathcal {P})$ -linear map. We denote by $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(M,N)$ , or just $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M,N)$ , the vector space of morphisms from M to N. In Section 4, we will work over an arbitrary finite-dimensional algebra, and thus the symbol $I(\mathcal {P})$ will be replaced with $\Lambda $ while maintaining our conventions.

We identify $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ with the category of pfd persistence modules over $\mathcal {P}$ . That is, we consider a module $M \in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ as a functor from $\mathcal {P}$ to the category of finite-dimensional K-vector spaces. Given $a \leq b \in \mathcal {P}$ , we denote by $M(a)$ and $M(a,b)$ the result of applying M to the object a and to the unique morphism $a\rightarrow b$ in $\mathcal {P}$ , respectively.

We adopt the common practice of identifying modules with their isomorphism classes. In particular, the term “subcategory” will always refer to a subcategory which is full and closed under isomorphism. Moreover, any use of the phrase “the set of—modules” could more precisely be replaced with “the set of isomorphism classes of—modules.”

Given a set $\mathcal {X}$ of $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules, we denote by $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ the subcategory of $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ whose objects are (isomorphic to) finite direct sums of the objects in $\mathcal {X}$ . That is, a module M is in $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ if and only if there is a finite subset $\mathcal {Y} \subseteq \mathcal {X}$ and a tuple of natural numbers $(n_R)_{R \in \mathcal {Y}}$ such that $M \simeq \bigoplus _{R \in \mathcal {Y}} R^{(n_R)}$ . Note that by taking $\mathcal {Y} = \emptyset $ , we have that $0 \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ . As an example, if $\mathcal {X}$ is the set of indecomposable projective $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules, then $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ is the subcategory consisting of all projective $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules.

2.1 Spread modules

In this section, we define a subclass of $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules which we refer to as spread modules. As we explain in Remark 2.5, these are often referred to as “interval modules” in the persistence theory literature. We will study this class of modules in more details in Section 5.

Let $a\in \mathcal {P}$ , and let $B\subseteq \mathcal {P}$ be a set of incomparable elements. We say $a\leq B$ (resp. $a\geq B$ ) if there exists $b\in B$ such that $a\leq b$ ( resp. $a\geq b$ ). Sets of incomparable elements of $\mathcal {P}$ can then be partially ordered by the relation

$$ \begin{align*}A\leq B \iff \forall_{a \in A}\forall_{b \in B} \ a\leq B \text{ and } A\leq b.\end{align*} $$

Let Q be the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ . We call $[a,c]:=\{b \mid a\leq b\leq c\}$ the interval from a to c. A subset S of $\mathcal {P}$ is called connected if it is a connected part of Q; that is, there exists a non-oriented path between any two points of S. A subset S of $\mathcal {P}$ is called convex if for any pair $(a,b)\in S$ , $[a,b]\subseteq S$ .

Clearly, intervals are connected and convex. We generalize the notion of interval with the following definition.

Definition 2.1 Let $A, B \subseteq \mathcal {P}$ be two sets of incomparable elements with $A \leq B$ . The spread from A to B is the subset

$$ \begin{align*}[A, B] := \{ x\; | \text{ there exists } a\in A, b\in B \text{ such that } a\leq x \leq b\}.\end{align*} $$

We refer to A and B as the sets of sources and targets of $[A,B]$ , respectively.

If $A = \{a\}$ contains only a single element, we call $[A,B]$ a single-source spread and write $[a,B]$ in place of $[\{a\},B]$ . Single-target spreads are defined and notated analogously. Note that spreads that are both single-source and single-target are precisely intervals (as in the classical poset-theory literature; see, e.g., [Reference StanleySta11]). Spreads are also convex. Indeed, if $x,z\in [A,B]$ , then there exist a and b such that $a\leq x$ and $z\leq b$ , so for any $y\in [x,z]$ , we have $a\leq x\leq y\leq z \leq b$ , showing that it is convex. In fact, all finite convex subsets are spreads, as made precise in the following proposition.

Proposition 2.2 Let X be a convex subset of $\mathcal {P}$ . Let A be the set of minimal elements of X, and let B be the set of maximal elements of X. Then $X= [A,B]$ .

Proof It is clear that A and B are sets of incomparable elements and that $A \leq B$ . Now, take $y\in X$ to be neither maximal nor minimal. Then there exist elements in X that are, respectively, bigger and smaller than y, say $x_1\leq y \leq z_1$ . We then iteratively find bigger and smaller elements, obtaining a sequence

$$ \begin{align*}x_n\leq \cdots \leq x_1 \leq y \leq z_1 \leq \cdots \leq z_m,\end{align*} $$

where $x_n$ is minimal and $z_m$ is maximal. This sequence must end in a finite number of steps because $\mathcal {P}$ , and thus also X, is finite.

We also fix the following notation for convenience.

Definition 2.3 Let $X\subseteq \mathcal {P}$ be a set of incomparable elements. By Proposition 2.2, the sets

$$ \begin{align*}[-\infty,X]:=\{y \mid y \leq X\} \qquad [X,\infty]:=\{y \mid X \leq y\}\end{align*} $$

are spreads. We call them downsets and upsets, respectively. Note that downsets are sometimes called “order ideals,” and are characterized by being closed under taking predecessors. Likewise upsets are sometimes called “order filters,” and are characterized by being closed under taking successors.

Definition 2.4 Given a spread $[A,B]\subseteq \mathcal {P}$ , we call spread module the persistence module $M_{[A,B]}$ defined by

$$\begin{align*}M_{[A,B]}(p)= \begin{cases} K, & \text{ if } p\in [A,B],\\ 0, & \text{ if } p\not\in [A,B], \end{cases} \quad \quad \quad \quad M_{[A,B]}(p,q)= \begin{cases} 1_K, & \text{ if } p,q \in [A,B],\\ 0, & \text{ else.} \end{cases} \end{align*}$$

If in addition $|A| = 1 = |B|$ , we call $M_{[A,B]}$ an interval module. We likewise define single-source spread modules, single-target spread modules, upset modules, and downset modules in the natural way.

Remark 2.5 In much of the recent literature on persistence modules (e.g., [Reference Asashiba, Buchet, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiABE+22, Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb, Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO] and several others), the term “interval module” is used for what we have called a “spread module” and the term “segment module” is used for what is called an “interval module.” Our naming convention was chosen to emphasize that spreads are not intervals in the classical poset-theory sense.

The following are some important examples of spread modules.

Example 2.6

  1. (1) All simple modules are interval modules. Indeed, let $a \in \mathcal {P}$ . Then $S_a := M_{[a,a]}$ is the simple module supported at a.

  2. (2) All indecomposable projective modules are upset modules. Indeed, for $a \in \mathcal {P}$ , we have that $P_a:=M_{[a,\infty ]}$ is the projective cover of $S_a$ . Symmetrically, indecomposable injective modules are downset modules: $I_a:= M_{[-\infty ,a]}$ is the injective envelope of $S_a$ .

  3. (3) If the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ is Dynkin type A, then all indecomposable modules are spread modules. If moreover $\mathcal {P}$ is totally ordered, then all indecomposable modules are interval modules.

Remark 2.7 The modules $P_a$ in Example 2.6(2) are sometimes referred to as “free persistence modules.” This is because if $\mathcal {P} = \mathbb {Z}^n$ , then the module $P_a$ is a free n-graded module over $K[x_1,\ldots ,x_n]$ . See [Reference Carlsson and ZomorodianCZ09, Section 4.2]. On the other hand, $P_a$ is not free as an $I(\mathcal {P})$ -module, so we have chosen not to use the word free in this context. See also [Reference Bubenik and MilićevićBM21, Section 6].

By construction, if M is a spread module, then $\dim M(a) \leq 1$ for all $a \in \mathcal {P}$ . Modules with this property are sometimes called thin. Another motivation for studying spread modules is the following.

Theorem 2.8 [Reference Asashiba, Buchet, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiABE+22, Theorem 24]

Suppose $\mathcal {P} = [0,a]\times [0,b]\subseteq \mathbb {Z}^2$ is a product of two finite totally ordered sets. Then every thin indecomposable module in $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ is isomorphic to a spread module.

As previously mentioned, if $\mathcal {P}$ is totally ordered, then all indecomposable modules are spread modules. Theorem 2.8 thus points toward a natural invariant: the multiplicity of thin modules in the direct sum decomposition. If the quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ is Dynkin type A, this invariant is equivalent to the barcode. More generally, however, this invariant loses all information about any indecomposable direct summand which is not thin. Nevertheless, in some applications, it looks like the proportion of non-thin factors is small, making this invariant somewhat valuable. See, e.g., [Reference Escolar and HiraokaEH16, Section 5] for further discussion.

An immediate consequence of Theorem 2.8 is that, over these particular posets, thin indecomposable modules are uniquely determined by their support. For more general posets, however, there are thin indecomposables which are neither isomorphic to spread modules nor determined by their support, as seen in the following example.

Example 2.9 As in [Reference MillerMil, Example 2.7], let $\mathcal {P}$ be the poset with Hasse diagram.

Note that the incidence algebra $I(\mathcal {P})$ is in this case a path algebra of type $\widetilde {A}_3$ . Now, for $\lambda \in K$ , let $N_\lambda $ be the following thin module.

It is well known that each $N_\lambda $ is indecomposable and that $N_\lambda \simeq N_{\lambda '}$ if and only if $\lambda = \lambda '$ . Moreover, we observe that $N_\lambda $ is a spread module if and only if $\lambda = 1$ (in which case we have $N_\lambda = M_{[\{1,2\},\{3,4\}]}$ ). This shows that $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ contains thin indecomposables which are neither isomorphic to spread modules nor determined by their support.

3 Motivation and related invariants

In this section, we examine many invariants from the literature and how the information they contain is interpreted. In particular, we highlight places where homological algebra can be used to clarify, complement, or expand existing frameworks. This section is not meant as a thorough treatise, but rather as motivation for studying the particular invariants we propose.

While we give formal definitions in Definition 4.10, we recall that an (additive) invariant is a map $p:\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P}) \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^n$ which is constant on isomorphism classes and satisfies $p(M\oplus N) = p(M) + p(N)$ . Furthermore, we say that two invariants p and q are equivalent if $p(M) = p(N)$ if and only if $q(M) = q(N)$ for all $M, N \in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ .

3.1 The dimension vector/Hilbert function

We begin by overviewing many different ways that one may interpret the dimension vector. Recall that for a persistence module M, the dimension vector (or Hilbert function) is defined by

$$ \begin{align*}\underline{\mathrm{dim}} M = (\dim M(a))_{a \in \mathcal{P}}.\end{align*} $$

This invariant is often considered as taking values in the free abelian group with basis $\mathcal {P}$ ; however, we can also see $\underline {\mathrm {dim}}{M}$ as an element of the free abelian group with basis $\{[S_a] \mid a \in \mathcal {P}\}$ . (Precisely, we are treating $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M$ as an element of the classical Grothendieck group of $\mathsf {mod} I(\mathcal {P})$ . See Section 4.) The second choice highlights the fact that given a short exact sequence

$$ \begin{align*}0 \rightarrow L \rightarrow M \rightarrow N \rightarrow 0\end{align*} $$

of persistence modules, one has that

$$ \begin{align*}\underline{\mathrm{dim}}(M) = \underline{\mathrm{dim}}(L) + \underline{\mathrm{dim}}(N).\end{align*} $$

In particular, the dimension vector $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M$ and the multiset of composition factors for M uniquely determine one another. As a special case, we have that $\underline {\mathrm {dim}}(M\oplus N) = \underline {\mathrm {dim}}(M) + \underline {\mathrm {dim}}(N)$ ; that is, the dimension vector is an (additive) invariant.

We now turn toward understanding the dimension vector $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M$ using the projective modules $P_a$ . To start with, recall the well-known fact that for $a \in \mathcal {P}$ , one has $\dim M(a) = \dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(P_a,M)$ . One may then see $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M$ as counting the number of “test morphisms” from a set of well-understood modules (namely the indecomposable projectives). Moreover, if $I(\mathcal {P})$ has finite global dimension, then there is a change of basis $\sigma : \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {P}|} \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {P}|}$ which can be conceptualized as sending the free abelian group with basis $\{S_a \mid a \in \mathcal {P}\}$ to that with basis $\{P_a \mid a \in \mathcal {P}\}$ . Formally, $\sigma $ is defined as the inverse of the Cartan matrix of $I(\mathcal {P})$ . Since we are working over a poset algebra, this also coincides with the Möbius inversion formula. We will give further details in Section 4, but for the purpose of this section, the change of basis $\sigma $ works as follows. Given an arbitrary projective module P, there is a unique direct sum decomposition $P \simeq \bigoplus _{a \in \mathcal {P}} (P_a)^{r_a}$ . We then set $[P] = \sum _{a \in \mathcal {P}} r_a [P_a]$ , where $[P_a]$ is the basis element corresponding to $P_a$ . Now, given M an arbitrary persistence module, we choose a finite projective resolution

$$ \begin{align*}P_m \rightarrow \cdots \rightarrow P_1 \rightarrow P_0 \rightarrow M.\end{align*} $$

One then has $\sigma (\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M) = \sum _{j = 1}^m (-1)^j [P_j]$ . Taking this one step further, let us denote by $[M]_a$ the coefficient of $[P_a]$ in $\sigma (\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M)$ . Now, define

$$ \begin{align*}P_+ = \bigoplus_{a: [M]_a> 0} (P_a)^{[M]_a}, \qquad\qquad P_- = \bigoplus_{a: [M]_a < 0} (P_a)^{-[M]_a}.\end{align*} $$

One may then consider the pair $(P_+,P_-)$ as a “signed approximation” of M by the category of projective modules. Indeed, by applying $\sigma ^{-1}$ , we obtain the equation $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M = \underline {\mathrm {dim}} P_+ - \underline {\mathrm {dim}} P_-$ .

To summarize, we have the following ways to interpret the dimension vector $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M$ :

  1. (1) as recording the dimensions of the vector spaces comprising M,

  2. (2) as recording the number of “test morphisms” from the indecomposable projectives to M,

  3. (3) as some data determined by a projective resolution of M,

  4. (4) as a “signed approximation” of M by the category of projective modules.

As we will see in Section 4, “the homological invariants” we introduce in this paper are readily given interpretations in the spirit (2)–(4) above. In essence, we will enlarge the set of indecomposable projective modules to a larger set $\mathcal {X}$ of indecomposable $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules, typically a subset of the connected spread modules. This instantly gives rise to the invariant $(\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(R,M))_{R \in \mathcal {X}}$ , which can be seen as counting “test morphisms” from the objects in $\mathcal {X}$ to M. For many choices of $\mathcal {X}$ , this is equivalent to data coming from an “ $\mathcal {X}$ -resolution” of M. As each step of such a resolution is an “approximation” in some precise sense, the result is readily interpreted as a “signed approximation” of M by $\mathcal {X}$ . Finally, as made explicit in Proposition 5.1, it is also possible to understand our invariants more directly in the spirit of (1) above.

In the remainder of this section, we focus on many of the invariants which serve as motivation and background for our study. In particular, we emphasize existing works that yield interpretations in the spirt of (2)–(4) above. We also discuss alternative approaches to extracting data from a projective resolution, as these can also be readily applied to our new framework.

3.2 The rank invariant and its generalizations

Recall the definition of the rank invariant $\underline {\mathrm {rk}} M$ from equation (1.1). In this section, we explain various interpretations and generalizations of the rank invariant which have appeared in recent work.

3.2.1 The generalized rank invariant and compressed multiplicities

The rank invariant can be seen as associating one nonnegative integerFootnote 1 to M for each interval $I = [a,b] \subseteq \mathcal {P}$ . The recent works [Reference ThomasTho19, Section 3.2], [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21], and [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb] each give alternative interpretations of these integers which extend naturally to allow one to consider subsets of $\mathcal {P}$ which are not intervals. This results in new invariants, known as the multirank invariant [Reference ThomasTho19, Section 3.2], the generalized rank invariant [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21], and compressed multiplicities [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb]. We give a brief overview of these constructions.

Remark 3.1 In [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21], the authors work over general posets (without the assumption that $|\mathcal {P}| < \infty $ ), but we keep the assumption that $|\mathcal {P}| < \infty $ for simplicity. Moreover, they consider functors with target categories more general than $\mathrm {vec}(K)$ .

The definition that follows makes use of the categorical notions of limits and colimits. A brief explanation of these constructions can be found in [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21, Section 3.1 and Appendix A]. Note also that our definition is slightly more general than that of [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21], in which it is required that X be (path-)connected as a subset of $\mathcal {P}$ .

Definition 3.2 Let M be a ( $\mathcal {P}$ -)persistence module, and let $X \subseteq \mathcal {P}$ such that X is a connected poset with the induced order from $\mathcal {P}$ .Footnote 2 We define a diagram $M(X)$ in the category of finite-dimensional K-vector spaces as follows:

  • The objects of $M(X)$ are the vector spaces $M(a)$ for $a \in X$ .

  • The morphisms of $M(X)$ are the linear maps $M(a,b)$ for $a \leq b \in X$ .

Alternatively, one may view $M(X)$ as the restriction of M to X. We denote by $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,X)$ the rank of the natural map from the limit of $M(X)$ to the colimit of $M(X)$ . We refer to $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,X)$ as the X-rank of M. More generally, for $\mathcal {R}$ a subset of the power set $2^{\mathcal {P}}$ consisting of sets X as in Definition 3.2, we define the $\mathcal {R}$ -rank of M to be $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R}) := (\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,X))_{X \in \mathcal {R}}$ .

If $X = [a,b]$ is an interval subset of $\mathcal {P}$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,X) = \operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M(a,b))$ . In particular, if $\mathcal {I}$ is the set of intervals in $\mathcal {P}$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {I}) = \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M)$ . Motivated by this fact, Kim and Mémoli define the generalized rank invariant in [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21]. This is precisely the invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R})$ for $\mathcal {R}$ , the set of “path-connected” subsets of $\mathcal {P}$ . In the subsequent works [Reference Dey, Kim and MémoliDKM, Reference Kim and MooreKM], the set $\mathcal {R}$ has been restricted to that of (all) connected spreads. More generally, in [Reference Bubenik and ScottBOO], Botnan, Oppermann, and Oudot consider the invariants $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R})$ , where $\mathcal {R}$ is any set of the connected spreads. (They actually work over posets which may not be finite and impose some conditions on these sets, but these conditions are always satisfied over finite posets.)

In another recent work [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb], Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima, and Yoshiwaki work exclusively with finite posets of the form $[0,a] \times [0,b] \subseteq \mathbb {Z}^2$ . For every spread $[A,B]$ , they introduce three invariants. It is shown in [Reference Kim and MooreKM], using [Reference Chambers, Letscher, Chambers, Fasy and ZiegelmeierCL18, Lemma 3.1], that the “total compression factor” of [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb] is precisely $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,[A,B])$ . An analogous argument shows that the “sink-source compression factor” and “corner-complete compression factor” of [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb] are both of the form $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,X)$ for some choice of X. For example, let $[A,B] \subseteq \mathcal {P}$ be a connected spread. Then the invariant $d^{ss}(M,[A,B])$ introduced in [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb] is precisely $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,A\cup B)$ .

Finally, the “multirank function” introduced by Thomas in [Reference ThomasTho19, Section 3.2] is similar in concept to the association $X \mapsto \operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,X)$ , but it does not rely on the formal concepts of limits and colimits. Indeed, given a pair of subsets $X, Y \subseteq \mathcal {P}$ with no restrictions, Thomas defines the “multirank from X to Y” as the rank of a map $\oplus _{a \in X} M(a) \rightarrow \oplus _{b \in Y} M(b)$ formed by the component maps of M together with zero maps where necessary. When $X = A$ and $Y = B$ are antichains and $[A,B]$ is a connected spread, we expect that the rank of this map will be related to $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,A \cup B)$ .

3.2.2 Signed barcodes and Möbius inversion

In this section, we will discuss how Möbius inversion can be used to reinterpret the $\mathcal {R}$ -rank invariants. We refer to [Reference StanleySta11, Section 3.7] for the definition of Möbius inversion.

As previously mentioned, when $\mathcal {P}$ is totally ordered, the (classical) rank invariant is equivalent to the barcode (see also Section 7.1 for the formal statement). To unpack this fact, let us view the rank invariant and barcode as taking values in the free abelian groups whose bases are given by the sets of (i) interval subsets of $\mathcal {P}$ and (ii) interval modules over $I(\mathcal {P})$ . Then Möbius inversion is a change of basis $\sigma : \mathbb {Z}^{{|\mathcal {P}|}\choose {2}} \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^{{|\mathcal {P}|}\choose {2}}$ which sends $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M)$ to the barcode of M. We emphasize that this change of basis is not the one that sends the interval $[a,b]$ to the interval module $M_{[a,b]}$ .

We now return to the case where $\mathcal {P}$ is not totally ordered. As in the preceding section, let $\mathcal {R}$ be a subset of the power set $2^{\mathcal {P}}$ consisting of sets X as in Definition 3.2. Then $\mathcal {R}$ is itself a poset under inclusion. We denote by $\delta (M,\mathcal {R})$ the result of applying the resulting Möbius inversion formula to the invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R})$ . Invariants obtained in this way are sometimes referred to as “generalized persistence diagrams.” See, e.g., [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb, Reference Betthauser, Bubenik and EdwardsBBE22, Reference Bubenik and ElchesenBE22, Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO Reference Kim and MémoliKM21, Reference McCleary and PatelMP22, Reference PatelPat18].

In [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb, Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO, Reference Kim and MémoliKM21], the invariants $\delta (M,\mathcal {R})$ are considered for the choices of $\mathcal {R}$ (and generality of poset) discussed in the previous section. To better understand these invariants, given a set $\mathcal {R}$ of connected spreads, we denote $\mathcal {M}(\mathcal {R}) = \{[M_{[A,B]}] | [A,B] \in \mathcal {R}\}$ . In all three works, the invariant $\delta (M,\mathcal {R})$ is considered as taking values in the free abelian group which has $\mathcal {M}(\mathcal {R})$ as a basis.Footnote 3 It is then shown that for any $[A,B] \in \mathcal {R}$ one has $\delta (M_{[A,B]},\mathcal {R}) = [M_{[A,B]}]$ . Due to this fact, one can interpret these particular invariants as “signed approximations” by spread modules. The word “signed” here refers to the fact that some of the coefficients of $\delta (M,\mathcal {R})$ may be negative.

Finally, for $[A,B] \in \mathcal {R}$ , let us denote by $r_{[A,B]}$ the coefficient of $[M_{[A,B]}]$ in $\delta (M,\mathcal {R})$ . Now, define

$$ \begin{align*}M_+ = \bigoplus_{[A,B]: r_{[A,B]}> 0} (M_{[A,B]})^{r(M,[A,B])}, \qquad\qquad M_- = \bigoplus_{[A,B]: r_{[A,B]} < 0} (M_{[A,B]})^{-r(M,[A,B])}.\end{align*} $$

By applying the inverse Möbius inversion formula, one then obtains the equation $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R}) = \operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M_+,\mathcal {R}) - \operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M_-,\mathcal {R})$ . See [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO, Theorem 2.5], where the pair $(M_+,M_-)$ is referred to as a “signed rank decomposition.” In the special case that $\mathcal {R} = \mathcal {I}$ is the set of intervals, we recall that $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {I}) = \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M)$ . In this case, the pair $(M_+,M_-)$ admits a visual interpretation called the “signed barcode.” See [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO, Section 6].

To summarize, there has been a large amount of recent work aimed at turning the $\mathcal {R}$ -rank invariants $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R})$ into signed approximations $\delta (M,\mathcal {R})$ by spread modules. One of our goals is to examine if and when these coincide with the homological notion of a (signed) approximation by spread modules, as defined in Section 4. For the (classical) rank invariant, [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO] has already given an affirmative answer to this question, which we will now explain.

3.2.3 Test morphisms and exact structures

In [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO], the authors consider a set $\mathcal {H}$ of spreads called hooks. (See Section 7.2 for the definition.) They then show that the rank invariant $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M)$ is equivalent to the (dim-hom) invariant $(\dim _K\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_I(\mathcal {P})(H,M))_{H \in \mathcal {H}}$ . In other words, the rank invariant can be seen as recording the number of “test morphisms” from the hook modules to M.

It is further shown that the hook modules are precisely the indecomposable “relative projective” modules for some exact structure on $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ . We will discuss exact structures in more detail in Section 4. For the purposes of motivation, this amounts to choosing a subset of short exact sequences in $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ which are deemed “admissible.” In [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO], these are the short exact sequences $0 \rightarrow L \rightarrow M \rightarrow N \rightarrow 0$ for which $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M) = \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(L) + \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(N)$ . As a consequence of our Theorem 7.4, this means that the rank invariant is equivalent to a “signed approximation” by hook modules in the homological algebra sense. In other words, the rank invariant is a “homological invariant” as defined in Definition 4.12. In Section 7.2, we more carefully examine how this compares to the signed approximation coming from the invariant $\delta (M,\mathcal {H})$ .

3.3 Generalized Betti numbers and g-vectors

As the dimension vector can be derived from the data of a projective resolution, so too can homological invariants be derived from the data of a “relative projective resolution.” In our discussion of the dimension vector, this is done by taking the signed sum of the terms which appear in the resolution. However, this is not the only way to turn the data of a resolution into a vector which is readily usable in machine learning. We will briefly explain some of the alternative vectorization methods, all of which can be used in a straightforward manner for our relative homological algebra framework.

Let M be an $I(\mathcal {P})$ -module and assume it admits a finite projective resolution

$$ \begin{align*}P_m \xrightarrow{f_m} \cdots \xrightarrow{f_2} P_1 \xrightarrow{f_1} P_0 \xrightarrow{f_0} M.\end{align*} $$

We will further assume that this projective resolution is taken to be “minimal,” meaning that each map $f_k$ is the projective cover of $\ker (f_{k-1})$ . For $a \in \mathcal {P}$ , and $k \in \{0,\ldots ,m\}$ , we denote by $r_{k,a}$ the multiplicity of $P_a$ as a direct summand of $P_k$ . Each $r_{k,a}$ can be seen as an invariant of M, and in particular each tuple $(r_{k,a})_{a \in \mathcal {P}}$ is referred to as the kth generalized Betti numbers of M. This is a straightforward analog of classical Betti numbers, where one records the multiplicities of free modules in a free resolution.

We recall that the dimension vector can be recovered from the generalized Betti numbers. Indeed, the dimension vector $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M$ is then (equivalent to) $\sum _{k = 0}^m\sum _{a \in \mathcal {P}}r_{k,a} [P_a]$ , where $[P_a]$ is the basis element associated with $P_a$ . This means that the generalized Betti numbers contain more information than the dimension vector. On the other hand, we caution that, unlike the dimension vector, the generalized Betti numbers require the assumption that our chosen projective resolution is minimal. Without this, they will no longer be well defined.

Especially in cases where an algebra has infinite global dimension, one may also record only the first k generalized Betti numbers for some choice of k. This is related to the concept of “g-vectors” from representation theory. Given a module M, its g-vector is by definition $(r_{0,a}-r_{1,a})_{a \in \mathcal {P}}$ . This invariant is particularly important to the concepts of cluster algebras [Reference Fomin and ZelevinskyFZ07], $\tau $ -tilting theory [Reference Adachi, Iyama and ReitenAIR14], and stability conditions [Reference KingKin94].

3.4 Amplitudes and a view toward stability

We conclude our motivation section with a brief discussion of stability. In this paper, we primarily discuss invariants as a tool for determining whether two persistence modules belong to the same isomorphism class. However, in applications, one is often interested in whether two persistence modules are derived from similar data (or from similar filtrations of topological spaces). In order for invariants to be useful for this purpose, one turns to stability. Given an invariant p, the key idea is to define a meaningful notion of distance on the output space of p. Informally, one then says that p is stable if given two “similar” persistence modules M and N, one has that the distance between $p(M)$ and $p(N)$ is sufficiently small.

After the first version of this manuscript was posted to arXiv, Oudot and Scoccola proved a stability result for certain invariants coming from exact structures [Reference Oudot and ScoccolaOS, Theorem 26]. Their result is proved with respect to the “Bottleneck dissimilarity function” for finitely presented $\mathbb {R}^n$ -persistence modules. Another place one may turn to look for stability results is the recent work of Giunti, Nolan, Otter, and Waas on amplitudes and their stability [Reference Giunti, Nolan, Otter and WaasGNOW]. Amplitudes are $\mathbb {Z}$ -valued invariants which are defined for any abelian category, and are characterized by how they behave with respect to short exact sequences. One could readily adapt this definition to the generality of exact categories by considering only those short exact sequences which are deemed “admissible.” It remains an open question to determine whether such a modification could be used to prove stability results for the invariants introduced in this paper.

4 Relative homological algebra

The purpose of this section is to provide background on relative homological algebra and relative Grothendieck groups. We largely follow the setup of Auslander and Solberg [Reference Auslander and SolbergAS93]. As these results are fully general, throughout this section, we will work over a finite-dimensional K-algebra $\Lambda $ and assume only (i) that $\Lambda $ is basic and (ii) that every simple $\Lambda $ -module is one-dimensional over K. Nevertheless, we note that the incidence algebras $I(\mathcal {P})$ satisfy both (i) and (ii), and so readers interested mainly in applications to persistence theory can safely replace $\Lambda $ with $I(\mathcal {P})$ .

The assumptions (i) and (ii) are made to facilitate the discussion of the dimension vector in the sequel. We recall its more general definition now.

Definition 4.1 Let $\mathcal {U}$ be the set of indecomposable projective $\Lambda $ -modules, and let $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ . Then the dimension vector of M is

$$ \begin{align*}\underline{\mathrm{dim}} M := (\dim_K\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(P,M))_{P \in \mathcal{U}}.\end{align*} $$

Alternatively, the assumptions (i) and (ii) are equivalent to the existence of a finite quiver Q such that $\Lambda $ is a quotient of the path algebra $KQ$ by an admissible ideal. In particular, every module $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ can be considered as a representation of Q analogously to the way an $I(\mathcal {P})$ -module is seen as a functor from $\mathcal {P}$ . For each vertex v of Q, we denote by $M(v)$ the vector space at vertex v arising from viewing M in this way. There is then a bijection $\sigma $ from $\mathcal {U}$ to the set of vertices of Q such that for all $P \in \mathcal {U}$ one has $\dim _K M(\sigma (P)) = \dim _K\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(P,M)$ .

4.1 Approximations, exact structures, and Grothendieck groups

Let $\mathcal {X}$ be a finite set of indecomposable modules, and let M be an arbitrary module. We recall that $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ is the subcategory of $\mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ consisting of all finite direct sums (including the empty direct sum) of modules in $\mathcal {X}$ . We say a morphism $f: R\rightarrow M$ , where $R \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ , is a (right) $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation if every morphism $R' \rightarrow M$ with $R' \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ factors through f. Since we have assumed $\mathcal {X}$ to be finite, such a morphism is guaranteed to exist. We call f a minimal approximation by $\mathcal {X}$ if for all $g: R \rightarrow R$ such that $f \circ g = f$ , the endomorphism g is an isomorphism. This is equivalent for asking the domain of f to have the minimum possible number of direct summands.

The following lemma is crucial to the remainder of our setup.

Lemma 4.2 Suppose $\mathcal {X}$ contains all of the indecomposable projective modules, and let $f: R \rightarrow M$ be an approximation by $\mathcal {X}$ . Then f is an epimorphism.

Proof Let $q: P \rightarrow M$ be the projective cover of M. By assumption, $P \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ , so there exists $g: P \rightarrow R$ such that $q = f \circ g$ . Since q is an epimorphism, this implies that f is an epimorphism as well.

We now consider two examples. Note in particular that Example 4.3(2) shows that there may exist epimorphisms from $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ to M which are not $\mathcal {X}$ -approximations.

Example 4.3

  1. (1) If $\mathcal {X}$ consists only of the indecomposable projectives, then any epimorphism $f: R \rightarrow M$ with $R \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ is an $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation. Indeed, any morphism $g: R'\rightarrow M$ with $R' \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ will factor through f by the definition of projective. Moreover, such an epimorphism f will be minimal if and only if it is the projective cover of M.

  2. (2) Let $\Lambda = K(1\rightarrow 2)$ . Then $\mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ contains three indecomposable modules: the projective-injective $P_1$ , the simple-projective $P_2$ , and the simple-injective $S_1$ . Let $\mathcal {X} = \{P_1,P_2,S_1\}$ . Then the identity $S_1\rightarrow S_1$ is an $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation which does not factor through the projective cover $P_1 \rightarrow S_1$ . This shows that the projective cover $P_1\to S_1$ , which is an epimorphism from add $(\mathcal {X})$ , is not an $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation.

We will assume from now on that $\mathcal {X}$ contains all of the indecomposable projectives. In light of the previous lemma, we can then consider an analog of a projective resolution of M, formed by taking approximations by $\mathcal {X}$ at each step. This yields the following diagram, where each $p_j$ is an approximation by $\mathcal {X}$ and $q_j=i_{j-1} \circ p_j$ for every j.

The first row of this diagram is exact by definition, and is called a resolution of M by  $\mathcal {X}$ or $\mathcal {X}$ -resolution. If every $p_i$ is a minimal approximation, then the resolution itself is called minimal. We then have the following definitions (see [Reference Enochs and JendaEJ00, Section 8.4]).

Definition 4.4

  1. (1) Let $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , and let $R_\bullet $ be a minimal resolution of M by $\mathcal {X}$ . The $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of M is then defined as $\min (\{j \mid R_{j+1} = 0\} \cup \{\infty \})$ .

  2. (2) The $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is defined to be the supremum over $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ of the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of M.

  3. (3) If there exists a module of infinite $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension, we say the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is properly infinite. On the other hand, if the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is infinity but every $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ has finite $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension, we say that the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is effectively infinite.

Remark 4.5

  1. (1) If $\mathcal {X}$ contains only the indecomposable projectives, the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimensions of a module M and of the algebra $\Lambda $ coincide with the projective dimension and global dimension, respectively. In this case, it is well known that algebras with effectively infinite $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension do not exist.

  2. (2) The relationship between the projective dimension and $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of a module, and by extension between the global dimension and $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of an algebra, is not clear. For example, in the setup of Example 4.3, the projective dimension of $S_1$ is 1, whereas its $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension is 0. On the other hand, in Example 6.4, we give an example of a module with projective dimension 1 and infinite $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension. One way to explain this discrepancy is that as we increase the size of $\mathcal {X}$ , we have both added more modules with which to form $\mathcal {X}$ -approximations, but also added more maps which need to factor through these approximations.

Now, let $\mathcal {E}_{\mathrm {max}}$ be the class of short exact sequences in $\mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ . We then denote

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{E}_{\mathcal{X}} = \left\{\left(0 \rightarrow M \xrightarrow{f} N \xrightarrow{g} L \rightarrow 0\right)\in \mathcal{E}_{max} \ \middle| \ (\forall R \in \mathcal{X}) \ \operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(R,g) \text{ is surjective}\right\}.\end{align*} $$

Equivalently, the short exact sequences in $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ are precisely those on which the functor $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(R,-)$ is exact for all $R \in \mathcal {X}$ .

It is shown in [Reference Dräxler, Reiten, Smalø and SolbergDRSS99] that $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ gives an exact structure on $\mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ . Readers are referred to [Reference BühlerBü11] for more information on exact structures. In the present paper, we will only use the following straightforward facts about $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ .

Proposition 4.6

  1. (1) Let $0 \rightarrow M \rightarrow N \rightarrow L \rightarrow 0$ be an exact sequence in $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ . Then

    $$ \begin{align*}\dim \operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(R, N) = \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(R, L) + \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(R, M)\end{align*} $$

    for all $R \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ .

  2. (2) Let $f: R \rightarrow M$ be an approximation of some module M by $\mathcal {X}$ . Then

    $$ \begin{align*}0 \rightarrow \ker(f) \rightarrow R \xrightarrow{f} M \rightarrow 0\end{align*} $$

    is in $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ . Moreover, $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ is the smallest exact structure which contains all such short exact sequences.

  3. (3) Every split short exact sequence is included in $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ .

Bearing this result in mind, we are prepared for the main definition of this section.

Definition 4.7

  1. (1) Let F be the free abelian group generated by the symbols $[M]$ for every isomorphism class of $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ . Denote by $H_{\mathcal {X}}$ the subgroup generated by the collection

    $$ \begin{align*}\{[M]-[N]+[L]\; | \text{ there exists a short exact sequence } 0\to M\to N\to L\to 0 \text{ in }\mathcal{E}_{\mathcal{X}}\}.\end{align*} $$

    The quotient group $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X}):= F/H_{\mathcal {X}}$ is called the Grothendieck group of $\Lambda $ relative to $\mathcal {X}$ .

  2. (2) Given $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , we denote by $[M]_{\mathcal {X}}$ (or just $[M]$ if the set $\mathcal {X}$ is clear from context) the representative of M in the Grothendieck group $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ .

Before proceeding, we highlight two important examples of relative Grothendieck groups.

Example 4.8

  1. (1) Let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of indecomposable projective modules. Then $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}} = \mathcal {E}_{\mathrm{max}}$ contains all short exact sequences. In this case, we call $K_0(\Lambda ) := K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ the classical Grothendieck group. This group has a basis given by the simple modules. By our assumptions (i) and (ii) from the beginning of Section 4, we can identify $[M] \in K_0(\Lambda )$ with the dimension vector of M using this basis. If in addition we assume that the global dimension of $\Lambda $ is finite, then $K_0(\Lambda )$ also has a dual basis given by $\mathcal {X}$ .

  2. (2) Let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of all indecomposable $\Lambda $ -modules. While this will generally not be a finite set, much of the theory developed in this section still applies. In particular, the exact structure $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ contains only the split short exact sequences. This exact structure is often denoted $\mathcal {E}_{\mathrm{min}}$ , and the corresponding relative Grothendieck group is often denoted $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda ):= K_0(\Lambda , \mathcal {E}_{\mathrm{min}})$ . This is the free abelian group with basis the set of isomorphism classes of indecomposable $\Lambda $ -modules (see, e.g., Proposition 4.9). That is, given a module $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , the data $[M] \in K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda )$ are equivalent to the direct sum decomposition of M. In particular, the isomorphism class of M is uniquely determined by $[M]$ .

Proposition 4.9 If the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is not properly infinite, the Grothendieck group $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ is free abelian with basis $\{[R]\mid R\in \mathcal {X} \}$ . In particular, $K_0(\Lambda , \mathcal {X}) \simeq \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {X}|}$ . Moreover, if

$$ \begin{align*}0\to R_n\xrightarrow{q_n}\cdots \xrightarrow{q_2} R_1\xrightarrow{q_1} R_0\xrightarrow{q_0} M\to 0\end{align*} $$

is a finite $\mathcal {X}$ -resolution of $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , then $[M] = \sum _{i = 0}^n (-1)^i [R_i]$ .

Proof Let $M\in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ and choose a finite $\mathcal {X}$ -resolution of M as in the statement. We can extract short exact sequences

$$ \begin{align*}0\to \text{ker}(q_i) {\hookrightarrow} R_i {\twoheadrightarrow} \text{ker}(q_{i+1})\to 0.\end{align*} $$

Each of these short exact sequences is in $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ by Proposition 4.6. So, in the Grothendieck group, $[R_i]= [\text {ker}(q_i)] + [\text {ker}(q_{i+1})]$ for all i. This yields

$$ \begin{align*} [M]&= [R_0] - [\text{ker}(q_0)]\\ &= [R_0] - \big( [R_1] - [\text{ker}(q_1)]\big) \\ &= [R_0] - [R_1] + \big( [R_2] - [\text{ker}(q_2)]\big)\\ &=\cdots\\ &= \sum_{i=0}^n (-1)^i [R_i], \end{align*} $$

where each $R_i$ is in $\text {add}(\mathcal {X})$ . This shows $\{[R] \mid R\in \mathcal {X} \}$ generates the Grothendieck group.

It remains to show that $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X}) = \langle [R]\rangle _{R \in \mathcal {X}}$ is free abelian. To see this, we recall that the short exact sequences ending in an $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation generate the subgroup $H_{\mathcal {X}}$ defining $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ . See Definition 4.7 and [Reference Auslander and SolbergAS93]. Moreover, given $R \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ , the identity $R\rightarrow R$ is a minimal $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation. Together, these facts imply that every exact sequence generating $H_{\mathcal {X}}$ on the subcategory $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ is split. This concludes the proof.

4.2 Homological and dim-hom invariants

In this section, we define dim-hom invariants and homological invariants. In order to make these definitions precise, we first formalize what we mean by an invariant, as outlined in the introduction.

Definition 4.10

  1. (1) An invariant is a surjective group homomorphism $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda ) \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^n$ for some $n \in \mathbb {N}$ . We call n the rank of the invariant p.

  2. (2) Given p and q two invariants, we say that p is finer than q if $\ker p \subseteq \ker q$ . Likewise, we say that p is equivalent to q if $\ker p = \ker q$ . In particular, p is finer than q if and only if $q(M)=q(N)$ implies $p(M)=p(N)$ .

To study different types of invariants, we consider inclusions of exact structures (see [Reference Brüstle, Hassoun, Langford and RoyBHLR20]). We need in particular the following lemma.

Lemma 4.11 Let $\mathcal {X}$ and $\mathcal {Y}$ be finite sets of indecomposable modules which contain the indecomposable projectives, and suppose that $\mathcal {X} \subseteq \mathcal {Y}$ . Then there is a well-defined quotient map $p: K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {Y}) \rightarrow K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ .

Proof It is immediate from the definitions of $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ and $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {Y}}$ that $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}} \supseteq \mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {Y}}$ . The result then follows immediately from the definitions of $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ and $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {Y})$ .

We note that, even if $\mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ contains infinitely many indecomposable objects, the statement and proof of Lemma 4.11 can be adapted to allow one to take $\mathcal {X}$ to be the set of all indecomposable modules. Thus, for any finite set $\mathcal {Y}$ of indecomposable modules containing the indecomposable projectives, we have that $K_0(\Lambda , \mathcal {Y})$ is a quotient of $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda )$ . This leads to the following definition.

Definition 4.12 Let $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda )\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^n$ be an invariant, and let $\mathcal {X}$ be a finite set of indecomposable modules.

  1. (1) We say that p is a dim-hom invariant relative to  $\mathcal {X}$ if it is equivalent to the invariant given by the map

    $$ \begin{align*} K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda) &\rightarrow \mathbb{Z}^{|\mathcal{X}|} \\ M &\mapsto (\dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_{\Lambda}(R,M))_{R \in \mathcal{X}}. \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) We say that p is homological relative to $\mathcal {X}$ if all of the following hold:

    1. (1) All of the indecomposable projectives are in $\mathcal {X}$ .

    2. (2) The $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is not properly infinite.

    3. (3) p is equivalent to the invariant given by the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda ) \rightarrow K_0(\Lambda , \mathcal {X})\simeq \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {X}|}.$

  3. (3) We say that p is a dim-hom invariant (resp. homological invariant) if it is a dim-hom (resp. homological) invariant relative to some $\mathcal {X}$ .

We will show that if a given $\mathcal {X}$ respects some assumptions extending (2b) above, then the homological and dim-hom invariants relative to $\mathcal {X}$ coincide. See Theorem 4.22.

The following example is well known.

Proposition 4.13 Suppose that $\Lambda $ has finite global dimension, and let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of indecomposable projective modules. Then the dimension vector $M \mapsto \underline {\mathrm {dim}} M := (\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (R,M))_{R \in \mathcal {X}}$ and the homological invariant $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda ) \rightarrow K_0(\Lambda )$ are equivalent.

Remark 4.14 In Proposition 4.13, one often interprets $\underline {\mathrm {dim}} M$ as sitting inside of $K_0(\Lambda )$ by taking the simple modules as a basis. One can change to the basis of $K_0(\Lambda )$ given by the indecomposable projectives by sending each simple module to the alternating sum of the terms in its projective resolution. See Section 3.1 for additional discussion.

We will explore homological invariants (and dim-hom invariants) in the context of persistence modules in Section 6.

4.3 Projectivization

Fix a finite set $\mathcal {X}$ of indecomposable modules which contains the indecomposable projectives. In this section, we use the theory of projectivization to construct an algebra with indecomposable projective modules corresponding to modules in $\mathcal {X}$ . In particular, this will allow us to show that, for many choices of $\mathcal {X}$ , the homological and dim-hom invariants relative to $\mathcal {X}$ coincide. It will also allow us to reduce the problem of computing $\mathcal {X}$ -resolutions to that of computing projective resolutions over an endomorphism algebra. The ideas outlined here are well known, and readers are referred to [Reference Auslander, Reiten and SmaløARS95, Section II.2] for details.

We recall that a morphism $f: M \rightarrow N$ is called a section (resp. retraction) if there exists a morphism $g: N \rightarrow M$ such that $g\circ f$ (resp. $f \circ g$ ) is the identity.

Definition 4.15 A morphism $f:R \rightarrow R'$ , with $R, R'\in \mathcal {X}$ , is called $\mathcal {X}$ -irreducible if it is not itself a section or a retraction and if all factorizations of f of the form $R\xrightarrow {g} M\xrightarrow {h} R'$ , with $M\in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ , must have g be a section or h be a retraction.

Now, consider the module $T = T_{\mathcal {X}}: = \bigoplus _{R\in \mathcal {X}} R$ . Then $\Gamma = \Gamma _{\mathcal {X}} := \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_{\Lambda }(T)^{op}$ is a finite-dimensional K-algebra under the composition of morphisms and the standard vector space structure. Denote by Q the Gabriel quiver of $\Gamma $ . The vertices of Q can be identified with $\mathcal {X}$ . Moreover, for $R, R' \in \mathcal {X}$ , the number of arrows $R \rightarrow R'$ in Q coincides with the number of linearly independent $\mathcal {X}$ -irreducible morphisms $R' \rightarrow R$ in $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(X,Y)$ .

The association $M\mapsto \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(T,M)$ yields a functor from $\mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ to $\mathsf {mod} \Gamma $ . The action of $\Gamma $ on $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(T,M)$ is given by precomposition. This functor induces an additive equivalence between $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ and the category of projective $\Gamma $ -modules. That is, given an (indecomposable) module $R\in \mathcal {X}$ , the $\Gamma $ -module $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(T,R)$ is isomorphic to the projective module (over $\Gamma $ ) at the vertex corresponding to R in the quiver Q.

The following is critical.

Proposition 4.16 [Reference Auslander, Reiten and SmaløARS95, Proposition 2.1] Let $R \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ and $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ . Then the functor $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (T,-)$ induces an isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(R,M) \simeq \operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Gamma(\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(T,R),\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(T,M)).\end{align*} $$

Putting this together, we have the following.

Proposition 4.17

  1. (1) Let $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , and let $R_\bullet $ be a (minimal) resolution of M by $\mathcal {X}$ . Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(T,R_\bullet )$ is a (minimal) projective resolution of the $\Gamma $ -module $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(T, M)$ .

  2. (2) Let $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , and let $Q_\bullet $ be a minimal projective resolution of the $\Gamma $ -module $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (T,M)$ . Then there exists a resolution $R_\bullet $ of M by $\mathcal {X}$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (T,R_\bullet ) \simeq Q_\bullet $ .

  3. (3) The $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is bounded by the global dimension of $\Gamma $ . In particular, if $\Gamma $ has finite global dimension, then $\Lambda $ has finite $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension.

Proof (1) and (2) follow immediately from Proposition 4.16 and the fact that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(T,-)$ induces an additive equivalence. (3) is an immediate consequence of (1).

While the global dimension of $\Gamma $ gives an upper bound on the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension, we demonstrate with the following example that this bound will in general not be tight.

Example 4.18 Let $\Lambda $ be as in Example 4.3. Then $\Gamma = \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_\Lambda (P_1\oplus S_1\oplus P_2)^{\mathrm{op}}$ is the so-called Auslander algebra of $\Lambda $ . The Gabriel quiver of $\Gamma $ is

and we can write $\Gamma \simeq KQ/(\iota \pi )$ . It is well known that the global dimension of $\Gamma $ is 2, whereas the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is clearly 0 since $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X}) = \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ .

As a consequence of Propositions 4.17 and 4.9, we have the following.

Proposition 4.19 Suppose that $\Gamma $ is of finite global dimension. Then:

  1. (1) The Grothendieck group relative to $\mathcal {X}$ is free with basis given by $\{[R]\mid R\in \mathcal {X} \}$ . In particular, the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda ) \rightarrow K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ is a homological invariant.

  2. (2) There is an isomorphism of Grothendieck groups $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X}) \rightarrow K_0(\Gamma )$ which sends $[M]$ to $[\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (T,M)]$ .

Remark 4.20

  1. (1) The axioms of exact structures allow one to define a relative version $\mathcal {D}^b( \Lambda , \mathcal {X})$ of the derived category of $\Lambda $ relative to $\mathcal {X}$ (see [Reference KrauseKra21, Chapter 4]). When the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is finite, then it can be shown that T is a tilting object as defined in [Reference KrauseKra21, Section 7.2]. In this case, the functor $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{\Lambda }(T,-)$ induces an additive equivalence $\mathcal {D}^b( \Lambda , \mathcal {X}) \to \mathcal {D}^b( \Gamma ),$ and thus also an isomorphism of the corresponding Grothendieck groups $K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X}) \simeq K_0(\Gamma ).$ It is well known that the Grothendieck group $K_0(\Gamma )$ is freely generated by the projective $\Gamma $ -modules since $\Gamma $ has finite global dimension. As the projectives correspond to the elements of $\mathcal {X}$ under the above isomorphism, we can deduce Proposition 4.9 from the general theory of relative derived categories.

    Note, however, that the simple $\Gamma $ -modules in general do not correspond to $\Lambda $ -modules, but only to objects in the relative derived category. So, even if the derived categories are equivalent, the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is in general not equal to the global dimension of $\Gamma $ , like it is often observed in classical tilting theory.

  2. (2) We are not aware of any case where the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $\Lambda $ is finite and the global dimension of $\Gamma $ is infinity. It would not be surprising if such a case were impossible in light of the fact that tilting preserves finite global dimension (see [Reference Keller and KrauseKK20]).

We are now prepared to prove the main results of this section.

Proposition 4.21 Let $\mathcal {X}$ be a finite set of indecomposable $\Lambda $ -modules which contains the indecomposable projectives, and suppose that the global dimension of $\Gamma = \Gamma _{\mathcal {X}}$ is finite. Given $M \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , write $[M] \in K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ in the form

$$ \begin{align*}[M] = \sum_{R \in \mathcal{X}} c_R[R],\end{align*} $$

where each $c_R \in \mathbb {Z}$ . Then, for $R' \in \mathcal {X}$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*}\dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(R',M) = \sum_{R \in \mathcal{X}}c_R\dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(R',R).\end{align*} $$

Proof Let n be the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of M. We proceed by induction of n.

If $n = 0$ , then $M \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ . The result then follows immediately from the additivity of the functors $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(R',-)$ .

Now, let $n> 0$ and suppose that the result holds for $n - 1$ . Let $f: R \twoheadrightarrow M$ be a minimal $ \mathcal {X}$ -approximation of M. Note that f is surjective by Lemma 4.2 and the short exact sequence

$$ \begin{align*}0 \rightarrow \ker f \rightarrow R \rightarrow M \rightarrow 0\end{align*} $$

is in $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}}$ by Proposition 4.6(2). So we have $[M] = [R] - [\ker f]$ . Moreover, for $R' \in \mathcal {X}$ , Proposition 4.6(1) implies that

$$ \begin{align*}\dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(R', M) = \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(R', R) - \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_\Lambda(R',\ker f).\end{align*} $$

Since the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimensions of R and $\ker f$ are 0 and $n-1$ , respectively, the result then follows from the induction hypothesis.

Theorem 4.22 (Theorem 1.1)

Let $\mathcal {X}$ be a finite set of indecomposable $\Lambda $ -modules which contains the indecomposable projectives, and suppose that the global dimension of $\Gamma = \Gamma _{\mathcal {X}}$ is finite. Let $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda ) \rightarrow K_0(\Lambda ,\mathcal {X})$ be the canonical quotient map, and let $q: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(\Lambda ) \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {X}|}$ be the dim-hom invariant given by $q(M) = (\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (R,M))_{R \in \mathcal {X}}$ . Then p and q are equivalent invariants. In particular, any invariant that is either homological or a dim-hom invariant relative to $\mathcal {X}$ is both homological and a dim-hom invariant relative to $\mathcal {X}$ .

Proof Let $M, N \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ . It follows from Proposition 4.21 that if $p(M) = p(N)$ , then $q(M) = q(N)$ . Thus, suppose $q(M) = q(N)$ . By Propositions 4.13 and 4.16, this implies that $[\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (T,M)] = [\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_\Lambda (T,N)]$ in $K_0(\Gamma )$ . Proposition 4.19 then implies that $p(M) = p(N)$ and that p is a homological invariant.

Remark 4.23 This result points toward the possibility that all homological invariants are dim-hom invariants. Indeed, if we replace the finiteness condition (2)(b) in Definition 4.12 with the condition that the global dimension of $\Gamma _{\mathcal {X}}$ is finite, this would follow from Theorem 4.22. As we suggest in Remark 4.20(2), we suspect that the two finiteness conditions are equivalent, and thus that all homological invariants are in fact dim-hom invariants.

5 Classes and morphisms of spread modules

We now return to the realm of persistence modules over a finite poset $\mathcal {P}$ , or equivalently to modules over the incidence algebra $I(\mathcal {P})$ . We recall the definition and notation of spread modules from Section 2.1. We start by focusing on single-source spread modules and the link between persistence and morphisms from such modules. We then characterize the $I(\mathcal {P})$ -linear maps between arbitrary spread modules.

5.1 Single-source spreads

The single-source spread modules defined in Section 2.1 are particularly relevant for persistence theory. To be precise, take an arbitrary module $M \in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ , some vector $v\in M(a)$ , and consider the set of vertices where v persists:

$$ \begin{align*}X(v)=\{x\in \mathcal{P} | \; M(a,x)(v)\neq 0\}.\end{align*} $$

We observe that $X(v)$ is precisely a single-source spread. The following proposition thus ties the notions of morphism and persistence together.

Proposition 5.1 Let $M \in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ , and let $[a,B] \subseteq \mathcal {P}$ be a single source spread. Then, for $v \in M(a)$ , the map $M_{[a,B]}(a)\ni 1_K\mapsto v$ induces a morphism $M_{[a,B]}\to M$ if and only if $[a,B]\supseteq X(v)$ . Moreover, the single-source spread module $M_{X(v)}$ is isomorphic to the image of the map $P_a\to M$ , induced by $P_a(a)\ni 1_K\mapsto v$ .

Proof If the map $M_{[a,B]}(a)\ni 1_K\mapsto v$ induces a morphism $f:M_{[a,B]}\to M$ , then for each vertex $x\in [a,B]$ , $f_x\circ M_{[a,B]}(a,x)(1_K)=M(a,x)(v)$ . In particular, if $x\in X(v)$ , $f_x$ cannot be zero, so its domain cannot be zero. Then $[a,B]\supseteq X(v)$ . Conversely, if this containment is respected, the described map is indeed a morphism.

Now, recall that $P_a$ , the indecomposable projective module at a, is isomorphic to $M_{[a,\infty ]}$ . Clearly, $X(v)\subseteq [a,\infty ]$ , so the map $P_a(a)\ni 1_K\mapsto v$ induces a morphism $g:P_a\to M$ . By definition, $g_x\neq 0$ if and only if $x\in X(v)$ . This means that $\text {im}(g)$ is a thin module of support $X(v)$ . By taking $f_x(1_K)$ as the basis vector for the image at each vertex x, we get

$$\begin{align*}\text{im}(g)(x,y)= \begin{cases} 1_K, & \text{ if } x,y\in X(v),\\ 0, & \text{otherwise.} \end{cases} \end{align*}$$

So $\text {im}(g)\simeq M_{X(v)}$ as expected.

Single-source spread modules also admit other characterizations.

Proposition 5.2 Let $M\in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ . Then the following are equivalent.

  1. (1) M is a single-source spread module.

  2. (2) There exist an indecomposable projective $P \in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ and a (possibly empty) set $\mathcal {Q}$ of proper projective submodules of P such that $M \simeq P/(\sum _{Q \in \mathcal {Q}}Q).$

  3. (3) The projective cover of M is indecomposable.

Proof We first note that given $a, b \in \mathcal {P}$ , we have that $P_b \subseteq P_a$ if and only if $a \leq b$ .

(1 $\implies $ 2): Write $M = M_{[a,B]}$ . Define

$$ \begin{align*}B' = \{x\mid x> a, \ x \not\leq B, \text{ and }\forall y \in \mathcal{P}: y < x \implies y \leq B\}.\end{align*} $$

That is, $B'$ consists of those elements of $\mathcal {P}$ which cover elements of $[a,B]$ , but do not themselves lie in $[a,B]$ . We conclude that $P_x \subset P_a$ for all $x \in B'$ . Moreover, we have $M_{[a,B]} \simeq P_a/(\sum _{x \in B'} P_x)$ .

(2 $\implies $ 3): Under the assumption of (2), the projective cover of M is the quotient map $P\rightarrow M$ .

(3 $\implies $ 1): Let $p: P \rightarrow M$ be the projective cover of M. By assumption, there exists $a \in \mathcal {P}$ such that $P = P_a$ . In particular, we have $\dim P_a(x) \leq 1$ for all $x \in \mathcal {P}$ . Now, let B be the set of elements which are maximal in

$$ \begin{align*}\{x \in \mathcal{P} \mid P_a(x) \neq 0 \text{ and } (\ker p)(x) = 0\}.\end{align*} $$

It is clear that B is a set of incomparable elements of $\mathcal {P}$ and that $M \simeq M_{[a,B]}$ . This completes the proof.

Remark 5.3 In the setup of Proposition 5.2(2), those single-source spread modules which satisfy $|\mathcal {Q}| \leq 1$ play a key role in the description of the rank invariant via an exact structure given in [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO]. We discuss this special case further in Section 7.2.

5.2 Morphisms between spread modules

We now turn our attention toward computing the Hom-spaces between spread modules. We begin with an example.

Example 5.4 Let $\mathcal {P} = \{1,2,3,4,5\}\times \{1,2,3\}$ be the $3\times 5$ grid. We will denote elements of $\mathcal {P}$ using concatenation rather than ordered pairs, e.g., 13 will be used in place of $(1,3)$ . Consider the spreads $[\{13,41\},43]$ (drawn below in dashed red) and $[11,\{23,51\}]$ (drawn below in dotted blue).

We want to compute the space of morphisms between the spread representations $M := M_{[\{13,41\},43]}$ and $N := M_{[11,\{23,51\}]}$ . Since the supports of M and N only intersect at $13, 23$ , and $41$ , any $f: M_{[\{13,41\},43]} \rightarrow M_{[11,\{23,51\}]}$ must satisfy $f_v = 0$ for $v \notin \{13,23,41\}$ . We then have a pair of commutative diagrams:

These diagrams imply that $f_{13} = f_{23}$ and that $f_{41} = 0$ . Thus, choosing a morphism $f:M \rightarrow N$ is equivalent to choosing a scalar $\lambda \in K$ and setting $f_{13}(1) = \lambda $ . So, $\text {Hom} \left (M_{[\{13,41\},43]},M_{[11,\{23,51\}]}\right )\simeq K$ .

Generalizing this example, we have the following explicit description of the Hom-space between spread modules. See also [Reference MillerMil, Proposition 3.10].

Proposition 5.5 Let $[A,B]$ and $[C,D]$ be spreads. Denote by $X_1,\ldots ,X_n$ the connected components of $[A,B] \cap [C,D]$ which satisfy

(⋆) $$ \begin{align} \{a\in A \; | a\leq X_i \} \subseteq X_i \text{ and } \{d \in D \; | \; X_i \leq d\} \subseteq X_i.\end{align} $$

Then there are inverse isomorphisms $\Phi : K^n \rightleftarrows \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[A,B]},M_{[C,D]}): \Psi $ given as follows.

  • Let $(\lambda _1,\ldots ,\lambda _n) \in K^n$ . We identify each $\lambda _i$ with the linear map $K \rightarrow K$ given as scalar multiplication by $\lambda _i$ . Then, for each $x \in \mathcal {P}$ , set

    $$ \begin{align*}\Phi(\lambda_1,\ldots,\lambda_n)_x = \begin{cases} \lambda_i, & x \in X_i,\\0, & \text{otherwise.}\end{cases}\end{align*} $$
  • For each i, choose some $x_i \in X_i$ . Then, for $f \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[A,B]},M_{[C,D]})$ , set

    $$ \begin{align*}\Psi(f) = (f_{x_1}(1),\ldots,f_{x_n}(1)).\end{align*} $$

Proof We will first show that $\Psi $ is well defined. Let $f: M_{[A,B]}\rightarrow M_{[C,D]}$ , and let $x, y \in \mathcal {P}$ lie in the same connected component Y of $[A,B] \cap [C,D]$ . Then x and y are connected by a path in the Hasse quiver of Y. Moreover, if $x \leq z \in Y$ , then $M_{[A,B]}(x,z) = 1_K = M_{[C,D]}(x,z)$ . These two observations together imply that $f_x = f_y$ , and therefore $\Psi $ is well defined.

We will next show that $\Psi $ is injective. Let $f: M_{[A,B]}\rightarrow M_{[C,D]}$ , and suppose $\Psi (f) \,{=}\, 0$ . We wish to show that $f = 0$ , or equivalently that $f_x = 0$ for $x \notin \bigcup _{i = 1}^n X_i$ . This is clear if $x \notin [A,B]$ or $x \notin [C,D]$ ; thus, assume that $x \in [A,B] \cap [C,D]$ . By assumption, the connected component Y containing x does not satisfy ( $\star $ ). We then have two cases to consider. Suppose first that there exists $a \in A$ with $a \leq Y$ and $a \notin Y$ . Then there exists $y \in Y$ with $a \leq y$ . By the previous paragraph, this means $f_a = f_y = f_x$ . However, we cannot have $a \in [C,D]$ , because otherwise the interval $[a,y]$ would be contained in Y. We conclude that $f_x = 0$ . The case where there exists $d \in D$ with $Y \leq d$ and $d \notin Y$ is analogous.

We will now show that $\Phi $ is well defined. Let $(\lambda _1,\ldots ,\lambda _n) \in K^n$ . Obviously, $\Phi (\lambda _1,\ldots ,\lambda _n)$ satisfies the morphism condition within each connected component of $[A,B] \cap [C,D]$ . The only other morphism conditions to check are at the boundaries of the components $X_1,\ldots ,X_n$ . Since these components satisfy ( $\star $ ), there is no diagram of either of the following shapes:

Therefore, the only patterns that could make the morphism condition fail never happen. We conclude that $\Phi (\lambda _1,\ldots ,\lambda _n)$ is well defined.

It is clear that $\Psi \circ \Phi $ is the identity on $K^n$ . In particular, this means $\Psi $ is surjective. Since we have already shown that $\Psi $ is injective, we conclude that $\Psi $ is an isomorphism with inverse $\Phi $ .

To conclude this section, we tabulate several consequences of Proposition 5.5.

Corollary 5.6 Let $[A,B]$ be a connected spread. Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[A,B]},M_{[A,B]})= K$ . In particular, $M_{[A,B]}$ is indecomposable.

Proof The result is a direct consequence of the previous proposition, taking $[A,B] = [C,D]$ . Since the intersection of $[A,B]$ with itself is again itself, it is a single connected component. Since $A,B\subseteq [A,B]$ , it clearly verifies both conditions of ( $\star $ ).

Corollary 5.7 Let $[A,B]$ and $[C,D]$ be spreads and suppose that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[A,B]},M_{[C,D]}) \neq 0$ . Then there exist $a \in A, b \in B, c \in C$ , and $d \in D$ such that $c \leq a \leq d \leq b$ .

Proof By Proposition 5.5, there exists a connected component X which satisfies ( $\star $ ). Then there exist $a \in A \cap X$ and $d \in D\cap X$ such that $a \leq d$ . Moreover, since $a \in X \subseteq [C,D]$ , there exists $c \in C$ with $c \leq a$ . Likewise, since $d \in X \subseteq [A,B]$ , there exists $b \in B$ with $d \leq b$ . This proves the result.

As a corollary, we also directly get the following characterization of morphism between intervals, as is well known for type A quivers.

Corollary 5.8 There exists a nonzero morphism from $M_{[a,b]}$ to $M_{[c,d]}$ if and only if $c\leq a\leq d\leq b$ . In this case, Hom $(M_{[a,b]},M_{[c,d]})=K$ .

Proof It follows directly from Corollary 5.7 and Proposition 5.5.

Next, we show the following necessary conditions to have nonzero morphisms between spreads of the same type, which will be crucial to show Theorem 6.2. We note that Lemma 5.9(2) is an immediate consequence of [Reference MillerMil, Proposition 3.10], but we provide a proof here for the convenience of the reader.

Lemma 5.9

  1. (1) Let $[a, B]$ and $[c,D]$ be single-source spreads. Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[a,B]},M_{[c,D]}) \neq 0$ implies either $c<a$ or $c=a$ and $[c,D]\subseteq [a,B]$ .

  2. (2) Let $[A, \infty ]$ and $[B,\infty ]$ be connected upsets. Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}} (M_{[A,\infty ]},M_{[B,\infty ]})\neq 0$ implies $[A,\infty ]\subseteq [B,\infty ]$ .

Proof (1) Suppose $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[a,B]},M_{[c,D]}) \neq 0$ . By Corollary 5.7, we have $c \leq a$ . Thus, suppose $c = a$ . It follows that $X:= [a,B] \cap [c,D]$ is connected and must therefore satisfy ( $\star $ ). It is clear that $c \in X$ , so it remains only to show that $D \subseteq X$ . Since $c \in X$ and $c \leq d$ for all $d \in D$ , we have $\{d\in D| X \leq d\}= D$ . As X verifies ( $\star $ ), we thus have $D\leq X\leq B$ . So, $D\leq B$ , and $[c,D]\subseteq [a,B]$ .

(2) We prove the contrapositive. Suppose $[A,\infty ] \not \subseteq [B,\infty ]$ , and let $f: M_{[A,\infty ]} \rightarrow B_{[B,\infty ]}$ be a morphism. Because $[A,\infty ]$ and $[B,\infty ]$ are upsets, the assumption that $[A, \infty ] \not \subseteq [B,\infty ]$ means there exists $c \in A \setminus [B,\infty ]$ . In particular, we have $f_c = 0$ . Now, let $a \in A$ be arbitrary. Since $[A,\infty ]$ is connected, it follows that there exists a finite set $\{x_0,\ldots ,x_k\} \subseteq [A,\infty ]$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}c = x_0 \leq x_1 \geq x_2 \leq \cdots \geq x_k = a.\end{align*} $$

It follows by induction that $f_{x_i} = 0$ for each $x_i$ . In particular, we have that $f_a = 0$ for all $a \in A$ . By Proposition 5.5, we conclude that $f = 0$ .

Finally, Proposition 5.5 can be used to show the following generalization of the well-known fact that irreducible morphisms (in the traditional sense) are either monomorphisms or epimorphisms (see, for example, [Reference Auslander, Reiten and SmaløARS95, Lemma 5.1]). Our proof follows similar arguments to the traditional case, which arise as a special case of the following by setting $\mathrm {add}(X)= \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ .

Proposition 5.10 Suppose that $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ is closed under images in the sense that if $g: R\rightarrow R'$ with $R, R' \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ , then $g(R) \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ . Let $f: M_{[A,B]} \rightarrow M_{[C,D]}$ be an $\mathcal {X}$ -irreducible morphism. Then f is either a monomorphism or an epimorphism. In particular, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[A,B]},M_{[C,D]})\simeq K$ and either $[A,B]\subseteq [C,D]$ or $[C,D]\subseteq [A,B]$ .

Proof Consider the factorization $M_{[A,B]} \twoheadrightarrow f(M_{[A,B]}) \hookrightarrow M_{[C,D]}$ of f. By assumption, we have $f(M_{[A,B]}) \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ . If the quotient map $M_{[A,B]} \twoheadrightarrow f(M_{[A,B]})$ is a section, then f is a monomorphism. If it is not, the inclusion map $f(M_{[A,B]}) \hookrightarrow M_{[C,D]}$ must be a retraction. In this case f, is an epimorphism.

If f is a monomorphism, then $[A,B] \subseteq [C,D]$ since these are the supports of $M_{[A,B]}$ and $M_{[C,D]}$ , respectively. Proposition 5.5 then implies that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[A,B]},M_{[C,D]}) \simeq K$ . The case where f is an epimorphism is completely analogous.

Remark 5.11 We note that if we remove the assumption that $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ is closed under images, then there may be $\mathcal {X}$ -irreducible morphisms which are neither mono nor epi. For example, in the setting of Example 5.4, take $\mathcal {X}$ to be the set consisting of M, N, and the indecomposable projectives. Then any nonzero morphism $M \rightarrow N$ is an $\mathcal {X}$ -irreducible morphism, but is neither mono nor epi.

6 Homological invariants in persistence theory

In this section, we use the spread modules discussed in Section 5 to describe examples of homological invariants for persistence modules over some incidence algebra $I(\mathcal {P})$ . More precisely, we first use the theory of projectivization from Section 4.3 to provide sufficient conditions for a set $\mathcal {X}$ of spread modules to give rise to a homological invariant. We then use these conditions to prove Theorem 1.2 as Theorem 6.2. In particular, this theorem yields many concrete examples of homological invariants. Finally, we discuss how our theoretical framework gives an algorithm to compute them. Proposition 6.7 gives a way to optimize such an algorithm for certain choices of $\mathcal {X}$ . It can also be used to extend the reach of this theory to posets that are not finite.

6.1 Homological invariants

We now turn our attention to showing that many interesting sets of spread modules give rise to endomorphism algebras of finite global dimension, and thus homological invariants. The basis for these results is the following well-known lemma. Note that this lemma holds more generally, but we have stated it in the generality of the other results of this section. Thus, for the duration of this section, $\mathcal {X}$ denotes an arbitrary set of spread modules which contains the indecomposable projectives.

Lemma 6.1 If the transitive closure of the relation $X \rightarrow Y$ whenever ${\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(X,Y)\neq 0}$ is a partial order on $\mathcal {X}$ , then the endomorphism algebra $\Gamma = \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(T)^{op}$ has finite global dimension.

Proof Let Q be the Gabriel quiver of $\Gamma = \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(T)^{op}$ . By the discussion following Definition 4.15, there is a directed path from X to Y in Q if and only if there is a sequence of nonzero morphisms

$$ \begin{align*}Y = Z_0 \xrightarrow{f_1} Z_1 \xrightarrow{f_2} \cdots \xrightarrow{f_m} Z_m = X\end{align*} $$

with each $Z_i \in \mathcal {X}$ . That is, if $\preceq $ denotes the transitive closure of $\rightarrow $ , then there is a directed path from X to Y if and only if $Y \preceq X$ . The assumption that $\preceq $ is a partial order then implies that the quiver Q contains no oriented cycles. It is well-known consequence that $\mathsf {gl.dim}\Gamma < \infty $ .

We are now prepared to prove our first main theorem.

Theorem 6.2 (Theorem 1.2)

Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a finite poset.

  1. (1) Let $\mathcal {X}$ be a set of single-source spread modules over $I(\mathcal {P})$ which contains the indecomposable projectives. Then the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {X})$ is a homological invariant.

  2. (2) Let $\mathcal {X}$ be a set of connected upset modules over $I(\mathcal {P})$ which contains the indecomposable projectives. Then the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {X})$ is a homological invariant.

Proof (1) Let $\mathcal {Q}$ be the poset of single-source spreads, ordered by inclusion. By Lemma 5.9(1), the transitive closure of the relation $M_{[a,B]}\rightarrow M_{[c,D]}$ whenever $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[a,B]},M_{[c,D]})\neq 0$ can be identified with a subposet of the lexicographical product $\mathcal {P}\otimes _{lex}\mathcal {Q}$ . The result then follows from Lemma 6.1 and Proposition 4.17.

(2) Let $\mathcal {U}$ be the set of upsets of $\mathcal {X}$ ordered by inclusion. By Lemma 5.9(2), the transitive closure of the relation $M_{[A,\infty ]}\to M_{[B,\infty ]}$ whenever $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M_{[A,\infty ]},M_{[B,\infty ]})\neq 0$ can be identified with a subposet of $\mathcal {U}$ . As with (1), the result then follows from Lemma 6.1 and Proposition 4.17.

Remark 6.3 The special case of Theorem 6.2(2) where $\mathcal {X}$ is the set of all connected upset modules can also be deduced from [Reference MillerMil, Theorem 6.12]. Indeed, over a finite poset, every (pfd) persistence module satisfies [Reference MillerMil, Definition 2.11]. Thus, condition (6) in [Reference MillerMil, Theorem 6.12] says precisely that the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $I(\mathcal {P})$ is not properly infinite.

In case $\mathcal {X}$ is the set of all single-source spread modules, we refer to the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {X})$ as the single-source homological spread invariant. We defer further discussion of this invariant, and others which fit into the framework of Theorem 6.2(1), to Section 7.

It is an interesting problem to characterize precisely which sets of spread modules yield homological invariants. Unfortunately, over arbitrary posets, we cannot hope for an extension of Theorem 6.2 to arbitrary choices of $\mathcal {X}$ , as the following example shows.

Example 6.4 Let $\mathcal {P}$ be the poset with Hasse diagram

Note that the incidence algebra $I(\mathcal {P})$ is in this case a path algebra of type $\widetilde {A}_5$ . Now, set

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{X} = \{\text{indecomposable projectives}\} \cup \{M_{[\{1,3\},\{5,6\}]}, M_{[\{1,2\},\{4,6\}]}, M_{[\{2,3\},\{4,5\}]}\}.\end{align*} $$

The Gabriel quiver of $\operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(T)^{op}$ is then

The oriented 3-cycle at the center of this quiver has the relation that the composition of any two arrows is 0. Moreover, the three oriented pentagons (for example, from $M_{\{[1,3\},\{5,6\}]}$ to $M_{[6,6]}$ ) all have commutativity relations. We claim that the global dimension of $\Gamma $ is infinite. To see this, given a spread module $M_{[A,B]} \in \mathcal {X}$ , we denote by $P_{[A,B]}$ the projective $\Gamma $ -module at the vertex labeled by $M_{[A,B]}$ . Now, let N be the indecomposable $\Gamma $ -module supported at the vertices labeled by $M_{[\{1,3\},\{5,6\}]}$ , $M_{[3,\{5,6\}]}$ , and $M_{[5,5]}$ . Then N has a minimal projective resolution

$$ \begin{align*}\cdots\rightarrow P_{[\{1,2\},\{4,6\}]}\rightarrow P_{[\{1,3\},\{5,6\}]}\rightarrow P_{[\{2,3\},\{4,5\}]}\rightarrow P_{[\{1,2\},\{4,6\}]}\rightarrow N\rightarrow 0.\end{align*} $$

Indeed, the kernel of the first map is the $\Gamma $ -module supported at the vertices labeled by $M_{[\{1,2\},\{4,6\}]}, M_{[1,\{4,6\}]}$ , and $M_{[6,6]}$ . The symmetry of the quiver then makes it clear that this will be the projective resolution of N.

In addition, we can see directly that the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $(\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {X}})$ is properly infinite. Indeed, the following is readily seen to be a minimal $\mathcal {X}$ -resolution of the spread representation $M_{[1,6]}$ :

$$ \begin{align*}\cdots\rightarrow M_{[\{1,2\},\{4,6\}]}\rightarrow M_{[\{1,3\},\{5,6\}]}\rightarrow M_{[\{2,3\},\{4,5\}]}\rightarrow M_{[\{1,2\},\{4,6\}]}\rightarrow M_{[1,6]}\rightarrow 0.\end{align*} $$

Note that there are connected spread modules which are not included in set $\mathcal {X}$ in Example 6.4. Thus, while Example 6.4 shows that we cannot fully generalize Theorem 1.2 to arbitrary sets of spread modules, one natural question is what happens when one asks that $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of all spread modules.

Question 6.5 Let $\mathcal {P}$ be an arbitrary finite poset, and let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of all connected spread modules. Is the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {X})$ a homological invariant?

Remark 6.6 After a preliminary version of this paper was posted on the arXiv, Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima, and Yoshiwaki provided a positive answer to Question 6.5 in [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYa]. Their proof is based on a result of Iyama [Reference IyamaIya03] (see also [Reference RingelRin10]) which shows that for any finite-dimensional algebra $\Lambda $ and any generator-cogenerator $T \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ , then there exists $T' \in \mathsf {mod}\Lambda $ such that (i) $\operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_\Lambda (T \oplus T')^{op}$ has finite global dimension and (ii) every indecomposable direct summand of $T'$ is a submodule of an indecomposable direct summand of T. The positive answer to Question 6.5 then comes from showing that if $\mathcal {X}$ is the set of all connected spreads, then every submodule of an object in $\mathcal {X}$ lies in $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ (see [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYa, Lemma 4.4]).

6.2 Algorithms and extensions to infinite posets

Proposition 4.17 can be leveraged into an algorithm for computing the value of the invariant $[M]_{\mathcal {X}}$ when $\Gamma $ has finite global dimension. Indeed, one can first compute a minimal projective resolution of the $\Gamma $ -module $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(T,M)$ . By Proposition 4.19, the class of M in the Grothendieck group can then be computed by alternating sum of the terms of this resolution. The advantage of this approach is that one avoids needing to compute an $\mathcal {X}$ -resolution directly in favor of the more straightforward process of computing a projective resolution.

Another way to help compute approximations more effectively is to reduce the size of $\mathcal {X}$ in function of the module we are approximating. In the following proposition, we show how this can be done when all quotients of the modules of $\mathcal {X}$ lie in $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ . We emphasize that this is different than saying $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ is closed under quotients. For example, if we take $\mathcal {X}$ to be the set of all single-source spread modules, then all nonzero quotients of the modules in $\mathcal {X}$ will lie in $\mathcal {X}$ (hence also in $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ ) by Proposition 5.2. On the other hand, the category $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ will not be closed under arbitrary quotients, as this would force $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X}) = \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ . Indeed, every module is a quotient of its projective cover, which will lie in $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ .

Proposition 6.7 Let M be an arbitrary $I(\mathcal {P})$ -module. Let $\mathcal {X}$ a set of spread modules and suppose that every quotient of a module in $\mathcal {X}$ lies in $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ . Denote $\mathcal {Y} = \{R \in \mathcal {X} \mid \mathrm {supp}(R) \subseteq \mathrm {supp}(M)\}$ . Then every $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation of M is also a $\mathcal {Y}$ -approximation. In particular, the minimal $\mathcal {X}$ -approximation of M is exactly the minimal $\mathcal {Y}$ -approximation of M.

Proof It suffices to show that all morphisms from $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ to M factor through morphisms from $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {Y})$ . Let $R \in \mathrm {add}(\mathcal {X})$ , that is, $R=R_1\oplus \cdots \oplus R_n$ for some $R_i\in \mathcal {X}$ , and take some morphism $f:R\to M$ . Then f admits a factorization of the form

$$ \begin{align*}R\rightarrow \bigoplus_{i = 1}^n f(R_i) \rightarrow \sum_{i = 1}^n f(R_i) = f(R)\hookrightarrow M.\end{align*} $$

As each $f(R_i)$ is a quotient of a module in $\mathcal {X}$ and satisfies $\mathrm {supp}(f(R_i)) \subseteq \mathrm {supp}(M)$ , this shows that f factors through $\mathrm {add}(\mathcal {Y})$ .

Remark 6.8 The previous proposition indicates that much of the theory introduced in this paper may be applicable to finite-dimensional representations of locally finite posets that are not necessarily finite. Note that here we are using finite-dimensional to mean that the total dimension is finite, not to mean pfd. In particular, such representations have finite support. Given an infinite set of finite-dimensional spread modules $\mathcal {X}$ , we can then use Proposition 6.7 to form $\mathcal {X}$ -approximations of arbitrary finite-dimensional representations. On the other hand, the indecomposable projective representations will generally not be finite-dimensional, and if $\mathcal {X}$ is infinite, then the module $T_{\mathcal {X}} = \bigoplus _{R \in \mathcal {X}}R$ will not be finite-dimensional either. Thus, the extent to which the rest of the paper applies to locally finite posets requires further investigation.

7 Examples and comparison to other invariants

In this section, we investigate the relation between our homological invariants and other invariants in persistence theory. It was already shown in Section 3 that the dimension vector is a homological invariant relative to the set of projective modules (see Proposition 4.13). We now investigate the barcode, the rank invariant, the generalized rank invariant, the signed barcode, and the generalized persistence diagrams of [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21].

7.1 The barcode

In this section, we assume that the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P} = (\mathcal {P}, \preceq )$ is Dynkin type A. More precisely, as a set we identify $\mathcal {P}$ with $\{1,2,\ldots ,|\mathcal {P}|\}$ . We denote by $\preceq $ the partial order defining $\mathcal {P}$ and by $\leq $ the standard linear order on $\mathcal {P} = \{1,2,\ldots ,|\mathcal {P}|\}$ . The assumption that the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ is Dynkin type A then amounts to the assumption that all cover relations in $\mathcal {P}$ are either of the form $i \preceq i + 1$ or $i + 1 \preceq i$ .

Under this setup, it is well known that the indecomposable $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules are precisely the connected spread modules. Moreover, the connected spreads under the order $\preceq $ correspond directly to the intervals under the order $\leq $ . For example, if the quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ is $1 \rightarrow 2 \leftarrow 3$ , it is common to identify the spread module $M_{[\{1,3\},2]}$ with the interval $[1,3]$ . More generally, let $F \simeq \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {P}|\choose 2}$ be the free abelian group generated by the closed intervals of $(\mathcal {P}, \leq )$ . Then the identification between indecomposable $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules and closed intervals of $(\mathcal {P}, \leq )$ induces an isomorphism ${\underline {\mathrm {bar}}:K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow F}$ . Given a persistence module $M \in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ , the data $\underline {\mathrm {bar}}[M]$ are often referred to as the barcode of M.

Proposition 7.1 Suppose that the Hasse quiver of $\mathcal {P}$ is Dynkin type A. Then the barcode $\displaystyle \underline {\mathrm {bar}}:K_0^{\mathrm{split}} \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {P}|\choose 2}$ is a homological invariant.

Proof Let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of all connected spread modules. By the above discussion, $\mathcal {X}$ is also the set of all indecomposable $I(\mathcal {P})$ -modules. This means the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P}))\rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {X})$ is an isomorphism, and is in particular equivalent to $\underline {\mathrm {bar}}$ . Thus, it remains only to show that the $\mathcal {X}$ -dimension of $I(\mathcal {P})$ is finite. To see this, let $T_{\mathcal {X}} = \bigoplus _{R \in \mathcal {X}}R$ . As $\mathcal {X}$ contains all indecomposable modules, $\operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_{I(\mathcal {P})}(T_{\mathcal {X}})^{\mathrm{op}}$ is the so-called Auslander algebra of $I(\mathcal {P})$ , which is known to have global dimension 2. The result thus follows immediately from Proposition 4.19.

7.2 The rank invariant

We return to $\mathcal {P}$ denoting an arbitrary finite poset.

Denote by F the free abelian group generated by the (closed) intervalsFootnote 4 of $\mathcal {P}$ . Then the rank invariant (equation (1.1)) can be considered as a map $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P}))\rightarrow F$ . It is shown in [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO, Theorem 2.5] that p is surjective, and is therefore an invariant in the sense of Definition 4.10. In order to show that this invariant is homological, we recall a special collection of single-source spreads following [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO]. We append an extra element $\infty $ to $\mathcal {P}$ , and we set $a < \infty $ for all $a\in \mathcal {P}$ . For any $a < b \in \mathcal {P}\cup \{\infty \}$ , the persistence module $N_{\langle a , b\langle }$ , defined by

$$ \begin{align*}N_{\langle a, b\langle}(c) = \begin{cases} K, & a \leq c \text{ and } b \not\leq c,\\0, & \text{otherwise,}\end{cases}\qquad \qquad N_{\langle a, b\langle}(c,d) = \begin{cases} 1_K, & N_{\langle a, b\langle}(c) = K = N_{\langle a, b\langle}(d)\\0, & \text{otherwise}\end{cases}\end{align*} $$

is called the hook module from a to b. Note that, if $b \neq \infty $ , then $N_{\langle a,b\langle }$ is precisely the quotient of the projective at a by the projective at b. Likewise, if $b = \infty $ , then $N_{\langle a,b\langle }$ is precisely the projective at a. In particular, hook modules are single source spread modules by Proposition 5.2.

One of the main results of [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO], specialized to finite posets and restated in the language of this paper, is the following.

Theorem 7.2 [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO, Theorems 4.4, 4.8, and 4.10]

Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a finite poset, and let $\mathcal {H}$ be the set of hook modules in $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ . Then the rank invariant is homological with respect to $\mathcal {H}$ .

For the convenience of the reader, we give a proof of this result using the language of our framework.

Proof We first note that the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {H})$ is homological as a consequence of Theorem 1.2(1) and the fact that every hook module is also a single-source spread module. In particular, this means that this quotient map is equivalent to the invariant $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow \mathbb {Z}^{|\mathcal {H}|}$ given by $p(M) = (\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(M,H))_{H \in \mathcal {H}}$ . It therefore suffices to show that the rank invariant is equivalent to p.

To see this, first let $N_{\langle a,b\langle } \in \mathcal {H}$ with $b \neq \infty $ , and let v be a nonzero vector in $N_{\langle a,b\langle }(a)$ . Then, for any $M \in \mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ , the morphisms from $N_{\langle a,b\langle }$ to M can be identified with the vectors in $\ker M(a,b)$ . Indeed, for $w \in M(a)$ , there is a morphism $f: N_{\langle a,b\langle } \rightarrow M$ with $f_a(v) = w$ if and only if $M(a,b)(w) = 0$ . As $N_{\langle a,\infty \langle } = P_a$ , this means the following all hold:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{rk}}(M(a,b)) &= \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(N_{\langle a,\infty\langle},M) - \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(N_{\langle a,b\langle},M),\\ \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(N_{\langle a,b\langle},M) &= \operatorname{\mathrm{rk}}(M(a,a)) - \operatorname{\mathrm{rk}}(M(a,b)),\\ \operatorname{\mathrm{rk}}(M(a,a)) &= \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(N_{\langle a,\infty\langle},M). \end{align*} $$

This shows that $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M)$ is determined by $p(M)$ and vice versa. Thus, $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}$ and p are equivalent invariants.

Remark 7.3 One consequence of this result, which is made explicit as part of [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO, Theorem 4.4], is that the exact sequences $0 \rightarrow L \rightarrow M \rightarrow N \rightarrow 0$ in $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {H}}$ are characterized by the property that $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M) = \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(L) + \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(N)$ . Said differently, the set of exact sequences on which $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(-)$ is additive form an exact structure, and this exact structure is precisely $\mathcal {E}_{\mathcal {H}}$ .

We are now ready to prove our second main theorem, which shows that the single-source spread invariant is finer than the rank invariant.

Theorem 7.4 (Theorem 1.3)

Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a finite poset. Then the single-source homological spread invariant is finer than the rank invariant on $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ . Moreover, these invariants are equivalent if and only if for all $a \in \mathcal {P}$ the upset $[a,\infty ]$ is totally ordered.

Proof Let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of single-source spread modules. Since $\mathcal {X}$ contains all of the hook modules in $\mathsf {mod}I(\mathcal {P})$ , it follows immediately from Lemma 4.11 and Theorem 7.2 that the single-source spread invariant is finer than the rank invariant.

Now, suppose that for all $a \in \mathcal {P}$ , the upset $[a,\infty ]$ is totally ordered. We claim that the interval modules, hook modules, and single-source spread modules all coincide. Indeed, suppose $[a,B]$ is a single-source spread. Then $[a,B] \subseteq [a,\infty ]$ is totally ordered, and so $B = \{b\}$ for some $b \in \mathcal {P}$ . In particular, $[a,B] = [a,b]$ is an interval. Now, if $[a,b] = [a,\infty ]$ , then $M_{[a,b]} = P_a$ is a hook module. Otherwise, the set $\mathcal {S} = \{x \in \mathcal {P} \mid b < x\}$ is nonempty and totally ordered. We can then write $M_{[a,b]} = N_{\langle a,\min (\mathcal {S})\langle }$ , which proves the claim. It then follows from Theorem 7.2 that the single-source spread invariant and the rank invariant are equivalent.

Finally, suppose that there exists $a \in \mathcal {P}$ such that the upset $\mathcal {Q}_a := \{x \in \mathcal {P} \mid a \leq x\}$ is not totally ordered. Choose two elements $b, c \in \mathcal {Q}_a$ which are incomparable. Without loss of generality, we can assume that $a \leq b$ and $a \leq c$ are both cover relations; that is, we can suppose that $[a,\{b,c\}] = \{a,b,c\}$ . Now, denote $M := M_{[a,b]} \oplus M_{[a,c]}$ and $M' := M_{[a,a]} \oplus M_{[a,\{b,c\}]}$ . As M and $M'$ are not isomorphic and are both direct sums of single-source spread modules, we have $[M]_{\mathcal {X}} \neq [M']_{\mathcal {X}}$ . On the other hand, we have $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M) = \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M')$ . This concludes the proof.

Remark 7.5 The hypotheses of Theorem 1.3 include the case where $\mathcal {P}$ is totally ordered, but are slightly more general. Indeed, we only require that for every $a \in \mathcal {P}$ , the upset $[a,\infty ]$ is totally ordered. Such subsets are sometimes called “principle upsets.” For example, consider the poset with Hasse quiver

The principle upsets of this poset are $\{1,2,4,5\}, \{2,4,5\}, \{3,4,5\}, \{4,5\}$ , and $\{5\}$ , all of which are totally ordered. Thus, the rank invariant and the homological spread invariant coincide for this particular poset.

In the spirit of the counterexample used to prove Theorem 7.4, we consider the following.

Example 7.6 Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a finite poset which contains a unique maximal element. Let $\mathcal {H}$ be the set of hook modules, and let $\mathcal {I}$ be the set of interval modules. Since $\mathcal {P}$ contains a unique maximal element, we note that $\mathcal {I}$ contains all of the indecomposable projectives. Since every interval is a single-source spread, the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P}))\rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {I})$ is therefore a homological invariant by Theorem 6.2(1). We also know that the quotient map $K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P}))\rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {H})$ is equivalent to the rank invariant and is also homological by Theorem 7.2.

These two invariants have the same rank (given by the number of pairs $a \leq b \in \mathcal {P}$ ), but are not equivalent. For example, let $\mathcal {P} = \{(0,0), (0,1), (1,0), (1,1)\}$ be the $2\times 2$ grid. We consider the modules

We note that $\underline {\mathrm {dim}}(M) = \underline {\mathrm {dim}}(M')$ and that $\underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M) = \underline {\mathrm {rk}}(M')$ . On the other hand, we see that M is a direct sum of interval modules, whereas $M'$ has an $\mathcal {I}$ -resolution

$$ \begin{align*}0 \rightarrow M_{[(1,1),(1,1)]} \rightarrow M_{[(0,0),(1,1)]}\oplus M_{[(0,0),(0,0)]} \rightarrow M' \rightarrow 0.\end{align*} $$

Since this resolution has a nonzero term in degree 1, this means that $[M]_{\mathcal {I}} \neq [M']_{\mathcal {I}}$ .

We conclude this section with a detailed explanation of why the signed barcode of [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO] and the homological invariant with respect to $\mathcal {I}$ are not equivalent.

Remark 7.7 Let $\mathcal {H}$ and $\mathcal {I}$ be as in Example 7.6. We denote by $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {H})$ and $q:K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {I})$ the two quotient maps. Now, recall that the signed barcode of a persistence module M is obtained in [Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO] by applying Möbius inversion to the classical rank invariant. The result is an invariant which is contained in $K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {I})$ and is equivalent to p. More explicitly, there is an isomorphism $\sigma :K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {H}) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {I})$ such that $\sigma \circ p(M)$ is the signed barcode of M. Asking whether the signed barcode and the homological invariant with respect to $\mathcal {I}$ are equivalent is then the same as asking whether $\sigma \circ p = q$ . However, if this equality were to hold, then we would have that p and q are equivalent, contradicting Example 7.6. In other words, there exists a persistence module M such that $[M]_{\mathcal {I}}$ and the signed barcode of M are not equivalent.

7.3 Generalized rank invariants

We conclude by discussing the generalizations of the rank invariant appearing in [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb, Reference Botnan, Oppermann and OudotBOO, Reference Kim and MémoliKM21]. Again $\mathcal {P}$ denotes an arbitrary finite poset in this section. Given a set $\mathcal {R}$ of connected spread modules, we recall the “ $\mathcal {R}$ -rank invariant” $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ from Section 3. We also recall that a “generalized persistence diagram” $\delta (-,\mathcal {R})$ can be obtained by applying Möbius inversion to the $\mathcal {R}$ -rank invariant. We emphasize that while $\delta (-,\mathcal {R})$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ are equivalent as invariants, $\delta (-,\mathcal {R})$ has the advantage of yielding a “signed approximation” of a given persistence module by the spreads in $\mathcal {R}$ .

To understand the connection between the $\mathcal {R}$ -rank invariants, dim-hom invariants, and homological invariants, we first consider the following example.

Proposition 7.8 Let $\mathcal {P} = \{1,2\} \times \{1,2,3\}$ be the $2\times 3$ grid. Let $\mathcal {R}$ be the set of connected spreads in $\mathcal {P}$ , and let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of connected spread modules over $I(\mathcal {P})$ . Then the generalized rank invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ is not a dim-hom invariant relative to $\mathcal {X}$ .

Proof Let M be the following module:

Over this poset, indecomposable modules are uniquely determined by their dimension vector. For example, we identify M with the vector $\begin {bmatrix}1 & 1 & 0\\1 & 2 & 1\end {bmatrix}$ .

Seeking a contradiction, we compute the “generalized persistence diagram” obtained by applying Möbius inversion to the invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R})$ . Following [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21, Proposition 3.19] or [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb, Definition 5.9], this yields

$$ \begin{align*}\delta(M,\mathcal{R}) = \begin{bmatrix}1&0&0\\1&1&1 \end{bmatrix} + \begin{bmatrix}1&1&0\\1&1&0 \end{bmatrix} + \begin{bmatrix}0&0&0\\0&1&0 \end{bmatrix} - \begin{bmatrix}1&0&0\\1&1&0 \end{bmatrix}.\end{align*} $$

Now, denote

$$ \begin{align*}N := M \oplus \begin{bmatrix}1&0&0\\1&1&0 \end{bmatrix},\qquad\qquad L := \begin{bmatrix}1&0&0\\1&1&1 \end{bmatrix} \oplus \begin{bmatrix}1&1&0\\1&1&0 \end{bmatrix} \oplus \begin{bmatrix}0&0&0\\0&1&0 \end{bmatrix}.\end{align*} $$

Recalling that $\delta (X,\mathcal {R}) = X$ whenever X is a direct sum of spread modules (see [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21, Theorem 3.14]), we conclude that $\delta (N,\mathcal {R}) = \delta (L,\mathcal {R})$ . On the other hand, denote $X = \begin {bmatrix} 1 & 0 & 0\\1 & 1 & 0\end {bmatrix}$ and observe that

$$ \begin{align*}\dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_{I(\mathcal{P})}(X,N) = 1, \qquad\qquad \dim\operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_{I(\mathcal{P})}(X,L) = 0.\end{align*} $$

Thus, the dim-hom invariant induced by $\mathcal {X}$ can distinguish N and L, whereas the invariant $\delta (-,\mathcal {R})$ cannot. Since the latter is equivalent to the generalized rank invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ , this proves the result.

Remark 7.9 Since this example is small, it is a coincidence that the signed approximation $\delta (M,\mathcal {R})$ preserves the values of $\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(-,M_{[A,B]})$ for $[A,B] \in \mathcal {R}$ . If one were to replace M with $\begin {bmatrix}1&2&1\\0&1&1\end {bmatrix}$ , the result would be an approximation which no longer preserves these values.

As an immediate consequence, we obtain the following.

Corollary 7.10 Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a poset in which the $2\times 3$ grid is embedded. Let $\mathcal {R}$ be the set of connected spreads in $\mathcal {P}$ , and let $\mathcal {X}$ be the set of connected spread modules over $I(\mathcal {P})$ . Then the generalized rank invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ is not a dim-hom invariant relative to $\mathcal {X}$ .

Proof All of the modules in the proof of Proposition 7.8 embed into persistence modules over the larger poset, and the computation is preserved by this embedding.

To summarize, let $\mathcal {P}, \mathcal {R}$ , and $\mathcal {X}$ be as in Corollary 7.10. We have shown that the generalized rank invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ , and thus also the signed barcode $\delta (-,\mathcal {R})$ , is not a dim-hom invariant relative to $\mathcal {X}$ . This choice of $\mathcal {X}$ is particularly natural (see Question 6.5). Indeed, if the quotient map $p: K_0^{\mathrm{split}}(I(\mathcal {P})) \rightarrow K_0(I(\mathcal {P}),\mathcal {X})$ is a homological invariant, then both p and $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ assign a persistence module M to a “signed approximation” of M by the set of spread modules. Corollary 7.10 would then imply that these approximations do not coincide, even if one allows for a change of basis.

While restricting $\mathcal {X}$ to be composed of only spread modules is a natural choice, it remains an open question whether the generalized rank invariant is either homological or a dim-hom invariant relative to some other set $\mathcal {Y}$ . We have shown with a brute-force calculation that this is not the case when $\mathcal {P}$ is the $2\times 3$ grid, which leads to the following conjecture.

Conjecture 7.11 Let $\mathcal {P}$ be a finite poset in which the $2\times 3$ grid is embedded, and let $\mathcal {R}$ be the set of connected spreads in $\mathcal {P}$ . Then the generalized rank invariant $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(-,\mathcal {R})$ is neither a homological invariant nor a dim-hom invariant (relative to any $\mathcal {Y})$ .

Acknowledgment

The authors are thankful to Rose-Line Baillargeon, Mickaël Buchet, Barbara Giunti, Denis Langford, Souheila Hassoun, Ezra Miller, Charles Paquette, Job D. Rock, Ralf Schiffler, and Luis Scoccola for their contributions to numerous discussions pertaining to this project. They are also thankful to an anonymous referee for their careful reading of this manuscript and suggestions for improvement.

Footnotes

This work was supported by the NSERC of Canada. A portion of this work was completed while E.J.H. was affiliated with the Norwegian University of Science and Technology (NTNU).

1 We recall that we are using the term “interval” in its classical order-theoretic sense. This is different from the definition used in [Reference Kim and MémoliKM21].

2 Note that X may be a connected poset even if it is not connected as a subset of $\mathcal {P}$ . For example, take $\mathcal {P} = \{0,1\}\times \{0,1\}$ . Then $X = \{(0,0), (1,1)\}$ is connected as a poset, but not as a subset of $\mathcal {P}$ .

3 To be precise, we note that the Möbius inversion procedures for the “corner-complete” and “sink-source” invariants of [Reference Asashiba, Escolar, Nakashima and YoshiwakiAENYb] are done using connected spreads. Since these invariants are both of the form $\operatorname {\mathrm {rk}}(M,\mathcal {R})$ for sets $\mathcal {R}$ which contain non-spreads, the Möbius inversion procedure described here would lead to a different result. Nevertheless, the resulting invariants would still be equivalent since Möbius inversion is an invertible procedure.

4 Recall that in this paper, intervals are always of the form $[a,b]$ for some $a, b \in \mathcal {P}$ .

References

Adachi, T., Iyama, O., and Reiten, I., $\tau$ -tilting theory . Compos. Math. 150(2014), 415452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asashiba, H., Buchet, M., Escolar, E. G., Nakashima, K., and Yoshiwaki, M., On interval decomposability of 2D persistence modules . Comput. Geom. 105–106(2022), 101879.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asashiba, H., Escolar, E. G., Nakashima, K., and Yoshiwaki, M., Approximation by interval-decomposables and interval resolutions of persistence modules. Preprint, 2022. arXiv:2207.03663 [math.RT]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asashiba, H., Escolar, E. G., Nakashima, K., and Yoshiwaki, M., On approximation of 2D persistence modules by interval-decomposables. Preprint, 2022. arXiv:1911.01637 [math.RT]10.1016/j.jaca.2023.100007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Assem, I., Simson, D., and Skowroński, A., Elements of the representation theory of associative algebras, volume 1: techniques of representation theory, London Mathematical Society Student Texts, 65, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Auslander, M., Reiten, I., and Smalø, S. O., Representation theory of Artin algebras, Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, 36, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Auslander, M. and Solberg, Ø., Relative homology and representation theory 1: relative homology and homologically finite subcategories . Comm. Algebra 21(1993), no. 9, 29953031.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barannikov, S., The framed Morse complex and its invariants. In: Arnold, V. I. (ed.), Singularities and bifurcations, Advances in Soviet Mathematics, 21, American Mathematical Society, Providence RI, 1994.Google Scholar
Betthauser, L., Bubenik, P., and Edwards, P. B., Graded persistence diagrams and persistence landscapes. Discrete Comput. Geom. 67(2022), 203230.10.1007/s00454-021-00316-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Botnan, M. and Crawley-Boevey, W., Decomposition of persistence modules . Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 148(2020), no. 11, 45814596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Botnan, M. B., Oppermann, S., and Oudot, S., Signed barcodes for multi-parameter persistence via rank decompositions and rank-exact resolutions. Preprint, 2022. arXiv:2107.06800 [math.AT]Google Scholar
Brüstle, T., Hassoun, S., Langford, D., and Roy, S., Reduction of exact structures. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 224(2020), no. 4, 106212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bubenik, P. and Elchesen, A., Virtual persistence diagrams, signed measures, Wasserstein distances, and Banach spaces. J. Appl. Comput. Topol. 6(2022), 429474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bubenik, P. and Milićević, N., Homological algebra for persistence modules. Found. Comput. Math. 21(2021), 12331278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bubenik, P. and Scott, J., Categorification of persistent homology. Discrete Comput. Geom. 51(2014), 600627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bühler, T., On the algebraic foundations of bounded cohomology, Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, 214(1006), American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlsson, G. and Zomorodian, A., The theory of multidimensional persistence. Discrete Comput. Geom. 42(2009), 7193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chambers, E. and Letscher, D., Persistent homology over directed acyclic graphs. In: Chambers, E., Fasy, B., and Ziegelmeier, L. (eds.), Research in computational topology, Association for Women in Mathematics Series, 13, Springer, Cham, 2018.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crawley-Boevey, W., Decomposition of pointwise finite-dimensional persistence modules. J. Algebra Appl. 14(2015), no. 5, 1550066.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delfinado, C. J. A. and Edelsbrunner, H., An incremental algorithm for Betti numbers of simplicial complexes . In: SCG’93: proceedings of the ninth annual symposium on computational geometry, Association for Computing Machinery, New York, NY, 1993, pp. 232239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dey, T. K., Kim, W., and Mémoli, F., Computing generalized rank invariant for 2-parameter persistence modules via zigzag persistence and its applications. Preprint, 2022. arXiv:2111.15058 [math.AT]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dräxler, P., Reiten, I., Smalø, S. O., and Solberg, Ø., Exact categories and vector space categories. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 351(1999), 647682.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edelsbrunner, H., Letscher, D., and Zomorodian, A., Topological persistence and simplification. Discrete Comput. Geom. 28(2002), 511533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enochs, E. E. and Jenda, O. M. G., Relative homological algebra, De Gruyter Expositions in Mathematics, 30, De Gruyter, Berlin, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Escolar, E. G. and Hiraoka, Y., Persistence modules on commutative ladders of finite type. Discrete Comput. Geom. 55(2016), no. 1, 100157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fomin, S. and Zelevinsky, A., Cluster algebras IV: coefficients . Compos. Math. 143(2007), 112164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frosini, P., A distance for similarity classes of submanifolds of a Euclidean space. Bull. Aust. Math. Soc. 42(1990), 407416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giunti, B., Nolan, J. S., Otter, N., and Waas, L., Amplitudes on abelian categories. Preprint, 2021. arXiv:2107.09036 [math.AT]Google Scholar
Igusa, K., Rock, J. D., and Todorov, G., Continuous quivers of type  $A$ (I) foundations. Rend. Circ. Mat. Palermo (2) (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12215-021-00691-xGoogle Scholar
Iyama, O., Finiteness of representation dimension . Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 131(2003), no. 4, 10111014.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, B. and Krause, H., Tilting preserves finite global dimension. C. R. Math. Acad. Sci. Paris 358(2020), no. 5, 563570.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, W. and Mémoli, F., Generalized persistence diagrams for persistence modules over posets. J. Appl. Comput. Topol. 5(2021), 533581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, W. and Moore, S., The generalized persistence diagram encodes the bigraded Betti numbers. Preprint, 2022. arXiv:2111.02551 [math.AT]Google Scholar
King, A. D., Moduli of representations of finite dimensional algebra . Quart. J. Math. Oxford 2(1994), no. 45, 515530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krause, H., Homological theory of representations, Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, 195, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCleary, A. and Patel, A., Edit distance and persistence diagrams over lattices. SIAM J. Appl. Algebra Geom. 6(2022), no. 2, 134155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, E., Homological algebra of modules over posets. Preprint, 2020. arXiv:2008.00063 [math.AT]Google Scholar
Oudot, S., Persistence theory: from quiver representations to topological data analysis, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, 209, American Mathematical Society, Providence RI, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oudot, S. and Scoccola, L., On the stability of multigraded Betti numbers and Hilbert functions. Preprint, 2022. arXiv:2112.11901 [math.AT]Google Scholar
Patel, A., Generalized persistence diagrams. J. Appl. Comput. Topol. 1(2018), 123.Google Scholar
Ringel, C. M., Iyama’s finiteness theorem via strongly quasi-hereditary algebras . J. Pure Appl. Algebra 214(2010), no. 9, 16871692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robins, V., Towards computing homology from finite approximations . Topology Proc. 24(1999), 503532.Google Scholar
Simson, D., Linear representations of partially ordered sets and vector space categories, Algebra, Logic and Applications Series, 4, Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, Yverdon, Switzerland, 1992.Google Scholar
Stanley, R. P., Enumerative combinatorics. Vol. I, 2nd ed., Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, 49, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, A. L., Invariants and metrics for multiparameter persistent homology. Ph.D. thesis, Duke University, 2019.Google Scholar