Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-19T04:45:01.593Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Getting ready for primetime: Paths to acquiring substance-free phonology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 December 2022

Bridget D. Samuels*
Affiliation:
University of Southern California, Los Angeles, California, USA
Samuel Andersson*
Affiliation:
Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut, USA
Ollie Sayeed*
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, USA
Bert Vaux*
Affiliation:
Cambridge University, Cambridge, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Substance-free phonology (SFP) is based on the hypothesis that phonological computation makes no reference to phonetic substance, and that phonological features are treated as arbitrary symbols for the purposes of computation. However, phonologists within the SFP tradition disagree about whether the content of phonological features is innate or learned (“emergent”), and if learned, whether the acquisition process is based on phonological patterning alone or refers to phonetic substance. In the present article we identify predictive differences between these accounts. We conclude that there is an innate basis to phonological features, but that featural content is not innate. We suggest that a hybrid phonetic-phonological approach to feature content acquisition may ultimately be the most successful.

Résumé

Résumé

La phonologie sans substance (PSS) est basée sur l'hypothèse que le calcul phonologique ne fait aucune référence à la substance phonétique, et que les caractéristiques phonologiques sont traitées comme des symboles arbitraires pour les besoins du calcul. Cependant, les phonologues de la tradition PSS ne sont pas d'accord sur la question de savoir si le contenu des caractéristiques phonologiques est inné ou appris (« émergent »), et s'il est appris, si le processus d'acquisition est basé seulement sur le patterning phonologique ou s'il fait référence à la substance phonétique. Dans le présent travail, nous identifions des différences prédictives entre ces propositions. Nous concluons que les caractéristiques phonologiques ont une base innée, mais que le contenu phonétique n'est pas inné. Nous suggérons qu'une approche hybride phonétique-phonologique de l'acquisition du contenu des caractéristiques pourrait ultimement être la plus efficace.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Linguistic Association/Association canadienne de linguistique 2022

1. Introduction

In this article, we attempt to shed light on the question of how much of phonology is free of phonetic substance.Footnote 1 At its core, substance-free phonology (SFP)Footnote 2 is based on the hypothesis that phonological computation makes no reference to phonetic substance; phonological entities like features are treated as arbitrary symbols for the purposes of computation (Hale and Reiss Reference Hale and Reiss2000: 162). There remains widespread disagreement concerning whether phonological primes (features), too, are substance-free in their acquisition and/or their ultimate acquired state. As we see it, there are four possibilities, outlined in (1):

  1. (1) Feature acquisition decision tree

The traditional view in substanceful phonology, also held by some practitioners of SFP (e.g., Hale and Reiss Reference Hale and Reiss2008 et seq.), takes both the concept of phonological features and their content to be innate. On this view, children are born with a set of phonological features that map to certain acoustic and/or articulatory targets, and phonological acquisition involves learning which of these features are active in the child's target language(s). Innate features may be consistently transduced into phonetic content (see Volenec and Reiss Reference Volenec and Reiss2017 for a proposal). Alternatively, phonetics may be at least partly unpredictable on a language-specific basis, and therefore acquired (e.g., Keating Reference Keating1984). We discuss these possibilities in section 2.

Adopting SFP raises the possibility that the content of features may be acquired based on either phonetics, giving us sets of segments that share articulatory or acoustic properties, or on phonology, giving us sets of segments that pattern together in the language. This has sometimes been called the “emergentist” view (e.g., Mielke Reference Mielke2008). Acquiring featural content is a logical possibility only if the SFP hypothesis is correct, and no innate components of phonological computations refer to phonetic content; this approach is also motivated by a more generally minimalist view of the language faculty that attempts to eliminate redundancy while taking into account evolutionary plausibility (on implications for phonology, see Samuels Reference Samuels2011). Some works have posited that features are acquired purely on the basis of phonological patterning (e.g., Mayer and Daland Reference Mayer and Daland2019, Odden Reference Odden2022, in this issue); language-specific features constructed in such a manner are themselves substance-free and may not be transducible into coherently describable phonetic content. We call this the “phonological feature-learning” view. On the other hand, acquisition of features may be at least partly determined by their phonetic properties, such that features are ultimately transduced to phonetic content, though phonological computation may not be able to refer to that content. We call this the “phonetic feature-learning” view; see Lin (Reference Lin2005) and Mielke (Reference Mielke2012) for attempts to identify features via unsupervised clustering on acoustic and articulatory data. We discuss the phonological and phonetic feature-learning views in 3.1 and 3.2, respectively.

In the present article we point to a number of predictive differences between these accounts. We carefully consider both the philosophical and empirical arguments for and against the innatist view, focusing on data that could help decide between – or bring together – phonetic and phonological feature-learning accounts. We conclude that there is an innate basis to phonological features (including, at the very least, the concept of a feature), but that the content of features is not innate. Phonetic and phonological feature-learning approaches have different shortcomings, collectively and individually, and will need revision and augmentation to account for the range of attested data. We suggest that a feature-learning approach that takes phonetic information into account but allows phonology to overrule the phonetics may ultimately be the most successful.

2. The innatist view

Although a range of work has been done under the name ‘substance-free phonology’, there is disagreement within the substance-free literature concerning where substance does and does not appear in the process of acquiring a language. As noted in (1), to a first approximation, there are two schools of thought regarding the origin of phonological features: either they are innate, or they are learned. Innatists in the substance-free tradition could in principle permit language-specific phonetics, although we are not aware of any practitioners of SFP who do so.

The innatist position within SFP is perhaps best represented by the work of Mark Hale and Charles Reiss, who have argued for “the logical necessity of a discrete, innately available system for phonological representation” (Hale and Reiss Reference Hale and Reiss2008: ix). In later work by these authors and others, the mapping from phonological features to articulatory instructions is also taken to be innate and invariant across languages, so that there is no language-specific phonetics (Hale, Kissock and Reiss Reference Hale, Kissock and Reiss2007; Hale and Reiss Reference Hale and Reiss2008: 116-117; Volenec and Reiss Reference Volenec and Reiss2017, Reiss and Volenec Reference Reiss and Volenec2022, in this issue). The arguments for innate features and universal phonetics are explored in the rest of this section.

2.1 Card grammars and phonological grammars

The argument that innate features are a ‘logical necessity’ is illustrated in Hale and Reiss (Reference Hale and Reiss2003) by using toy languages involving playing cards. Consider a learner with only the innate feature [ᴅɪᴀᴍᴏɴᴅs], present for all and only diamonds, and otherwise absent. Below in (2) are some input cards, and the way that a learner with this impoverished feature system would parse them:

  1. (2) Toy card grammar

    Input  Parse by learner

    5 of diamonds  [ᴅɪᴀᴍᴏɴᴅs]

    King of diamonds  [ᴅɪᴀᴍᴏɴᴅs]

    7 of hearts  —-

    7 of spades  —-

Since the only feature available encodes suit, there is no representation of a card's value: both the 5 and the king of diamonds are assigned the same representation. Non-diamond cards are not parsed as linguistic information at all; Hale and Reiss (Reference Hale and Reiss2003, Reference Hale and Reiss2008) draw a comparison to the parse of a belch by the phonological system. Since many of these contrasts are not parsed, they can never be acquired, the argument goes. The learner can never begin to notice that the 5 and the king of diamonds are distinct cards, because their representational system provides no way of distinguishing them. Similarly, the learner can never acquire a distinction between hearts, spades, and clubs because noticing this difference is beyond the power of the learner's representations. Because of this, with card grammars as well as phonological grammars, all possible contrasts that languages can make must be available innately to the representational system.

Hale and Reiss (Reference Hale and Reiss2008: 116–117) point to a learnability problem for the idea that the phonetics-phonology interface may vary across languages if features are innate. Without knowing which feature a particular acoustic output comes from, there is no way of knowing what the surface form, or output of phonological computation, might be. Perhaps a vowel like mid-centralized /i̽/ is really targeted as [i] (with language-specific lowering and centralization) or [e] (with language-specific centralization), or [ɨ] (with language-specific lowering), and so on. Without knowing what the surface forms are, there is no way to set up an underlying form or any phonological processes, and so phonological learning cannot progress. Taking this view to its extreme leads to the rejection of any language-specific phonetics. This entails that consistent phonetic differences between languages must be represented phonologically:

In our view, for example, the recurrent difference in pronunciation of English [i] and German [i] is to be attributed to representational (featural) differences present in I-languages of English and German speakers, not to language-specific phonetics. In general, our position is that all recurrent or linguistically relevant differences in pronunciation result from representational differences in the lexicon and from differences in the phonological rule component. (Volenec and Reiss Reference Volenec and Reiss2017: 272)

Having summarized two important parts of the innatist view from SFP – innate representational primes and universal phonetics – we now discuss several arguments against this position. In section 3 we present alternatives.

2.2 The card grammar argument does not preclude feature learning

We propose that phonological features build on innate infrastructure, but that their content is not itself innate. In other words, we agree with the position set forth in 2.1 that innate representational primitives are necessary for learners to begin learning a phonological system, but we contend that these primitives are not phonological features. The possibility that there are “more basic primitives at the initial state” is raised by Hale and Reiss (Reference Hale and Reiss2008:37), who conclude that these initial primitives would still nevertheless be part of UG. Converging lines of evidence instead suggest to us that the initial primitives are (a) properties of the auditory system that are innate, but not exclusively phonological,Footnote 3 and (b) an evolutionary inheritance of (at least) the mammalian lineage, shared with animals that do not have phonology (see also Samuels Reference Samuels2011, Reference Samuels and Di Sciullo2012).

One of the strongest cases for an innate but pre-phonological psychoacoustic bias influencing phonological systems is the +20 ms voice onset time (VOT) boundary utilized by many languages. This is known as the positive auditory discontinuity, and represents a non-linear mapping between the acoustic input and the associated percept (Kuhl and Miller Reference Kuhl and Miller1975, Keating Reference Keating1984; see Holt et al. Reference Holt, Lotto and Diehl2004 for an overview). We are particularly sensitive to contrasts in both speech and non-speech stimuli that straddle auditory discontinuities; in other words, these psychoacoustic biases enhance our categorical perception. As Holt et al. (Reference Holt, Lotto and Diehl2004: 1763) put it, “[l]anguages may capitalize on regions of perceptual space where sensitivity is enhanced, adopting sounds for which moderate changes in articulatory or acoustic characteristics result in disproportionately large perceptual consequences”. The positive auditory discontinuity has been confirmed by many perceptual studies of VOT and its non-speech analogue, tone onset time (TOT), which can be defined as the temporal difference between the onset of low-frequency energy and the onset of higher-frequency energy (Hay Reference Hay2005). Even humans whose native languages do not include category boundaries at these discontinuities remain particularly sensitive to them (Williams Reference Williams1974, Streeter Reference Streeter1976, Hay Reference Hay2005). In experiments testing TOT discrimination, it was found that distributional boundaries coinciding with the +20 ms and −20 ms auditory discontinuities appear easier to learn than boundaries at +40 ms and −2.5 ms TOT, which do not coincide with discontinuities (Holt et al. Reference Holt, Lotto and Diehl2004). Enhanced sensitivity to these TOT values is already detectable in 2.5-month-old infants (Jusczyk et al. Reference Jusczyk, Pisoni, Walley and Murray1980).

The significance of these results for the question at hand is difficult to interpret: there are no truly ‘pre-linguistic’ infants, and the relationship between speech and non-speech auditory processing is not entirely clear.Footnote 4 For this reason, it's important to look to other species. Since the 1970s (e.g., Kuhl and Miller Reference Kuhl and Miller1975, Waters and Wilson Reference Waters and Wilson1976, Kuhl and Padden Reference Kuhl and Padden1982, Kluender et al. Reference Kluender, Diehl and Killeen1987, Dooling et al. Reference Dooling, Okanoya and Brown1989), studies on animals’ ability to perceive and categorize auditory stimuli, including their own acoustic communications and those of humans, have brought substantial evidence to bear on the question of whether speech is special in the way it is processed by our species. In their review of thirty years of literature in this area, Brown and Sinnott (Reference Brown, Sinnott, Greenberg and Ainsworth2006:198) concluded that “humans are not much more sensitive than other animals to differences between speech sounds” such that humans and other species perceived similar boundaries for 17 of 27 tested contrasts including ba-pa, ra-la, and ba-wa. Neuroimaging and psychoacoustic studies have shed further light on the temporal dynamics of auditory processing. Comparative studies of the acoustics of animal calls and human speech led Suga (Reference Suga1969, Reference Suga and Møller1973) to conclude that there are at least three basic acoustic elements shared across species – constant-frequency components, frequency-modulated components, and noise-burst components – and to hypothesize that these elements are recognized by specialized types of neurons. Distinct clusters of neurons in auditory cortex that respond to combinations of these properties have since been revealed in amphibians, birds, bats, and primates (see Suga Reference Suga, Greenberg and Ainsworth2006 and references therein). The picture that has emerged is one in which “the basic principles operating for processing species-specific complex sounds in amphibians, avians, and nonhuman mammals are greatly shared with the human auditory system for processing ‘speech sounds,’ and the human auditory system has developed highly specialized mechanisms for processing ‘speech’ from shared mechanisms” (Suga Reference Suga, Greenberg and Ainsworth2006:177). Suga's hypothesis is further supported by recent neurophysiological studies, such as that of Mesgarani et al. (Reference Mesgarani, David, Fritz and Shamma2008), who found that individual neurons in ferret auditory cortex are sensitive to important acoustic properties of human speech, such as specific frequency bands, formant transitions, broad-spectrum noise (as for frication), and rapid transitions between silence and noise (e.g., plosive release bursts). Phonological features may indeed find their basis in these shared sensitivities, but this does not entail that the features themselves are innate as such; these sensitivities are not themselves features, either (a point also made by Dresher Reference Dresher2009, Reference Dresher2014).

Taken together, these studies strongly suggest that phonological features and categories build on the sensitivities of an auditory system that is largely shared with other species. In Oudeyer's (Reference Oudeyer2006: 53) terms, this stance is nativist in a “morphoperceptual” sense: the neurophysiological and psychoacoustic building blocks of phonology are innate, but they evolutionarily pre-date human language.

The heart of the matter therefore lies in knowing what human specialization enables infants to go from categorizing sounds with the help of these sensitivities to having a full-fledged system of phonological features. This remains to be elucidated in more detail, but it likely involves warping the cortical perceptual map specifically for speech sounds, while maintaining access to the ‘un-warped’ map when perceiving non-speech (see Samuels Reference Samuels and Di Sciullo2012 for a more concrete proposal). We concur with Odden (Reference Odden2022, in this issue), and indeed with Hale and Reiss (Reference Hale and Reiss2008), that in addition to the properties of the auditory system outlined above, humans must be innately endowed with the formal concept of a phonological feature, as well as a syntax of features and the phonological computations over which they operate. It is only by virtue of having such innate architecture that we can make crosslinguistic predictions about what phonological processes look like (e.g., A → B / C__D, where A–D are feature bundles), or how phonological processes interact (e.g., through extrinsic ordering). To the extent that there are universals in these domains (see Vaux Reference Vaux, Vaux and Nevins2008 and Andersson (Reference Andersson2020) for typological advantages of serial rule-based theories), an innate architecture captures them most insightfully.

We depart from Hale and Reiss, however, in our contention that the language acquisition device must then acquire both the features and the language-specific nature of the computations. Although it may seem like a daunting task to construct a feature system, it is worth noting that we can construct new categories from highly variant acoustic input in non-linguistic situations. Think of Beethoven's 5th symphony, opening with its famous four-note motif — absent obvious pathology, we can recognize this piece played by different instruments, or in a different studio with different acoustics, or in a disco style, or in a different key, or at a different tempo, or on an untuned instrument, or with errors, and so on.

2.3 Consequences of innate transduction of features

In 2.1 we saw that the innatist view has been extended to transduction, so that the mapping between phonological feature bundles and articulatory instructions is taken to be invariant across languages. Volenec and Reiss (Reference Volenec and Reiss2017: 272) describe their position as “somewhat controversial”, and it has many consequences, especially when paired with a computational system which relies on “abstract, symbolic, discrete, timeless units” (Volenec and Reiss Reference Volenec and Reiss2020: 48). This section explores some of these consequences, and highlights areas where additional work is necessary. Odden (Reference Odden2022, in this issue) provides further insights into the cross-linguistic landscape.

As Volenec and Reiss (Reference Volenec and Reiss2017) note, in their theory there is necessarily a featural difference between German [i] and English [i], since there are consistent phonetic differences between the pronunciations of these surface forms in the two languages. However, they note that with three feature values (+, -, and unspecified) for 20 different features, we get 320, or roughly 3.5 billion, distinct segments. Even with a small number of features, then, we can describe large numbers of segments. However, this ignores the fact that the features and their transductions are meant to be innate. Consider [i] within the phonological system of German (3):

  1. (3) German monophthongs (reproduced from Kohler Reference Kohler1999: 87)

[i] is surrounded on almost all sides by other contrastive vowels, and so is presumably [+high] (to be distinct from [e]), [+ATR] (to be distinct from [ɪ]), and [-round] (to be distinct from [y]).Footnote 5 Although there is no [ɨ] in German, it is clear from the chart above that [i] is the most front vowel in the entire inventory, and so we treat it as [-back]. We disagree with Volenec and Reiss (Reference Volenec and Reiss2020: 55) who say that “there are many different feature sets (segments) that inhabit the ‘high front unrounded vowel’ space.” We have now used up all of the common features used to distinguish plain (non-nasal, non-creaky, etc.) vowels, and the result is only a single [i]. But there are millions of speakers of German! Accounting for minute dialectal variations from one town to the next would require at least several thousand [i]-like vowels, but a small (conventional) feature set gives us only one. What if we were to add all of the possible [i]-like vowels found across all speakers of all varieties of Germanic? We would likely need several million possible [i]-like vowels, all of which are representationally identical in current systems with 20 to 30 features.

The problem seen with German(ic) [i] can be extended to any phonetic contrast (see also Keating Reference Keating1984 for related arguments): a theory with invariant transduction would have to represent thousands of different laryngeal settings, thousands of ways of grooving one's tongue for a sibilant, and so on. The observation that 320 is a large number is largely irrelevant, since each segment is only represented by a tiny number of feature bundles within this large space. If we are to capture every possible segment as realized in every possible human language, we would need to be able to represent thousands of variants of each IPA symbol, unlike current theories where each IPA symbol has at most a handful of possible feature representations. If it is possible to do this with only a small number of features, it should be easy to write down the complete list of these features, along with the innate transductions of each feature to articulatory instructions. Such a proposal would then make concrete, falsifiable predictions, which could be tested by analyzing large sets of phonetic data on similar speech sounds across different languages.

We must also remember that much of the featural variation discussed above exists within individual speakers. We consider one example based on the Dutch rhotic below, but it must be emphasized that virtually any study of intraspeaker variation could have been used. Vieregge and Broeders (Reference Vieregge and Broeders1993) report on Dutch speakers’ realizations of the rhotic phoneme in different phonological environments. Their Speaker 5 uses at least 12 different realizations of the rhotic, and all of these can be found within a single phonological environment (the coda). Speaker 5's I-language would therefore need at least eleven optional rules to derive the eleven coda realizations which are not the underlying form.

Speaker 5's twelve realizations were all found in a sample of only 53 coda tokens. How many variants would exist if we considered 530 or 5,300 tokens?Footnote 6 And what if we considered all Dutch phonemes rather than just one, in all phonological environments? How many optional rules would be needed for a full grammar of Speaker 5? Given the range of intraspeaker variation, especially when fine phonetic detail is considered, it seems likely that the vast majority of rules in the vast majority of grammars would be optional.

Despite the huge importance of optionality under the innatist view, the current innatist substance-free literature talks only about categorical and obligatory rules manipulating discrete symbols. There are many possible analyses of optionality, each with empirical consequences (see Anttila Reference Anttila and Lacy2007 for an overview). For example, we could let features vary according to independent optional binary parameters, which would make strong predictions about how optional properties combine. For example, for all Dutch speakers who produce [r] (coronal trill), [ʀ] (uvular trill), and [ɹ] (coronal approximant), optional binary features predict that uvularity and approximance can also be combined to give [ʁ̞]. A speaker with only [r], [ʀ], and [ɹ] is predicted to be impossible. Is it true that no such speakers exist? What do other theories of optionality predict? Which approaches are empirically preferable to capture the many cases of intraspeaker variation from the previous decades of sociophonetic research? Carrying out these empirical studies on variation in phonetic detail strikes us as one of the key priorities for the innatist view, and we hope such work receives the attention it deserves in future literature from this perspective.

2.4 Evidence from non-speech modalities

In 2.4.1 we explore a case study from Gomera Spanish and its whistled equivalent, Silbo Gomero, in some detail. Our central argument is that there is only a single phonological grammar underlying both the spoken and whistled versions of this language. This means that some (I-)language-specific mapping must happen after the output of the phonology, to derive the divergent bodily outputs of spoken and whistled Spanish. We also show that the same phonetic contrasts can be put to different phonological use in speech and whistling, which we take to challenge the idea that there is a one-to-one mapping between phonetic properties and phonological features. The same argument could be made by considering other whistled languages, or by analyzing visual and tactile versions of sign languages. We also discuss, in 2.4.2, some of the challenges raised by sign languages for an innate feature system.

2.4.1 Whistled language

Gomera Spanish is the variety of Spanish spoken on La Gomera, one of the Canary Islands. On this small and mountainous island, a whistled language called Silbo Gomero is used to convey messages over longer distances than are possible with speech. Gomera Spanish and Silbo Gomero are not, however, different languages: it has been clear since the 19th century (Lajard Reference Lajard, Sebeok and Umiker-Sebeok1976) that they have the exact same lexicon, morphology, syntax, and so on, differing only in how the outputs of the grammar are realized. Moreover, the functional neuroimaging study by Carreiras et al. (Reference Carreiras, Lopez, Rivero and Corina2005) revealed that people proficient in Silbo Gomero, but not Spanish-speaking control subjects, showed activation of language-related cortical regions during passive listening as well as during active monitoring tasks in both whistled and spoken forms. This suggests that for whistlers, Silbo Gomero is processed as language, and that the mapping between speech and whistling is not something metalinguistic added on after ‘true’ linguistic processing.

Below in (4) are the phonemes of Gomera Spanish, and the corresponding ‘whistlemes’ of Silbo Gomero, along with their acoustic realizations. Note that Silbo Gomero has fewer contrasts than Gomera Spanish (see, e.g., Nevins Reference Nevins2015 on the reduction in vowel contrasts), although the set of contrastive units listed here is arguably too small, and additional distinctions may be made and sometimes perceived by some whistlers some of the time. We rely here on the minimal set of contrasts, which have high rates of recognition in perceptual experiments, and which are used in teaching of Silbo Gomero to local students (Classe Reference Classe1957, Trujillo Reference Trujillo1978, Meyer Reference Meyer2005, Rialland Reference Rialland2005).Footnote 7

  1. (4) Gomera Spanish and Silbo Gomero

    Silbo Gomero  Gomera Spanish  Silbo Gomero acoustic correlates (our symbols)

    /I/  /i, e/  Sustained higher pitch

    (roughly 2,000-2,500Hz)

    /A/  /a, o, u/  Sustained lower pitch

    (roughly 1,500Hz)

    /D/  /d, ɾ, r, l, n, ɲ, j, ʎ/  Rise-fall (whistled throughout)

    /T/  /t, s, t͡ʃ/  Rise-fall (middle portion silent)

    /B/  /b, m, ɡ/  Fall-rise (whistled throughout)

    /P/  /p, f, k, χ/  Fall-rise (middle portion silent)

The waveform and spectrogram below in (5), reproduced from Rialland (Reference Rialland, Solé, Recasens and Romero2003: 2133), show whistled /ABA/ on the left realized as a continuous fall-rise, and /APA/ on the right, with an interrupted fall-rise contour.

  1. (5) Whistled /ABA/ and /APA/ Figure from Rialland (Reference Rialland, Solé, Recasens and Romero2003: 2133), modified to highlight formants and to use the same transcription system as the rest of this article.

Collapsing 23 phonemes into six whistlemes naturally results in extensive homophony. For example, whistled /PATA/ may correspond to spoken /pata, pasa, pota, pot͡ʃo, kat͡ʃo/ and so on (Trujillo Reference Trujillo1978: 148).

Even with the heavily reduced inventory of Silbo Gomero, there is evidence that it shares a phonological grammar with Gomera Spanish. This is evident in processes applying in both speech and whistling, such as s-deletion and m-to-n, which apply in codas in Gomera Spanish. Below in (6) is a whistled and spoken example of s-deletion from Classe (Reference Classe1957), which shows up as T-deletion in Silbo Gomero. Classe (Reference Classe1957: 65) is explicit that all phonological processes “are maintained in the whistled form of Gomera Spanish.”

  1. (6) Gomera Spanish S-deletion corresponds to Silbo Gomero T-deletion

    Underlying form  Gomera Spanish  Silbo Gomero  Translation

    /as bisto/   [a βito], not  [A BITA], not  'you (sg.) have seen'

    [as bisto]  [AT BITTA]

The same morpheme may show up with or without an [s] depending on the phrasal environment: if a word-final /s/ is followed by a pause, it is deleted, but if the /s/ is followed by a vowel-initial word, it surfaces as [s] (Lipski Reference Lipski1985: 128). Below are examples containing word-final /s/ in deleting and non-deleting positions from the same whistler and the same utterance (audio from Wikimedia Commons 2006):

  1. (7) Word-final /s/ in Silbo Gomero

  1. a. Gomera Spanish /abises a/ [aβises a] ‘tell (to)’ whistled as [ABITIT A], with [T]

  2. b. Gomera Spanish /los mut͡ʃat͡ʃos/ [lo mut͡ʃat͡ʃo ] ‘the boys’ whistled as [DA BATATA], without [T]

We model this situation as follows:

  1. (8)

That is, the entire phonological grammar is the same for both varieties, as is suggested by the fact that all phonological processes are shared. The identical surface forms are then transduced in one of two different ways, to produce the articulatory instructions that result in speech and whistling respectively. This situation of having an identical phonology with non-identical phonetic outputs is not predicted by theories where the phonology-phonetics mapping is invariant. One way around this might be to posit separate transducers for spoken and whistled speech, but in an innatist model this would entail that every speaker has a whistling mode, even if they do not know a whistled language. Adding to the difficulty of sustaining this position, there are no attested languages that are only whistled, so whistling is not a full-fledged separate modality, unlike the independent visual modality of signed languages (anticipating the next subsection). Why should a separate, universal transducer and set of phonological primitives be posited for a modality that is always parasitic on the grammar of a spoken language?

A further problem with the innatist view can be illustrated with spoken and whistled featural mismatches, which are cases where both speech and whistling make use of the same phonetic contrast for different phonological purposes. Both Gomera Spanish and Silbo Gomero have phonemic contrasts based on continuancy. In Gomera Spanish, this is the familiar [continuant] feature, distinguishing the [+continuant] vowels, sonorants, and fricatives from the [-continuant] stops. In Silbo Gomero, the contrastive pairs /B/-/P/ and /D/-/T/ are only distinguished by continuancy. Both pairs share the same pitch movements, but while /B/ and /D/ involve continuous whistling, /P/ and /T/ contain a non-continuous period of silence in the middle, similar to the closure portion of a spoken stop (Trujillo Reference Trujillo1978, Rialland Reference Rialland2005). Despite this similarity in acoustic cues, whistled continuancy is unrelated to the [continuant] feature in speech, and instead maps onto spoken [voice], as noted by Rialland (Reference Rialland2005: 249). The whistled non-continuants represent all and only voiceless phonemes, whether continuous (/f, s, (t͡ʃ), χ/) or not (/p, t, (t͡ʃ), k/). Gomera Spanish and Silbo Gomero are phonologically the same language, and both use binary acoustic contrasts based on continuancy. If there were an invariant mapping between phonetic properties and phonological contrasts, both the whistled and spoken continuants would encode the same contrasts. Instead, there is a mismatch, where the same phonetic cue corresponds to different phonological categories. This suggests that there is no (I-)language-invariant correspondence between phonetic properties and phonological contrasts.

2.4.2 Sign language

The wealth of research on sign language phonological feature systems provides an interesting contrast to spoken language in several ways. Most pressingly for the current work, the hypothesis that there is an innate feature set with acoustic and/or articulatory correlates for spoken languages raises the question of how this feature set might pertain to signed languages. Mielke (Reference Mielke2008:16) raises three possibilities and provides several arguments, which we will review here in turn, rejecting the first two:

(1) relax the requirement that features are defined in phonetic terms and interpret each innate feature as having both spoken language and signed language phonetic correlates, (2) posit additional innate features which apply to signed language, and claim that humans are hardwired with two sets of innate features for two different modalities, or (3) consider that features and their phonetic correlates are learned during acquisition, according to the modality of the language being acquired.

The first possibility is compatible with an innatist view in which phonetics is language-specific such that a single feature may be transduced into different articulatory instructions, but not one in which transduction is invariant. If this were the case, we should see a strong correspondence between signed and spoken language features: they should be similar in number, and similar in feature geometric organization. Corina and Sagey (Reference Corina, Sagey, de Jong and No1989) reached the conclusion that this hypothesis is not borne out by studies of sign languages. For example, Stokoe et al. (Reference Stokoe, Casterline and Croneberg1976) propose 19 handshapes, 12 places of articulation, and 24 types of movement for ASL. Some models involve nearly 300 distinctive features (Liddell and Johnson Reference Liddell and Johnson1989) or employ features with more than two values (Brentari Reference Brentari and Lucas1990). Concurring with Corina and Sagey (Reference Corina, Sagey, de Jong and No1989), Sandler (Reference Sandler2014: 193) states that these feature sets “bear no relationship to those of spoken language.” Moreover, feature geometric models (i.e., feature hierarchies) for sign (e.g., Corina and Sagey Reference Corina, Sagey, de Jong and No1989, Sandler Reference Sandler2012) have little resemblance to those proposed for spoken languages. At the syllable level, too, there appear to be significant differences between sign and speech: there is “nearly complete consensus across models of sign language phonology (…) that movements are the nuclei of the syllable” (Brentari Reference Brentari, Goldsmith, Riggle and Yu2011: 695), but movement is generally predictable from the start and end locations of the syllable. Some feature models of sign languages therefore reject movement as a primitive, instead deriving it from the start and endpoints (Liddell and Johnson Reference Liddell and Johnson1989, van der Hulst Reference van der Hulst1993). This would be equivalent to a spoken language allowing only a single contrastive segment in the nucleus, which is clearly far from the norm in spoken languages. Due to the striking lack of similarity between spoken and signed languages, the possibility that they share a single feature system and differ only in phonetic implementation can be rejected.

Mielke (Reference Mielke2008) suggests that the second possibility seems unlikely from an evolutionary perspective, since deafness is relatively rare and sporadic, and all known sign languages are young; deaf communities were likely only established in the past few hundred years, and no hearing communities appear to use sign as their primary modality (Sandler Reference Sandler2012, Reference Sandler2014). The same would hold for tactile signs used by the deaf-blind, all the more so since there do not appear to be any languages that are exclusively conveyed in the tactile modality. As Sandler (Reference Sandler2014:184) puts it, “spoken language was evolution's choice”. Some researchers have suggested that language may find its evolutionary origins in gesture (e.g., Stokoe Reference Stokoe2002, Tomasello Reference Tomasello2008, Arbib Reference Arbib2012; see Kendon Reference Kendon2017 for a critical overview). However, none of these proposals go so far as to assume that these gestural proto-linguistic systems had duality of patterning, a necessary precondition for phonological features (Sandler Reference Sandler2014). To our knowledge, there are no supporters on record for the idea that sign language and spoken language have innate but distinct feature systems.

This leaves us with the third possibility, that phonological features of visual signed languages are acquired. It would seem to follow by the same logic that the phonological features of tactile signs and whistled languages would also be acquired. Put simply, if we can acquire features for these modalities, why not for speech? This seems to us to be the most likely origin of phonological features for sign, and as such provides support the position that features are learned for speech as well.

3. Learning features and ‘substance-freedom’

In substanceful theories of phonological computation, innate rules or constraints may refer to phonological features (as in most versions of Optimality Theory; see, e.g., Tesar and Smolensky Reference Tesar and Smolensky2000). Under such a conception of the language faculty, features must be innate. If phonological computation is substance-free, though, then there exists a logical possibility that features are acquired. In this view, not only are there no innate features, but the features learned by each child do not necessarily correspond to phonetic divisions of a language's phoneme inventory at all. Archangeli and Pulleyblank (Reference Archangeli and Pulleyblank2015: 2) describe these as “categories”: “these categories correspond roughly to the familiar ‘distinctive features,’ though there is no a priori set of features to map the sounds to, and in fact, a behavioral category is not necessarily an acoustic or articulatory category, and vice versa.”

3.1 Approaches to learning featural content

We turn now to the question of how such categories could be learned. As noted in (1), theories in which featural content is learned differ in whether substance is involved in acquisition of features (phonetic feature-learning) or not (phonological feature-learning). We review the evidence in favor of each of these views in the subsections to follow.

3.1.1 Arguments that featural content is learned from phonology

The phonological feature-learning view is perhaps best exemplified by Mielke's (Reference Mielke2004, Reference Mielke2008) emergent feature theory, Morén (Reference Morén2007), Nazarov (Reference Nazarov2014), and Odden (Reference Odden2022, in this issue). The main argument for the phonological feature-learning view is an empirical one, outlined by Mielke (Reference Mielke2004 et seq.). Mielke argues that the phonological systems of the world's languages relatively frequently need to refer to a phonetically ‘unnatural’ class as the target or environment of a phonological process. Out of 6,077 phonological classes in Mielke's database from 628 language varieties, 1,498 classes are unnatural according to all three of the most historically influential feature theories: those proposed by Preliminaries of Speech Analysis (Jakobson et al. Reference Jakobson, Fant and Halle1952), The Sound Pattern of English (SPE, Chomsky and Halle Reference Chomsky and Halle1968), and the more recent Unified Feature Theory (Clements and Hume Reference Clements, Hume and Goldsmith1995).

For example, in River West Tarangan (Nivens Reference Nivens, Burquest and Laidig1992: 219, Mielke Reference Mielke2008: 121), /m/ undergoes place assimilation to a following /t̪ ɡ s j/, but no other segments:

  1. (9) Place assimilation of /m/ in River West Tarangan

    • a. /bimtem/ → [bintém] ‘DUP small’

    • b. /jɛrɡimɡum/ → [jɛrɡiŋɡum] ‘DUP NF rub’

    • c. /simsimə/ → [sinsimə] ‘ant (sp)’

    • d. /ɸaɸamjɛmnə/ → [ɸaɸanjemnə] ‘overcast 3s’

    • e. /jɛrkimkam/ → [jɛrkimkam] ‘DUP NF dislike’

    • f. /dimdumdi/ → [dimdumdi] ‘DUP six PL’

These processes apply across morpheme boundaries, so must be productive in some part of the grammar. Given the consonant inventory of River West Tarangan, there is no combination of features in Jakobson et al. (Reference Jakobson, Fant and Halle1952), SPE, or Unified Feature Theory that could encode the set /t̪ ɡ s j/ as a phonological natural class:

  1. (10) River West Tarangan consonant inventory (Mielke Reference Mielke2008: 122)

         k

    b    d    ɡ

    ɸ    s

    m    n    ŋ

    r

    l

    j

There are a few possible responses to this set of data. One is to claim that there are no featurally unnatural phonologically active classes, and find other analyses of the phonemic inventory of the language to describe every unnatural-looking class featurally. The resulting feature may not have any identifiable acoustic or articulatory correlate. This would be a phonological feature-learning approach. We refer the reader to Odden (Reference Odden2022, in this issue) for a concrete proposal concerning how this learning would proceed.

A second response, which could be made in an attempt to salvage the innatist position, would be to argue that River West Tarangan has four separate rules, causing place assimilation of /m/ before /t̪/, before /ɡ/, before /s/, and before /j/. This potential analysis has some merit, given that assimilation is obligatory before /t̪/ but optional before /ɡ s j/ (Mielke Reference Mielke2008: 121); something special has to be said about the status of /t̪/, though notice that the class is featurally unnatural with or without this segment. Reiss (Reference Reiss, Hannahs and Bosch2017a) argues that children can only formulate rules that refer to the featural intersection of the segments that participate in the observed alternation. The four-rule analysis is thus unavailable; it is not a learning strategy provided by UG. However, in such a scenario the child must have some way to retreat from overgeneralizing and revert to multiple rules. Perhaps, upon realizing that feature intersection would predict the participation of other [+consonantal] segments known not to participate, the child avoids doing so.

In short, there is a decision to be made in light of languages like River West Tarangan: allow rules to proliferate, or allow features to be created. In light of the arguments presented in the previous section, we suggest the latter. This is also relevant to phonetic feature-learning approaches discussed below, which will need to permit the phonology to “override” the phonetics in these cases, as Dresher (Reference Dresher2018) puts it. Indeed, Sapir (Reference Sapir1925: 47–48) already noted that “it is most important to emphasize the fact, strange but indubitable, that a pattern alignment does not need to correspond exactly to the more obvious phonetic one.”Footnote 8

3.1.2 Differences among phonological feature-learning approaches

Few phonological feature-learning approaches have been explicated in sufficient detail to test their predictions, but one way of distinguishing between approaches such as Dresher's (Reference Dresher2014, Reference Dresher2018) and Odden's (Reference Odden2022, in this issue) lies in cases where non-contrastive features appear to be needed in the representation. Dresher (Reference Dresher2014: 166) states that “it is the learners’ task to arrive at a set of features that account for the contrasts in the lexical inventory (the phonemes) of their language.” As we understand Odden's approach, active features are first learned on the basis of phonological alternations, and non-active but contrastive features are filled in later. This may result in differing featural representations of segments and different geometric organizations of the features.

Pulleyblank (Reference Pulleyblank2003), Hall (Reference Hall2007), and Nevins (Reference Nevins2015) discuss a number of cases that pose a concern for contrast-based feature assignment, as formalized for instance in Hall's (Reference Hall2007: 20) Contrastivist Hypothesis, which states that “[t]he phonological component of a language L operates only on those features which are necessary to distinguish the phonemes of L from one another.” Rather than abandoning the hypothesis entirely, Hall proposes the ‘prophylactic’ assignment of non-contrastive features when necessary. We will illustrate the general nature of the argument with Czech, following Hall (Reference Hall2007: 40ff). Czech has final devoicing, as in (11):

  1. (11) Final devoicing in Czech (Hall Reference Hall2007)

    a.  muž    [muʃ]  ‘man’ (nom.sg)

    b.  mužem    [muʒem]  ‘man’ (inst.sg)

    c.  myš    [miʃ]  ‘mouse’ (nom.sg)

    d.  myši    [miʃi]  ‘mouse’ (inst.sg)

Czech also has regressive voicing assimilation in consonant clusters when the second member is an obstruent, both within words and across word boundaries. This can be demonstrated as in (12) with the prepositions /s/ ‘with’ and /z/ ‘from’.

  1. (12) Regressive voicing assimilation before obstruents, not sonorants

    a. s lesem  [slesem]  ‘with a forest’

    b. z lesa  [zlesa]  ‘from a forest’

    c. s mužem  [smuʒem]  ‘with a man’

    d. z muže  [zmuʒe]  ‘from a man’

    e. s domem  [zdomem]  ‘with a house’

    f. z domu  [zdomu]  ‘from a house’

    g. s polem  [spolem]  ‘with a field’

    h. z pole  [spole]  ‘from a field’

Two segments, /v/ and /r̝/, undergo final devoicing and regressive assimilation in these contexts, as is to be expected.

  1. (13) Final devoicing of /v/ and /r̝/

    a. zpěv  [spjef]  ‘song’ (nom.sg)

    b. zpěvem  [spjevem]  ‘song’ (inst.sg)

    c. barev  [baref]  ‘colors’ (gen.pl)

    d. barva  [barva]  ‘color’ (nom.sg)

    e. lékař  [le:kar̝̊]  ‘doctor’ (nom.sg)

    f. lékařem  [le:kar̝em]  ‘doctor’ (inst.sg)

  2. (14) Regressive assimilation of /v/ and /r̝/

    a. v lese  [vlese]  ‘in a forest’

    b. v pole  [fpole]  ‘in a field’

    c. v chybě  [fxibje]  ‘in a mistake’

    d. nářek  [na:r̝ek]  ‘lamentation’ (nom.sg)

    e. nářky  [na:r̝̊ki]  ‘lamentations’ (nom.pl.)

Interestingly, neither /v/ nor /r̝/ triggers voicing assimilation when it is the second segment in a consonant cluster, as demonstrated below. See Hall (Reference Hall2007) concerning dialectal variation, but for the present purposes, it will suffice to discuss dialects in which /v/ remains voiced but /r̝/ is voiceless if it is adjacent to a voiceless obstruent, as we have already seen in the previous examples.

  1. (15) Non-triggering of assimilatory voicing by /v/ and /r̝/

    a. s vránou  [svra:noʊ]  ‘with a crow’

    b. květ  [kvjet]  ‘flower’

    c. středa  [str̝̊eda]  ‘Wednesday’

    d. při  [pr̝̊i]  ‘near’

The problem is as follows: Hall adopts the Successive Division Algorithm (SDA), which begins by assuming that an early language learner “can perceive and distinguish speech sounds, but has not yet identified any contrasts” in the phonological system (Dresher Reference Dresher2014: 172). Thus, the learner begins with a single undifferentiated phoneme and then, upon finding a phonological contrast, “[assigns] contrastive features by successively dividing the inventory until every phoneme is distinguished” (Dresher Reference Dresher2014: 166; see Dresher Reference Dresher, Bhatia and Ritchie1998, Reference Dresher2009 for a more explicit algorithm). Thus, all and only the phonologically contrastive features are assigned, creating a language-specific, non-innate hierarchical organization. Hall (Reference Hall2007) argues that, in Czech, the SDA will produce a featural hierarchy like the one below (place features omitted for brevity):

  1. (16) Consonant inventory of Czech (reproduced from Samuels Reference Samuels2009: 58, following Hall Reference Hall2007: 82)

According to the feature geometry in (16), we can describe voicing assimilation as [Laryngeal] spreading leftward. The sonorants, including the “lapsed sonorant” or “sonorant obstruent” /v/ (Hall Reference Hall2007: 48, 54), are not specified with [Laryngeal] so they do not trigger this process. However, the [SV] (Sonorant or Spontaneous Voicing) feature of /v/ can be ‘overridden’ by [Laryngeal] and its dependent [Voice] spreading. Note also that [Laryngeal] is a phonological feature with no phonetic correlate: “the feature [Laryngeal] is associated not with any articulatory, auditory, or acoustic attribute of the sounds to which it is assigned”, but instead by its ability to trigger voicing assimilation (Hall Reference Hall2007: 56).

The problem is that /r̝/ does not bear either [Laryngeal] or [SV].Footnote 9 When /r̝/ is in a position to be devoiced, such that [Laryngeal] spreads onto it, the result should be that it turns into an obstruent specified only for [Laryngeal] and nothing else. This would not be /r̝̊/, because /r̝̊/ is not a phoneme. This analysis therefore incorrectly predicts that a devoiced /r̝/ should surface as some other phoneme, say /t/. Hall's solution is to specify /r̝/ for some non-contrastive feature – any one will do, because it need not be visible to the phonology. It does not trigger, block, or undergo any phonological processes. It simply prevents spreading of [Laryngeal] to /r̝/ from giving the wrong result because it keeps /r̝/ distinct from /t/ (or whatever the maximally underspecified obstruent happens to be) when it's devoiced. Dresher admits only contrastive features in the phonology, though; beyond that, only ‘post-phonological’ (phonetic) enhancement is permitted. The phonological portion of the theory would need to be augmented in order to account for Czech and cases like it. On the other hand, the analysis of voicing assimilation crucially depends on [Laryngeal], a feature that can only be identified by its phonological behavior, not the phonetic properties of segments that bear it.

In contrast to the SDA-based feature assignment described above, in Odden's approach, we would begin by assigning a feature – call it A – to the segments that undergo final devoicing. We would then assign another feature, B, to the segments that undergo regressive assimilation, and C to segments that trigger it. Since /v/ and /r̝/ undergo final devoicing and regressive assimilation but do not trigger regressive assimilation, they are both specified {A, B} but not {C}. As we have seen, /v/ stays voiced whereas /r̝/ undergoes progressive assimilation (i.e., devoicing), so /r̝/ gets another feature, D, to indicate this. This process of assigning features appears to provide a straightforward description of the facts, though it does not make the predictions about the range of possible phonologies entailed by adopting the Contrastivist Hypothesis.

The phonological feature-learning approach of Nazarov (Reference Nazarov2014: 24) differs considerably from the others discussed here, in that “the [acquisition] of phonological features is not motivated by an explicit requirement to have phonological features per se. Instead, features are induced by the learner because they help state constraints in a way that generalizes over more forms”. Constraints and features are induced in an iterative process, and constraints can refer to either features or directly to pre-existing “atomic segment units,” which Nazarov cautions “are not shorthand for a feature bundle” (Nazarov Reference Nazarov2014: 23). In Nazarov's model, the drive to maximize generalization will cause learners to state constraints over features only when multiple segments are affected – a position similar to that of Reiss (Reference Reiss, Hannahs and Bosch2017a). Thus, claims Nazarov (Reference Nazarov2014: 32), the learner will not generalize constraints that refer to a single segment: for example, a hypothetical constraint *m# banning [m] word-finally will not apply to novel [labial, nasal] segments. It is not clear, though, that this is a desirable prediction – or that it actually differs from the predictions made by Reiss (Reference Reiss, Hannahs and Bosch2017a), Odden (Reference Odden2022, in this issue), or indeed any other model presented here. Say, for the sake of argument, that the repair for word-final [m] is deletion. A Reissian child would trivially take the intersection of all the segments that undergo this process and arrive at the feature matrix for [m] (fully specified, since Reiss subscribes to an ‘archiphonemic’ view of underspecification in which only segments that alternate are underspecified; see Reiss 2008). The featural representation of a novel [labial, nasal] segment would differ from that of [m] and therefore not satisfy the conditions for deletion. An Oddenian child would assign some arbitrary feature to [m], and only [m], as it alone undergoes word-final deletion. Again, this would not generalize because a novel segment would not be assigned this feature without positive evidence. Of course, whether an actual child would fail to generalize to a novel [labial, nasal] segment should be tested experimentally. We discuss predictions regarding generalization further in 3.3.

3.2 The phonetic feature-learning view

Under the phonetic feature-learning view (e.g., Niyogi Reference Niyogi2004, Lin Reference Lin2005, Lin and Mielke Reference Lin, Mielke, Tauberer, Eilam and MacKenzie2008, Beguš Reference Beguš2020, Cui Reference Cui2020), features are acquired from the input and are not innate; but unlike under the phonological feature-learning view, this acquisition process is guided by phonetic substance. This approach takes seriously Hyman's (Reference Hyman1975: 25) pronouncement that “When a phonetic property can be extracted, a generalization is revealed. When no phonetic property can be extracted, these segments should not be able to occur as a class in linguistics.” A number of different models for mapping acoustic data to phones have been proposed (e.g., de Boer Reference de Boer2001, Niyogi Reference Niyogi2004, Coen Reference Coen2006, Oudeyer Reference Oudeyer2006 and many others), though this literature tends to be agnostic regarding whether the categories to be learned are phonemic or phonetic (see Dillon et al. Reference Dillon, Dunbar and Idsardi2013 on this point) and few commit to any particular model of phonology. Nevertheless, it is important to point out that phonology under the phonetic emergentist view must still be substance-free, even though the acquisition process is guided by substance: learned phonological categories are incompatible with theories in which there are innate rules or constraints that refer to phonetics (e.g., phonetically grounded theories).

Lin (Reference Lin2005: 74ff) proposes a model using unsupervised, iterative learning methods, incorporating a sub-model for identifying segments from a waveform followed by a sub-model for partitioning these segments to acquire features. Interestingly, Lin (Reference Lin2005: 98ff) also suggests that it is feasible to learn features inductively directly from the word-level acoustic waveform, and that the categories learned in this manner are very similar to those learned from the same training data augmented with segmental boundary information.

Another recent example of a phonetic learning-based approach is that of Cui (Reference Cui2020), who proposes a model of category acquisition in which the learner creates acoustic features one by one when needed to represent a lexical contrast. The child starts off with no phonological contrasts, representing individual acoustic tokens that all share the same phonological representation. When the learner finds evidence that two of the words in their lexicon have distinct referents, they pick the most salient cue distinguishing the two tokens, and turn that cue into a phonological feature. The feature defines a plane through acoustic space, and after the first division event, the child now has two categories. New tokens are sorted into those two categories according to which side of the plane they fall on.

Whenever children discover a new lexical distinction not representable by their current feature system, they again create a new feature defined by the most salient acoustic cue distinguishing the two tokens, and then use that cue to parse all future inputs. The phonetic category acquisition process stops when the child has enough features to represent every lexical contrast in the language. In this model, features are strictly acoustically defined: all featural distinctions correspond directly to planes in acoustic space. Features can be acquired in a language-specific (and indeed speaker-specific) order (similarly to the more phonologically driven proposal in Dresher Reference Dresher2018), with the most salient acoustic cues that distinguish the most frequent words in the language becoming categories the earliest.

Beguš (Reference Beguš2020) uses raw acoustic data to train a Generative Adversarial Network on an aspect of the allophonic distribution of English voiceless stops (aspirated word-initially if followed by a stressed vowel; unaspirated after [s]). The network is able to learn and generalize this generalization as well as to identify phonetic variables that correspond to the presence of [s]. This approach is similar to that of Dillon et al. (Reference Dillon, Dunbar and Idsardi2013) in that it learns aspects of phonetics and phonology at the same time. However, more work is needed to establish that this approach is feasible for other phonological alternations; opaque patterns and phonetically unnatural patterns would be particularly interesting cases.

3.3 Phonetics, phonology, or both?

The feature-learning approaches form a spectrum from those based entirely on phonology (e.g., Odden, Morén, Nazarov) to those that rely primarily on phonology but explicitly supplement it with phonetics (e.g., Archangeli and Pulleyblank, Dresher) through to those based exclusively on phonetics (e.g., Lin, Cui). As the example of River West Tarangan in 3.2 shows, we suspect that a purely phonetic approach will fail to account for many of the cases documented by Mielke (Reference Mielke2008). It is also interesting in this regard that all the ‘phonetic’ feature-learning approaches allow phonology to overrule the phonetics.Footnote 10 There is a division of labor and a logical sequence of events implied by both the phonetic and phonological feature-learning models: the child first identifies segments pre-phonologically on a phonetic basis, and then identifies the features that play a role in the phonological computation (i.e., are active). If this is correct, then the role of phonological features is purely computational, not to define contrasts (cf. Reiss Reference Reiss and Samuels2017b).

This is why we argue phonetic and phonological feature-learning approaches are stronger together. Lin (Reference Lin2005) and Dillon et al. (Reference Dillon, Dunbar and Idsardi2013) point out that most approaches to phonological acquisition assume segmental (phonemic) encoding of speech as their input. This is evident in the works reviewed in 3.1. Features, on this view, can be acquired by partitioning the segments based on their phonological activity, again as reviewed in the previous subsection. However, the starting assumption raises serious questions: how do children come to be able to parse the speech stream into segments? Moreover, what are these pre-existing segments, if not bundles of features? This is a particularly salient question for Nazarov, whose theory can refer directly to “atomic segment units.” We should not be fooled by the use of IPA into thinking that “atomic segment units” are the same type of thing as feature bundles that we also happen to label with IPA symbols as shorthand. It is very difficult to maintain the position that a child at this early stage of learning will be able to assign their percepts to unambiguous phonological categories, as we know (recall 2.3) that these categories vary from language to language and can overlap considerably.Footnote 11 Perhaps the phonological feature-learning approaches are still on the right track, but represent a stage after which the child has already used a phonetic strategy to arrive at a set of phones. Alternatively, Dillon et al. (Reference Dillon, Dunbar and Idsardi2013)Footnote 12 and Beguš (Reference Beguš2020) propose models that simultaneously learn aspects of phonetics (phones for Dillon et al., and features for Beguš) and the phonological processes that produce allophonic variation. Although these approaches are interesting, they have been demonstrated with only a couple of allophonic rules thus far.

It also remains unclear whether phonological feature-learning approaches can be modified to make correct predictions regarding the degree to which phonological rules are generalized by the learner. In 3.1.2 we discussed the special case of phonological rules that apply to only one segment, but it is worth considering this issue more broadly. Experiments with both infants and adults have demonstrated that learners generalize phonological rules to new contexts that would be featurally natural in an innatist approach (e.g., Cristià and Seidl Reference Cristià and Seidl2008, Finley and Badecker Reference Finley and Badecker2009). For example, Cristià and Seidl (Reference Cristià and Seidl2008) showed that infants will generalize a pattern involving nasals and stops to other members of the [-continuant] class. Speakers will also generalize a rule to a non-native/novel phoneme, as in the famous example of English speakers producing the plural of Bach /bɑx/ with [s] due to the voicelessness of /x/ (Halle Reference Halle1978). Here a contrastivist approach like that of Dresher or Hall correctly predicts generalization (see Dresher Reference Dresher2015 on loanword adaptation, which poses a very similar issue). However, for reasons discussed in 3.1.2, it seems to us that Odden (Reference Odden2022, in this issue) will not capture such generalizations.

One crucial component that appears to be missing from several of the phonetic and phonological feature-learning approaches we have discussed thus far is the ability to generate a phonemic system in addition to generating featural representations for all the surface phones. Odden (Reference Odden2022, in this issue) explicitly denies that ‘taxonomic phonemes’ need to be accounted for, but others remain silent. To the extent that generating a systematic phonemic inventory is desirable, phonological feature-learning models will need to be augmented by a second step to do so. Here again the approach taken by Dillon et al. (Reference Dillon, Dunbar and Idsardi2013) differs from the rest, as it is able to achieve all of this in one step. Perhaps this proposal could be coupled with a phonological or mixed phonetic-phonological feature-learning approach to learning phonemes, allophones, and features – but currently, no model does it all.

4. Conclusion and future directions

The spectrum of proposals regarding the status of phonological features within SFP is broad, and it is even broader when one considers models of phonological acquisition that are not explicitly substance-free but describe unsupervised learning methods for discretizing and categorizing acoustic input into phones. Despite this, we still find considerable common ground. With the exception of Nazarov, we all seem to agree – or at least, no other works of which we are aware explicitly disagree – that the notion “feature” is innate; that there is some innate syntax of features, albeit general enough to encompass both sign and speech; and that certain properties of our auditory processing system that are shared with other species appear to affect our phonological abilities. Among those of us who advocate feature-learning approaches, we also seem to agree that the procedure by which children go about acquiring features is innate. Although we can speak only for ourselves, this would seem to situate us all in the nativist tradition. We might disagree about the initial premises of Hale and Reiss's card grammar analogy, but we don't deny the basic argument: in their words, “ya gotta start with something!”

We have started – but much remains to be explored within the emergentist family of approaches. Future research will need to consider both theory and data carefully. Throughout section 3 we suggested a number of ways in which specific proposals are in need of refinement or further explication. For example, none of the phonetic theories address what the learner should do when confronted with a phonetically unnatural but phonologically active class, and the mixed theories are not explicit about the roles of each of these types of evidence. None of the theories discussed here except Dillon et al. (Reference Dillon, Dunbar and Idsardi2013) generate a phonemic inventory, but although they do not presuppose features, their theory does not explain how features are acquired, nor do many of the other models that learn phonetic categories from acoustic waveforms.

Though we have presented them as alternatives here, it seems that the phonological and phonetic feature-learning approaches could and should be synthesized, particularly in light of the fact that the phonological approaches seem to begin in medias res with a learner who can identify phones from the acoustic stream, whereas the phonetic approaches tackle this earlier stage of learning. Moreover, and very unfortunately given the arguments presented in 2.4, none of these proposals address learning features in modalities other than speech, something our theory of phonological acquisition must account for. We believe that these directions for future research will lead to more explicit, testable models, which will in turn strengthen SFP's position as a comprehensive theory of phonological competence from infancy to adulthood.

Footnotes

We would like to thank David Odden, Elan Dresher, Johanna Benz, the audiences at the Phonological Theory Agora in March 2019 and the Workshop on Theoretical Phonology in May 2020, as well as two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on previous versions of this material.

1 Following Hale and Reiss (Reference Hale and Reiss2000), the notion of phonological ‘substance’ is opposed to that of phonological ‘form.’ Specifically, the phonetic correlates of a particular feature are its substance, and the core hypothesis of substance-free phonology holds that “[p]honological primes are substance-free, in that their phonetic interpretation (…) does not play a role in phonological computation” (Blaho Reference Blaho2008: 2). Asymmetries that may be observed in the way particular features behave are attributed to extra-phonological properties, for example articulatory or perceptual biases, rather than markedness statements within the phonological grammar.

2 Abbreviations: SDA: Successive Division Algorithm; SFP: Substance-free phonology; SPE: Sound Pattern of English; TOT: tone onset time; VOT: voice onset time.

3 We set aside other sensory modalities for the time being. The same arguments should hold for visual primitives of signed languages, for example; see section 3.3.

4 It has commonly been assumed that speech and non-speech are processed similarly but independently (Liberman et al. Reference Liberman, Cooper, Shankweiler and Studdert-Kennedy1967, Liberman and Mattingly Reference Liberman and Mattingly1985), but see, for example, the findings of Bent et al. (Reference Bent, Bradlow and Wright2006) and Berent et al. (Reference Berent, Balaban, Lennertz and Vaknin-Nusbaum2010) that linguistic experience appears to affect performance on non-linguistic auditory tasks.

5 Some of these feature values may be underspecified: [0high, 0ATR, 0round] etc. We use + since there is no phonetic evidence for such underspecification in German, as there is, for instance, Marshallese (Bender Reference Bender1968, Choi Reference Choi1992, Hale Reference Hale2000). Even if we allow 0 and + options for all of these features across German-like I-languages, this would only give us eight different options (three features with two possible values each).

6 Of course the realizations studied in acoustic work are bodily outputs rather than surface forms or articulatory instructions, such that some of the variation observed is not phonological. However, in the case of Dutch rhotics, it should be clear that variants like [r, ʀ, j, ɻ, ɛ, ∅] (Sebregts Reference Sebregts2015: 281) require distinct sets of articulatory instructions.

7 Where sources differ on which Gomera Spanish phonemes correspond to which Silbo Gomero whistlemes, we have relied on Rialland (Reference Rialland2005), whose work is based on perceptual experiments.

8 However, some cases claimed to illustrate phonetically unnatural patterns are dubious and underscore the need to be cautious about the types of data that are brought to bear on this issue. See Hall (Reference Hall2010) and Uffmann (Reference Uffmann2018) for further discussion.

9 A maximally underspecified segment like this one necessarily occurs in every inventory produced by the SDA, so this problem is not an idiosyncrasy of Czech; see Hall (Reference Hall2007, section 1.2.7).

10 Krekoski (Reference Krekoski2013, Reference Krekoski2017) and Dresher (Reference Dresher2014) provide interesting evidence from Chinese tonal systems that phonological systems can remain stable despite phonetic changes, but only up to a certain point: when the phonetics no longer aligns with the phonological activity (in these cases, tone sandhi), the system is liable to undergo reanalysis. Such restructuring may weed out phonetically unnatural rules over time.

11 This is a feature-learning version of the concern raised by Dresher (Reference Dresher2015: 174) regarding Hale and Reiss's (Reference Hale and Reiss2008) innatist proposal, namely that features are inherently ambiguous (Dresher asks: “How low qualifies as [low]?”) and it seems unwise to assume that a learner could arrive at an unambiguous featural representation for the speech sounds they hear. See Cowper and Hall (Reference Cowper and Hall2014) for further helpful discussion.

12 Dillon et al. remain agnostic about whether features are innate, or if not, how they would be acquired (see discussion in their section 5.2).

References

Andersson, Samuel. 2020. I'm sorry but time travel isn't real: Against counterfeeding from the past. Penn Working Papers in Linguistics 26(1), Article 2. <https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol26/iss1/2>Google Scholar
Anttila, Arto. 2007. Variation and optionality. In The Cambridge handbook of phonology, ed. Lacy, Paul de, 519536. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arbib, Michael A. 2012. How the brain got language: The mirror neuron hypothesis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Archangeli, Diana, and Pulleyblank, Douglas. 2015. Phonology without universal grammar. Frontiers in Psychology 6: 1229.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beguš, Gašper. 2020. Modeling unsupervised phonetic and phonological learning in Generative Adversarial Phonology. Proceedings of the Society for Computation in Linguistics 3. Article 15.Google ScholarPubMed
Bender, Byron W. 1968. Marshallese phonology. Oceanic Linguistics 7(2): 1635.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bent, Tessa, Bradlow, Ann R., and Wright, Beverly A.. 2006. The influence of linguistic experience on pitch perception in speech and non-speech sounds. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 32(1): 97103.Google Scholar
Berent, Iris, Balaban, Evan, Lennertz, Tracy, and Vaknin-Nusbaum, Vered. 2010. Phonological universals constrain the processing of nonspeech stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 139(3): 418435.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Blaho, Sylvia. 2008. The syntax of phonology: A radically substance-free approach. Doctoral dissertation, University of Tromsø.Google Scholar
de Boer, Bart. 2001. The origins of vowel systems. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brentari, Diane. 1990. Licensing in ASL handshape. In Sign language research: Theoretical issues, ed. Lucas, C., 5768. Washington: Gallaudet University Press.Google Scholar
Brentari, Diane. 2011. Sign language phonology. In Handbook of phonological theory, ed. Goldsmith, John A., Riggle, Jason and Yu, Alan C.L., 691721. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Charles H. and Sinnott, Joan M.. 2006. Cross-species comparisons of vocal perception. In Listening to speech: An auditory perspective, ed. Greenberg, Steven and Ainsworth, William A., 183201. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Carreiras, Manuel, Lopez, Jorge, Rivero, Francisco and Corina, David P.. 2005. Linguistic perception: Neural processing of a whistled language. Nature 433: 3132.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Choi, John D. 1992. Phonetic underspecification and target interpolation: An acoustic study of Marshallese vocalic allophony. UCLA Working Papers in Phonetics 82.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam, and Halle, Morris. 1968. The sound pattern of English. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Classe, André. 1957. Phonetics of the Silbo Gomero. Archivum Linguisticum 9(1): 4461.Google Scholar
Clements, George N., and Hume, Elizabeth. 1995. The internal organization of speech sounds. In The handbook of phonological theory, ed. Goldsmith, John A., 245306. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Coen, Michael Harlan. 2006. Multimodal dynamics: Self-supervised learning in perceptual and motor systems. Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Corina, David P., and Sagey, Elizabeth. 1989. Are phonological hierarchies universal? Evidence from American Sign Language. In Proceedings of the 6th Eastern States Conference on Linguistics, ed. de Jong, Kenneth, and No, Yongkyoon, 7383.Google Scholar
Cowper, Elizabeth, and Hall, Daniel Currie. 2014. Reductiō ad discrimen: Where features come from. Nordlyd 41(2): 145164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cristià, Alejandrina, and Seidl, Amanda. 2008. Is infants’ learning of sound patterns constrained by phonological features? Language Learning and Development 4(3): 203227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cui, Aletheia. 2020. The emergence of phonological categories. Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
Dillon, Brian, Dunbar, Ewan, and Idsardi, William J.. 2013. A single-stage approach to learning phonological categories: Insights from Inuktitut. Cognitive Science 37(2): 344377.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dooling, Robert, Okanoya, Kazuo, and Brown, Susan. 1989. Speech perception by budgerigars (Melopsittacus undulatus): The voiced–voiceless distinction. Perception and Psychophysics 46(1): 6571.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dresher, B. Elan. 1998. Child phonology, learnability, and phonological theory. In The handbook of language acquisition, ed. Bhatia, Tej, and Ritchie, W.C., 299346. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Dresher, B. Elan. 2009. The contrastive hierarchy in phonology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dresher, B. Elan. 2014. The arch not the stones: Universal feature theory without universal features. Nordlyd 41(2): 165181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dresher, B. Elan. 2015. The motivation for contrastive feature hierarchies in phonology. Linguistic Variation 15: 140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dresher, B. Elan. 2018. Contrastive feature hierarchies in synchronic and diachronic phonology. Phonological Studies (Journal of the Phonological Society of Japan) 21: 9198.Google Scholar
Finley, Sara, and Badecker, William. 2009. Artificial language learning and feature-based generalization. Journal of Memory and Language 61(3): 423437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Mark. 2000. Marshallese phonology, the phonetics-phonology interface, and historical linguistics. The Linguistic Review 17(2–4): 241257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Mark, Kissock, Madelyn, and Reiss, Charles. 2007. Microvariation, variation, and the features of universal grammar. Lingua 117(4): 645665.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Mark, and Reiss, Charles. 2000. Substance abuse and dysfunctionalism: Current trends in phonology. Linguistic Inquiry 31(1). 157169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Mark, and Reiss, Charles. 2003. The subset principle in phonology: Why the tabula can't be rasa. Journal of Linguistics 39(2): 219244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Mark, and Reiss, Charles. 2008. The phonological enterprise. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hall, Daniel Currie. 2007. The role and representation of contrast in phonological theory. Doctoral dissertation, University of Toronto.Google Scholar
Hall, Daniel Currie. 2010. Probing the unnatural. In Linguistics in the Netherlands 2010 (27), ed. Jacqueline van Kampen and Rick Nouwen, 71–83. Amsterdam: Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halle, Morris. 1978. Formal versus functional considerations in phonology. Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.Google Scholar
Hay, Jessica. 2005. How auditory discontinuities and linguistic experience affect the perception of speech and non-speech in English- and Spanish-speaking listeners. Doctoral dissertation, University of Texas at Austin.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holt, Lori L., Lotto, Andrew J., and Diehl, Randy L.. 2004. Auditory discontinuities interact with categorization: Implications for speech perception. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 116: 17631773.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
van der Hulst, Harry. 1993. Units in the analysis of signs. Phonology 10. 209241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyman, Larry. 1975. Phonology: Theory and analysis. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.Google Scholar
Jakobson, Roman, Fant, C. Gunnar M., and Halle, Morris. 1952. Preliminaries to speech analysis: The distinctive features and their correlates. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Jusczyk, Peter W., Pisoni, David B., Walley, Amanda, and Murray, Janice. 1980. Discrimination of relative onset time of two-component tones by infants. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 61(1): 262270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keating, Patricia. 1984. Phonetic and phonological representation of stop consonant voicing. Language 60(2): 286319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendon, Adam. 2017. Reflections on the “gesture-first” hypothesis of language origins. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 24(1): 163170.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kluender, Keith R., Diehl, Randy L., and Killeen, Peter R.. 1987. Japanese quail can learn phonetic categories. Science 237: 11951197.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kohler, Klaus. 1999. German. In Handbook of the International Phonetic Association: A guide to the use of the International Phonetic Alphabet, 8689. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Krekoski, Ross. 2013. On tone and the nature of features. Ms., University of Toronto.Google Scholar
Krekoski, Ross. 2017. Contrast and complexity in Chinese tonal systems. Doctoral dissertation, University of Toronto.Google Scholar
Kuhl, Patricia K., and Miller, James D.. 1975. Speech perception by the chinchilla. Science 190. 6972.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kuhl, Patricia K., and Padden, Denise M.. 1982. Enhanced discriminability at the phonetic boundaries for the voicing feature in macaques. Attention, Perception and Psychophysics 32(6): 542550.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lajard, M. 1976. Le langage sifflé des Canaries. In Speech surrogates: Drum and whistle systems, vol. 2, ed. Sebeok, Thomas and Umiker-Sebeok, Donna Jean, The Hague: Mouton. [1891].Google Scholar
Liberman, Alvin M., Cooper, Franklin S., Shankweiler, Donald P., and Studdert-Kennedy, Michael. 1967. Perception of the speech code. Psychological Review 74. 431461.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Liberman, Alvin M., and Mattingly, Ignatius G.. 1985. The motor theory of speech perception revised. Cognition 21(1): 136.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Liddell, Scott, and Johnson, Robert. 1989. American Sign Language: The phonological base. Sign Language Studies 64. 197277.Google Scholar
Lin, Ying. 2005. Learning features and segments from waveforms: A statistical model of early phonological acquisition. Doctoral dissertation, University of California Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Lin, Ying, and Mielke, Jeff. 2008. Discovering place and manner features: What can be learned from acoustic and articulatory data? In Penn Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 14(1), ed. Tauberer, Joshua, Eilam, Aviad, and MacKenzie, Laurel: 241254.Google Scholar
Lipski, John M. 1985. Reducción de /s/ y /n/ en el español isleño de Luisiana: Vestigios del español canario en Norteamerica [Reduction of /s/ and /n/ in the Isleño Spanish of Louisiana: Vestiges of Canarian Spanish in North America]. Revista de Filologia de la Universidad de La Laguna 4: 125133.Google Scholar
Mayer, Connor, and Daland, Robert. 2019. A method for projecting features from observed phonological classes. Ms., University of California Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Mesgarani, Nima, David, Stephen V., Fritz, Jonathan B., and Shamma, Shihab A.. 2008. Phoneme representation and classification in primary auditory cortex. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 123(2): 899909.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meyer, Julien. 2005. Description typologique et intelligibilité des langues sifflées, approche linguistique et bioacoustique. Doctoral dissertation, Université Lumière Lyon 2.Google Scholar
Mielke, Jeff. 2004. The emergence of distinctive features. Doctoral dissertation, Ohio State University.Google Scholar
Mielke, Jeff. 2008. The emergence of distinctive features. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mielke, Jeff. 2012. A phonetically-based metric of sound similarity. Lingua 122(2): 145163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morén, Bruce. 2007. Phonological segment inventories and their phonetic variation: A substance-free approach. Paper presented at the GLOW XXX Segment Inventories Workshop, Tromsø.Google Scholar
Nazarov, Aleksei. 2014. A radically emergentist approach to phonological features: Implications for grammars. Nordlyd 41(1): 2158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nevins, Andrew. 2015. Triumphs and limits of the Contrastivity-Only Hypothesis. Linguistic Variation 15(1): 4168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nivens, Richard. 1992. A lexical phonology of West Tarangan. In Phonological studies in four languages of Maluku, ed. Burquest, Donald A. and Laidig, Wyn D., 127227. Summer Institute of Linguistics and University of Texas at Arlington.Google Scholar
Niyogi, Partha. 2004. Towards a computational model of human speech perception. In Proceedings of the Conference on Sound to Sense, 208–222. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Odden, David. 2022. Radical substance-free phonology and feature learning. In Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de linguistique 67(4): 500551CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oudeyer, Pierre-Yves. 2006. Self-organization in the evolution of speech. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pulleyblank, Douglas. 2003. Covert feature effects. In WCCFL 22: Proceedings of the 22nd West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Gina Garding and Mimu Tsujimura, 98422. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Google Scholar
Reiss, Charles. 2008. The OCP and NoBanana. In Rules, constraints, and phonological phenomena, ed. Bert Vaux and Andrew Nevins, 252301. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiss, Charles. 2017a. Substance free phonology. In Handbook of Phonological Theory, ed. Hannahs, Stephen J. and Bosch, Anna R. K., 425452. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiss, Charles. 2017b. Contrast is irrelevant in phonology. In Beyond Markedness in Formal Phonology, ed. Samuels, Bridget D., 2346. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiss, Charles, and Volenec, Veno. 2022. Conquer Primal Fear : Phonological Features are Innate and Substance Free. The Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de linguistique 67(4): 581610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rialland, Annie. 2003. A new perspective on Silbo Gomero. In Proceedings of the 15th International Congress of Phonetic Sciences, ed. Solé, María Josep, Recasens, Daniel, and Romero, Joaquín, 21312134. Barcelona: Causal Productions.Google Scholar
Rialland, Annie. 2005. Phonological and phonetic aspects of whistled languages. Phonology 22(2): 237271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuels, Bridget. 2009. The structure of phonological theory. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University.Google Scholar
Samuels, Bridget. 2011. Phonological architecture: A biolinguistic perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuels, Bridget. 2012. The emergence of phonological forms. In Towards a biolinguistic understanding of grammar. essays on interfaces, ed. Di Sciullo, Anna Maria, 193213. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, Wendy. 2012. The phonological organization of sign languages. Language and Linguistics Compass 6(3): 162182.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sandler, Wendy. 2014. The emergence of the phonetic and phonological features in sign language. Nordlyd 41(2): 183212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sapir, Edward. 1925. Sound patterns in language. Language 1(2): 3751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sebregts, Koen. 2015. The sociophonetics and phonology of Dutch r: Doctoral dissertation, Utrecht University.Google Scholar
Stokoe, William. 2002. Language in hand: Why sign came before speech. Washington: Gallaudet University Press.Google Scholar
Stokoe, William, Casterline, Dorothy C., and Croneberg, Carl G.. 1976. Dictionary of American Sign Language on linguistic principle. 2nd edition. Silver Spring, MD: Linstok Press.Google Scholar
Streeter, Lynn A. 1976. Kikuyu labial and apical stop discrimination. Journal of Phonetics 4(1): 4349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suga, Nobuo. 1969. Classification of inferior collicular neurons of bats in terms of responses to pure tones, FM sounds and noise bursts. Journal of Physiology 200: 555574.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Suga, Nobuo. 1973. Feature extraction in the auditory system of bats. In Basic mechanisms in hearing, ed. Møller, Aage R., 675744. New York: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suga, Nobuo. 2006. Basic acoustic patterns and neural mechanisms shared by humans and animals for auditory perception. In Listening to speech: An auditory perspective, ed. Greenberg, Steven and Ainsworth, William A., 159182. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Tesar, Bruce, and Smolensky, Paul. 2000. Learnability in Optimality Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasello, Michael. 2008. The origins of human communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trujillo, Ramón. 1978. El Silbo Gomero: Análisis lingüístico [Silbo Gomero: Linguistic analysis]. Santa Cruz de Tenerife: Andrés Bello.Google Scholar
Uffmann, Christian. 2018. A natural turn of Evenks. Paper presented at the 26th Manchester Phonology Meeting.Google Scholar
Vaux, Bert. 2008. Why the phonological component must be serial and rule-based. In Rules, Constraints, and Phonological Phenomena, ed. Vaux, Bert and Nevins, Andrew, 2060. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vieregge, Wilhelm H., and Broeders, A.P.A.. 1993. Intra- and interspeaker variation of /r/ in Dutch. EUROSPEECH’93: 267–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Volenec, Veno, and Reiss, Charles. 2017. Cognitive phonetics: The transduction of distinctive features at the phonology-phonetics interface. Biolinguistics 11(SI): 251294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Volenec, Veno, and Reiss, Charles. 2020. Formal generative phonology. Radical: A Journal of Phonology 2: 1148.Google Scholar
Waters, R.S., and Wilson, W.A.. 1976. Speech perception by rhesus monkeys: The voicing distinction in synthesized labial and velar stop consonants. Perception and Psychophysics 19(4): 285289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wikimedia Commons. 2006. Exemple de langage sifflé “El Silbo” pratiqué sur l’île de “La Gomera” (Canaries). <https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/file:silbo.ogg>>Google Scholar
Williams, L. 1974. Speech perception and production as a function of exposure to a second language. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University.Google Scholar