Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:36:37.142Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Editorial: Examining the Links

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 March 2020

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Special Section: Causality and Moral Responsibility
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2020

The topic of this special section, Causation and Moral Responsibility, was suggested to us by our ongoing research project Bioeconomy and Justice (BioEcoJust), funded by the Academy of Finland and the Finnish Ministry for Agriculture and Forestry. Bioeconomy, simply put, is a future alternative to the contemporary fossil-based economy, which, alongside the industrial revolution and the rise of global capitalism, has brought us our current coal, oil, and gas dependencies, pollution, environmental decay, and climate change. Bioeconomy has many connections to bioethics, given, of course, that we allow bioethics a remit beyond the immediate professional and organizational concerns of healthcare workers and authorities. Van Rensselaer Potter, one of the founders of the approach, thought that such a remit was essential,Footnote 1 although later developments have moved the cause, or discipline, into other directions.

In our project, we continue our two-decade research program, which has taken us through genetic engineering,Footnote 2 , Footnote 3 , Footnote 4 , Footnote 5 cloning,Footnote 6 , Footnote 7 , Footnote 8 , Footnote 9 , Footnote 10 , Footnote 11 , Footnote 12 , Footnote 13 , Footnote 14 genetic information,Footnote 15 , Footnote 16 , Footnote 17 , Footnote 18 , Footnote 19 , Footnote 20 , Footnote 21 , Footnote 22 , Footnote 23 human genetic databases,Footnote 24 , Footnote 25 , Footnote 26 , Footnote 27 systems biology,Footnote 28 genetic selection,Footnote 29 , Footnote 30 , Footnote 31 , Footnote 32 , Footnote 33 , Footnote 34 , Footnote 35 , Footnote 36 neuroethics,Footnote 37 , Footnote 38 , Footnote 39 , Footnote 40 , Footnote 41 synthetic biology,Footnote 42 , Footnote 43 , Footnote 44 and emerging technologies more generally,Footnote 45 , Footnote 46 , Footnote 47 back to the basics of rights, responsibilities, harm, justice, and the environment.Footnote 48 , Footnote 49 , Footnote 50 Our present focus on bioeconomy enables us to draw on work already done. Technological bioeconomy solutions often find their foundation in genetics, molecular biology, and synthetic biology. Forests and forestry are focal to the forthcoming bioeconomy in many ways, and issues like shrinking coal sinks and decreased biodiversity are, according to some, best encountered by genetic plant selection and cloning. Dietary choices, especially meat eating, produces a significant portion of our carbon footprint in the more affluent countries, and our studies into lifestyle restrictions,Footnote 51 , Footnote 52 coercion,Footnote 53 and paternalismFootnote 54 help us in this corner of the bioeconomy.Footnote 55

These substantial matters will be the topic of a future special section. In this collection of articles, however, we focus on one of the basic ethical questions of our project, namely, responsibility. Among our other research tasks, we aim to identify agents who promote or hinder the emergence of the bioeconomy, to determine the extent of their responsibilities, and to evaluate the normative meaning and impact of these responsibilities. To move in on the theme, we have gathered, and present here, a collection of articles, which approach responsibility and its moral implications from many different angles. Let us begin by contemplating the place and nature of responsibility in the bioethics institution that has the official duty of assessing the matter: ethics committees.Footnote 56 , Footnote 57 , Footnote 58

Most people working in bioethics have experience of hands-on ethical decisionmaking in these institutional review boards, or ethics committees as they are known outside the United States. Within the past few decades, institutional review boards have become standard practice in medicine and the biosciences. Research in the humanities and social sciences is also increasingly subjected to ethical review. This has improved the standing of research subjects, and contributed to the equality of researchers. Pretty much the same rules and protocols are upheld in institutions all over the world, which means that publishers and other interested parties can know that certain agreed standards of research ethics have been respected.

There is, however, a downside to institutionalized ethics. This is that there is very little ethics left, in particular from a consequentialist or utilitarian viewpoint. Much of the work in institutional review boards consists of checking that the proposal on the table right now follows national and international laws and regulations, and complies with institutional guidelines. The regulations and guidelines look at individual research proposals in isolation, which raises the question of how to keep an eye on the overall benefits and harms of research. It is, of course, good to ascertain that the participants of research projects are always protected, and that benefits always outweigh the associated harms. We do not, however, think that this is sufficient. If the goal is to achieve good outcomes—maximize preference satisfaction, minimize preference frustration, or the like—addressing research proposals one at a time is not enough.

Much of this boils down to research funding, and turns into a question of science policy. What kind of research gets funded, and why? How are the funding bodies—institutional, national, independent, and industry—allocating the funds available for research, and on what grounds? Are research funds allotted to projects that will benefit the greatest number? We do not think anyone could claim this. Rather, the growing trend seems to be that research with the highest short-term innovation and business potential gets the go-ahead. This raises a concern for the plight of poor people, people without powerful groups representing their interests, and people living in poorer countries more generally. The development of, say, medicines, treatments, and diagnostic tools for conditions effecting these people is unlikely to meet the threshold of commercial viability, and is, therefore, less likely to receive funding.

If we believe in the credo of classical liberalism, that economic prosperity will also benefit the worse-off, this would be an indirect route to “benefitting the greatest number.” We doubt that the credo is tenable. There is, as things stand, enough wealth in the world to feed everyone and to meet everyone’s basic health needs. The current uneven distribution of wealth, however, prevents this from happening, and there is no reason to think that this would change in the future. A far more probable scenario is that researchers develop more and more expensive treatments and medicines for the better-off (because this is where the profits that further benefit the wealthy are made), and this means that less and less becomes available for the worse-off.

From an ethical point of view, research fund allocation, in the bigger picture, can be seen as a variation of the trolley problem.Footnote 59 In a world of limited resources, funding research project A (advancing the wellbeing of group X) regularly implies not funding research project B (advancing the wellbeing of group Y), which means that one group of beneficiaries is chosen over another. To put the matter more provocatively, in the context of life-saving measures, funding allocation decisions are decisions about who lives and who dies. This being the case, we believe that it would be reasonable for someone, somewhere, to consider, among other things, the relative sizes of these groups, and the overall allocation of expected harms and benefits.

The matter of who, and at what level, should oversee these decisions is, of course, a tricky question. What would give legitimacy to the power of any such overseeing body? Why would independent funding organizations have to comply? These are complicated issues, and instead of trying to solve them here, let us start with two suggestions to make research ethics more ethical. First, and at minimum, we call for empirical studies on the allocation of research funding nationally and globally, to see to what extent our concerns are warranted. Who, under the current trend, would fund such studies remains uncertain. Second, we call upon our colleagues to come up with ideas on how to make the allocation of research funding more ethical and more just.

In some ways, what is happening in research ethics is symptomatic of many of the problems that face us in current times. Institutional structures, governmental and nongovernmental alike, are fragmented to the degree that when something goes wrong or grave injustice occurs, no one is, or can be, held accountable. For injustice to emerge, no wrongdoing by an accountable agent is needed. For moral wrongs to take place, no identifiable agent needs to commit the wrong, because the mechanism for letting them happen is inbuilt in the underlying structures. However, stubbornly holding on to the thought that ethics should be about equally considering the wellbeing of all, we would like to see something done about this. In the field of research ethics, a start would be to get people to care about the overall allocation of research funds.

In the first article of the collection, “The Undeserving Sick: An Evaluation of Patients’ Responsibility for their Health Condition,” Christine Clavien and Samia Hurst study the current tendency to hold individuals responsible for their lifestyle-related illnesses. In their thorough analysis, they show how the morally responsible parties could in fact be found elsewhere. Dr. Clavien and Prof. Hurst argue that, rather than the individuals, we should be looking at public health agencies and private industries as holders of much of the responsibility. In many cases, holding the individuals responsible would not only be morally wrong, but it would add further injustice to the injury they have already encountered.

In his commentary on Dr. Clavien and Prof. Hurst’s article, Thomas Douglas questions some of their psychological presuppositions, worries about further implications of their approach, and reminds us of the benefits of responsibility-sensitive health funding. In the end, however, he, at least tentatively, sides with the general thrust of their argument and policy conclusions.

Greg Bognar’s article, “The Mismarriage of Personal Responsibility and Health,” continues on the theme of the previous article. However, the approach here is quite different. Dr. Bognar scrutinizes the individual and population strategies, and studies their relative merits in addressing population health issues. He argues that the current responsibility-sensitive theories of distributive justice, together with the epidemiological change from communicable to noncommunicable diseases, have distorted our intuitions and resulted in us putting too much emphasis on personal responsibility in public health matters.

In her article, “The traditional Definition of Pandemic, Its Moral Conflation, and Its Practical Implications: A Defense of Conceptual Clarity in Global Health Laws and Policies” Thana C De Campos expands the theme of public health to global health. She studies the established notion of pandemic, and shows how it fails to differentiate between global emergencies and nonemergencies. This, she argues, is a result of the definition not being nuanced enough, and results in inadequate abilities to prepare for and respond to pandemics.

Commenting on De Campos’ article, Eduardo A Undurraga agrees with De Campos’ tenet that the current definition of pandemic might be inadequate for theoretical and practical purposes. He, however, notes that defining ‘severe’ might not be as straightforward as De Campos seems to believe, and further, that there are other factors contributing to insufficient ability to respond to global pandemics. For instance, while the International Health Regulation (IHR) treaty went into effect some twelve years ago, many low- and middle-income countries, due to insufficient funds, are yet to comply with the IHR and, more generally, in the absence of a coordinating institution, global preparedness is difficult to secure.

Scott Gelfand, in his “The Nocebo Effect and Informed Consent—Taking Autonomy Seriously,” discusses the phenomenon where learning about the possible side effects of a medical treatment increases the likelihood that one will suffer those side effects. He submits that there are two types of cases; those where there is only one treatment option and those where a choice needs to be made between several options. He argues that, based on ethical analysis, with the former, the default answer is nondisclosure, and with the latter, disclosure. However, there can be exceptions based on the intrinsic value the patient gives to her autonomy. To identify the exceptions, Dr. Gelfand would like to see a tool, similar to the Universal Pain Assessment Tool, developed to help physicians in their task of assessing their patients’ own concepts of autonomy.

In his response to Gelfand, Dien Ho challenges both Gelfan’s objections and the solution he proposes. Ho’s main criticism arises from his stance that the Nocebo Effect and the related ethical questions should not be dealt with isolated from clinical practice more generally. He concludes by stating that in order to better understand the tensions between respecting autonomy and nonmaleficence created by nocebos, we should look at the vast literature on conventional tensions in clinical practice.

Matti Häyry brings the harm caused to nonhuman animals to the table. His contribution, “Causation, Responsibility, and Harm: How the Discursive Shift from Law and Ethics to Social Justice Sealed the Plight of Nonhuman Animals” starts by analyzing different types of harm, and how they apply to human and nonhuman animals. Even though many of the categories overlap, when it comes to responsibility for harm, the two groups are treated very differently. Harm caused to humans creates an urgency to find the guilty parties, while harm inflicted on nonhuman animals, not so much. Prof. Häyry attributes this to the discursive shift from ethics to justice that took place in Western moral and political philosophy, and moral thought more generally in the late 1980s. He explains how, before the turn, the normative grounds for solving ethical issues were fairly straightforward, and were based on the wrongness of violating rights and causing harm. These normative assumptions were equally applicable to human and nonhuman animals. However, with the rise of complex theories of social justice, humans became a clear priority. While nonhuman suffering is still considered objectionable, each of the theories has its own reasons why human concerns take precedence, and nonhuman animals remain marginalized.

This special section closes with Fabrizio Turoldo’s two contributions to remind us that when discussing the matters of causation and moral responsibility, we might benefit from widening our horizons toward Continental philosophy and even psychoanalysis. In his first article, “The Cannibali that We Are: For a Bioethics of Food,” Dr. Turoldo studies the deeper social and psychological meanings that food and eating have for humans, and how this, for instance, affects our consumption habits. In his second contribution, “The Cannibal’s Gaze: A Reflection on the Ethics of Care Starting from Salvador Dalí’s Oeuvre,” Dr. Turoldo explores the importance of how we are seen. Understanding this is important for caring relationships in particular, and for human relationships in general.

Footnotes

Acknowledgements: The authors thank the Academy of Finland (project SA 307467 “Bioeconomy and Justice”) and the Finnish Ministry for Agriculture and Forestry (projects “The role of Justice in Decision Making Concerning Bioeconomy” and “A Just Management Model for Systemic and Sustainable Shift Towards Bioeconomy”) for their financial support.

References

Notes

1. Potter, VR. Bioethics: Bridge to the Future. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall; 1971 Google Scholar.

2. Häyry, M. Categorical objections to genetic engineering: A critique. In Dyson, A, Harris, J, eds. Ethics and Biotechnology. London: Routledge; 1994:202–15Google Scholar.

3. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Genetic engineering and the risk of harm. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1998;1:61–4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

4. Häyry, M. Playing God: Essays on Bioethics. Helsinki: Helsinki University Press; 2001 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5. Häyry, M. Genetic engineering of human beings. In: Chadwick, R, ed. Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics Vol. 4. Second edition. San Diego, CA: Academic Press; 2012:436–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6. Häyry, M. But what if we feel that cloning is wrong? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2001;10(2):205–8CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

7. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Cloning, naturalness and personhood. In: Thomasma, DC, Weisstub, DN, Hervé, C, eds. Personhood and Health Care. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers; 2001:281–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8. Häyry, M. Deeply felt disgust: A Devlinian objection to cloning humans. In: Almond, B, Parker, M, eds. Ethical Issues in the New Genetics: Are Genes Us? Aldershot: Ashgate; 2003:5567 Google Scholar.

9. Häyry, M. Philosophical arguments for and against human reproductive cloning. Bioethics 2003;17:447–59CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

10. Takala, T. The many wrongs of human reproductive cloning. In: Häyry, M, Herissone-Kelly, P, Takala, T, eds. Bioethics and Social Reality. Amsterdam and Atlanta: Rodopi; 2005:4962 Google Scholar.

11. Häyry, M. Cloning, Selection, and Values: Essays on Bioethical Intuitions. Helsinki: Acta Philosophical Fennica 81; 2007 Google Scholar.

12. Takala, T, Häyry, M. Benefiting from past wrongdoing, human embryonic stem cell lines, and the fragility of the German legal position. Bioethics 2007;21:150–9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

13. Takala, T. Cloning. In: Chadwick, R, ed. Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics Vol. 1. Second Edition. San Diego, CA: Academic Press; 2012:488–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14. Häyry, M. Ethics and cloning. British Medical Bulletin 2018;128:1521 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

15. Takala, T. Genes, Sense and Sensibility: Philosophical Studies on the Ethics of Modern Biotechnologies. Reports from the Department of Philosophy, University of Turku; 2000 Google Scholar.

16. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Genetic ignorance, moral obligations and social duties. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 2000;25:107–13Google Scholar.

17. Takala, T, Gylling, H. Who should know about our genetic makeup and why? Journal of Medical Ethics 2000;26:171–4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

18. Takala, T, Häyry, M, eds. Genetic Information . Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 2001;22:403–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Genetic information, rights, and autonomy. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 2001;22:403–14CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

20. Takala, T. Genetic ignorance and reasonable paternalism. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 2001;22:485–91CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

21. Takala, T. Genetic knowledge and our conception of ourselves as persons. In: Thomasma, DC, Weisstub, DN, Hervé, C, eds. Personhood and Health Care. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers; 2001:91–7Google Scholar.

22. Takala, T. Right to know and right not to know. Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics Vol. 3. Second edition. San Diego, CA: Academic Press; 2012:829–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23. Takala, T. Genetic moralism and health. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2019;28(2):225–35CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

24. Takala, T. Why we should not relax ethical rules in the age of genetics? In: Árnason, G, Nordal, S, Árnason, V, eds. Blood and Data: Ethical, Legal and Social Aspects of Human Genetic Databases. Reykjavik: University of Iceland Press & Centre for Ethics; 2004:135–40Google Scholar.

25. Häyry, M, Takala, T. American principles, European values, and the mezzanine rules of ethical genetic data banking. In: Häyry, M, Chadwick, R, Árnason, V, Árnason, G, eds. The Ethics and Governance of Human Genetic Databases: European Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2007:1436 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Bioethical analysis of the results: How well do laws and regulations address people’s concerns? In: Häyry, M, Chadwick, R, Árnason, V, Árnason, G, eds. The Ethics and Governance of Human Genetic Databases: European Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2007:249–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27. Takala, T. Setting a dangerous precedent? Ethical issues in human genetic database research. Medical Law International 2007;8:105–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

28. Häyry, M, Takala, J, Jallinoja, P, Lötjönen, S, Takala, T. Ethicalization in bioscience: A pilot study from Finland. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2006;15(3):282284 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29. Häyry, M. Selecting our offspring – Some objections and counterobjections. In: Bromham, D, Forsythe, E, Dalton, M, eds. Ethical Problems in Reproductive Medicine. London: National Association of Family Planning Doctors; 1989:36–8Google Scholar.

30. Takala, T. The child’s right to an open future and modern genetics. In: Almond, B, Parker, M, eds. Ethical Issues in the New Genetics: Are Genes Us? Aldershot: Ashgate; 2003:3946 Google Scholar.

31. Häyry, M. If you must make babies, then at least make the best babies you can? Human Fertility 2004;7:105112 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32. Häyry, M. There is a difference between selecting a deaf embryo and deafening a hearing child. Journal of Medical Ethics 2004;30:510–2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

33. Häyry M. The historical idea of a better race. Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 2008;2, Article 11; available at https://www.researchgate.net/publication/40823116_The_Historical_Idea_of_a_Better_Race (last accessed 31 July 2019).

34. Häyry, M. The moral contestedness of selecting “deaf embryos,” In: Kristiansen, K, Vehmas, S, Shakespeare, T, eds. Arguing About Disability: Philosophical Perspectives. London: Routledge; 2009:154–68Google Scholar.

35. Häyry, M. Rationality and the Genetic Challenge: Making People Better? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2010 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36. Häyry, M. Savior siblings. In: Chadwick, R, ed. Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics Vol. 4. Second edition. San Diego, CA: Academic Press; 2012:713 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37. Takala, T, ed. Philosophical Issues in Neuroethics . Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2010;19(2):161229 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

38. Häyry, M. Neuroethical theories. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2010;19(2):165178 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

39. Takala, T, Buller, T. Neural grafting: Implications for personal identity and personality. TRAMES: Journal of Humanities and Social Sciences 2011;15:168–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40. Launis, V, Takala, T, eds. Neuroethics . TRAMES: Journal of Humanities and Social Sciences 2011;15:123212 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41. Takala, T, Häyry, M. Neuroethics and animals, methods and philosophy. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2014;23(2):182–7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

42. Takala, T, Häyry, M, eds. Synthetic Biology: Ethical and Philosophical Challenges . Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2017;26(2):183277 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43. Häyry, M. Synthetic biology and ethics: Past, present, and future. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2017;26(2):186205 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

44. Takala, T. Finding hope in synthetic biology. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2017;26(2):239–45CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

45. Häyry, M. Considerable life extension and three views on the meaning of life. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2011;20(1):21–9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

46. Häyry, M. Protecting humanity: Habermas and his critics on the ethics of emerging technologies. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2012;21(2):211–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47. Häyry, M. Some additional thoughts on considerable life extension and the meaning of life. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2014;23(1):6872 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

48. Häyry, M, Vehmas, S. Disability as a test of justice in a globalising world. Journal of Global Ethics 2015;11:90–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

49. Häyry, M. Doctrines and dimensions of justice: Their historical backgrounds and ideological underpinnings. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2018;27(2):188216 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

50. Häyry, M. Justice and the possibility of good moralism. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2019;28(2):236–63CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

51. Häyry, H, Häyry, M. Karjalainen, S. Paternalism and Finnish anti-smoking policy. Social Science and Medicine 1989;28:293–7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

52. Häyry, M. Public health and human values. Journal of Medical Ethics 2006;32:519–21CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

53. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Coercion. In: ten Have, H, ed. Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics. Switzerland: Springer, Cham; 2016. Online. https://www.springer.com/gp/book/9783319094823 Google Scholar

54. Häyry, M. Liberal Utilitarianism and Applied Ethics. London: Routledge; 1994 Google Scholar, at 161.

55. A new issue that we are tackling is the inadequacy of perpetual economic growth as one of the cornerstones of “sustainable development.” For some of our views on this, see the recent presentation in a Finnish Ministry for Agriculture and Forestry organized conference EU Bioeconomy Scene, related to the Finnish late 2019 Presidency of the European Commission, Matti Häyry’s part beginning at 2:34:26; available at https://mmm.videosync.fi/eubioscene19 (last accessed 28 July 2019).

56. Häyry, M. Ethics committees, principles and consequences. Journal of Medical Ethics 1998;24:81–5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

57. Takala, T, Häyry, M. Ethics committees in Finland: their levels, methods, and point. Notizie di Politeia 2002;43(67):60–4Google Scholar.

58. Takala, T, Häyry, M. Research ethics and justice: The case of Finland. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2019;28(3):551–76CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

59. See, for example, note 54, Häyry 1994, at 101–4, 145–6.