Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T18:40:02.451Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The ethics of species extinctions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 November 2023

Anna Wienhues*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Art and Ideas, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway
Patrik Baard
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Art and Ideas, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway
Alfonso Donoso
Affiliation:
Institute of Applied Ethics and Institute of Political Science, Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile, Santiago, Chile
Markku Oksanen
Affiliation:
Department of Social Sciences, University of Eastern Finland, Kuopio, Finland
*
Corresponding author: Anna Wienhues; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This review provides an overview of the ethics of extinctions with a focus on the Western analytical environmental ethics literature. It thereby gives special attention to the possible philosophical grounds for Michael Soulé’s assertion that the untimely ‘extinction of populations and species is bad’. Illustrating such debates in environmental ethics, the guiding question for this review concerns why – or when – anthropogenic extinctions are bad or wrong, which also includes the question of when that might not be the case (i.e. which extinctions are even desirable). After providing an explanation of the disciplinary perspective taken (section “Introduction”), the concept of extinction and its history within that literature are introduced (section “Understanding extinction”). Then, in section “Why (or when) might anthropogenic extinctions be morally problematic?”, different reasons for why anthropogenic extinctions might be morally problematic are presented based on the loss of species’ value, harm to nonhuman individuals, the loss of valuable biological variety and duties to future generations. This section concludes by also considering cases where anthropogenic extinctions might be justified. Section “How to respond to extinctions?” then addresses a selection of topics concerning risks and de-extinction technologies. Finally, the section on “Extinction studies” introduces other viewpoints on the ethics of extinction from the extinction studies literature, followed by the “Conclusion”.

Type
Overview Review
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Impact statement

This is an overview review article of the ethics of species extinctions drawing on the environmental ethics literature. While most people seem to believe that extinctions are morally bad or wrong, no systematic review of the moral philosophical literature that can support or question such intuitions on this subject matter has been provided to date, which is the gap that this review article aims to fill.

Introduction

In an influential essay, conservation biologist Michael Soulé offered a list of what he termed ‘postulates of conservation biology’. Amongst these were also ‘normative postulates’ (i.e. value statements) such as that ‘[d]iversity of organisms is good’ and, relatedly, that ‘the untimely extinction of populations and species is bad’ (Reference Soulé1985, 730, italics in original removed). Soulé did not present any detailed argumentative justification for these normative postulates (see Baard, Reference Baard2022, 20ff), yet much could and must be said about their moral grounds, which provides an invitation to further discuss the ethical basis of species extinctions. So, why exactly are extinctions bad or wrong?

Extinctions – either as the extinction of single species or as mass extinction events on earth – are not only a matter of scientific inquiry and of policy relevance, but also a subject addressed by moral philosophy through questions concerning, amongst other things, the moral relevance and ontological status of species, moral responsibilities for human-caused extinctions, any moral obligations to avoid the loss of species and so on. Thus, this body of literature will aid us to explore the question of why extinctions might be bad or wrong, and for that purpose, we will provide a review of philosophical articles and books pertaining to the ethics of extinction (setting aside adjacent fields such as environmental law and history).

Moral philosophy, or ethics, is a normative discipline distinguished from empirical research on people’s values, preferences and practices as done in sociology, economics and history. Moral philosophy aims to assess critically and systematically the normative reasons that are expressed through/in value judgements, decisions and actions. It ranges from interrelated investigations about normative and evaluative languages and the relationship between fact and value (often known as meta-ethics), to research about fundamental ethical principles and ethical theories such as utilitarianism, deontology and virtue ethics (normative ethics), to the moral scrutiny of real-world cases and problems (practical/application-oriented/area-specific ethics). These three areas are often intertwined, and what is often called ‘applied ethics’ is not about merely applying more general or fundamental ethical theories. Rather, application-oriented practical reasoning gives rise to novel challenges and insights, which in turn also influence more general and fundamental discussions in ethics.

Environmental ethics spans across all these three areas of moral philosophy with a particular focus on concepts and arguments relating to the environment and nature, including the ethics of extinction, which gives rise to discussions about values and duties but also about issues concerning concepts such as species, ecosystems or biodiversity. Due to problems of deriving an action-guiding ‘ought’ from a descriptive ‘is’,Footnote 1 ethical discussions are pivotal to reasoning about and acting upon environmental issues.

Based on this disciplinary perspective, different positions and arguments presented here are not necessarily compatible with each other, because there are disagreements on different argumentative premises, intuitions, sentiments and underlying ethical theories. Therefore, in the following we are presenting different argumentative positions, but not a philosophical consensus on the ethical dimensions of species extinctions, such as in the form of a coherent theory that most authors would agree on, which is similar to how there are also disagreements in the natural and social sciences regarding which theory provides the best explanation of a natural or social phenomenon, which is not a weakness of this literature but an inherent feature of philosophical discussions that aim to critically exchange and improve arguments and theories. Ultimately, the moral judgements one finds reasonable or justified regarding extinction will not only depend on one’s empirical premises (and the quality thereof) but also on different metaphysical, ontological and normative premises and intuitions about how one sees the natural world and how one relates to it and lives within it.

Illustrating such debates in environmental ethics, the guiding question for this review concerns why – or when – anthropogenic (i.e. human-caused) extinctions are bad or wrong, which also includes the question of when that might not be the case (i.e. which extinctions are even desirable). This overarching question guides this review in two ways. Firstly, it led our selection of relevant positions and areas of discussion to be included in the review. In that regard, we aimed for as much comprehensiveness as possible pertaining to the representation of the main categories of reasons that have been presented in the field that can argumentatively support (or question) Soulé’s postulate. Secondly, this question narrows the scope of this review by including only arguments and positions that pertain to the ethics of extinction as opposed to providing a review of the much broader field of conservation ethics (about how to protect nonhuman individuals, species, ecosystems and landscapes). Consequently, we will cover, on the one hand, the major areas of discussion regarding the ethics of extinction (such as a growing body of literature on de-extinction technologies) and, on the other hand, we only include authors that provide substantive arguments on the topic of extinction (narrowly conceived).

To illustrate the breadth of such considerations, we will provide an overview of different concerns and arguments that are being discussed in the Western anglophone environmental ethics literature on species extinctions, broadly within the tradition of analytical philosophy. So, two caveats ought to be mentioned with respect to the chosen literature for this overview and the narrative presented. Firstly, because this review is largely limited to the Western anglophone analytical literature (except for some of the authors mentioned in the last section on extinction studies, which is necessitated by the character of that area of research), it can neither represent the rich variety of arguments and positions found in other philosophical traditions such as so-called continental philosophy and non-Western philosophy (e.g. Asian or African environmental philosophical traditions and Indigenous philosophies), nor does it cover relevant philosophical literature published in other languages. Secondly, by starting with Soulé’s postulate this review paints a particular narrative of the relevant reasons speaking in its favour or against it. We thereby particularly emphasise matters of moral value (i.e. different intrinsic and instrumental values) for providing reasons against or in favour of species extinctions due to their centrality in the environmental ethics literature, as well as in interdisciplinary conservation debates more broadly. Yet, certainly other somewhat different narratives that, for example, highlight more the differences between different ethical theories (e.g. rights-based versus virtue-focused perspectives) would be as plausible.

In the following, we start by presenting some noteworthy themes that have emerged from discussions within environmental ethics that address the concept of extinction and its history within that literature (section “Understanding extinction”). Then, we turn to different reasons for why anthropogenic extinctions might be morally problematic and cases where anthropogenic extinctions might be justified (section “Why (or when) might anthropogenic extinctions be morally problematic?”) and how to respond to extinctions (section “How to respond to extinctions?”). Finally, we look beyond our own narrow disciplinary perspective and introduce other viewpoints on the ethics of extinction from a body of work called ‘extinction studies’ (section “Extinction studies”) before concluding (section “Conclusion”).

Understanding extinction

The history of the concern about extinction in environmental ethics

A period from the late eighteenth century to the early twentieth century changed the way extinction was thought about in Europe and North America. During that time, three developments came together. Firstly, mostly thanks to Darwin, the idea of evolution and extinction as its key component replaced creationist ideas that distrusted the very possibility of extinction, if it was not outright denied. Reasons for this former denial are historical, as the influential Greek philosophers Plato and Aristotle, unlike some popular writers of the time, paid no attention to fossil bones of no longer existing vertebrates (Mayor, Reference Mayor2011). For them, species could not disappear except locally – a belief in line with the principle of plenitude dating back to Plato (Lovejoy, Reference Lovejoy1936), which states that all possible lifeforms necessarily exist and cannot disappear. Figuratively, the extant kinds form a ‘great chain of being’ and each kind in this chain is there necessarily; thus, the chain is unbreakable, and nature is in balance. This idea prevailed in pre- and early modern Europe and was endorsed by, for instance, Linnaeus as late as the eighteenth century.

Secondly, given the importance of the notion of extinction to evolutionary thinking, extinction was not seen as a matter of concern but rather the opposite: extinct species were too weak to survive, or an extinct species was replaced by another, thus maintaining the balance in nature. Both cases – through weeding out the weak and introducing novel species – were regarded as improvements in natural evolution (Barrow, Reference Barrow2009; Sepkoski, Reference Sepkoski2020).

Thirdly, despite this, and most relevant for thinking about the ethics of extinction, a concern about extinctions as universal and irreversible events started taking shape (as early as Marsh, 1864/Reference Marsh2003) and was broadly reflected in new legislation such as the Sea Birds Preservation Act of 1869 in the UK. This historical change is well conveyed by Aldo Leopold (1949/Reference Leopold1989, 110), when he stated that ‘[t]he sailor who clubbed the last auk thought nothing at all. But we, who have lost our [passenger] pigeons, mourn the loss’. Leopold (Reference Leopold1989, 210–211) also already noted that economic considerations fail to provide reasons for protecting those species that lack economic value. Instead of extending economic valuation, as has been proposed later by economists, Leopold saw conservation as action against extinction that also rests on non-anthropocentric ethical ideas. Nevertheless, a systematic philosophical discussion on the ethics of extinction evolved much later with the formation of the academic field of environmental ethics since the 1970s.

Early books and articles on environmental ethics did not explicitly discuss the ethics of extinction. The discussion focused on the flipside of the coin: Why protect endangered species (Elliot, Reference Elliot, Mannison, McRobbie and Routley1980; Gunn, Reference Gunn1980; Rescher, Reference Rescher1980)? One could see here a connection with new legislation, such as the US Endangered Species Act (1973), but the discussion broadened to also include the significance of diversity in nature more broadly (Naess, Reference Naess1973; Norton, Reference Norton1987), to incorporate the possibility of multiple extinctions in a relatively short period of time (for mass extinction, see Sepkoski, Reference Sepkoski2020) and to introduce a new concept, biodiversity (Wilson, Reference Wilson1986). For example, some ethicists have tried to develop a naturalistic account of the human propensity to value species and their diversity (Callicott, Reference Callicott1984, 305, Reference Callicott and Callicott1986; or, more recently, elaborated E.O. Wilson’s biophilia hypothesis, Baxter, Reference Baxter2007; cf. Takacs, Reference Takacs1996).

Arguably, one of the earliest contributions on the ethics of extinction is Richard Sylvan’s (then still known as Routley) famous thought experiment of the last person on earth (originally the ‘last man’), firstly formulated in 1973, which can be made relevant for thinking about extinction. Sylvan writes:

The last man (or person) surviving the collapse of the world system lays about him, eliminating, as far as he can, every living thing, animal or plant (but painlessly if you like, as at the best abattoirs). What he does is quite permissible according to basic chauvinism, but on environmental grounds what he does is wrong (Sylvan, 1973/Reference Sylvan, Light and Rolston2003, 49).

Later in the same article, he also specifically considers ‘vanishing species’:

Consider the blue whale (…). The blue whale is on the verge of extinction because of his qualities as a private good, as a source of valuable oil and meat. The catching and marketing of blue whales does not harm the whalers; it does not harm or physically interfere with others in any good sense, though it may upset them and they may be prepared to compensate the whalers if they desist; nor need whale hunting be willful destruction. (…) The behavior of the whalers in eliminating this magnificent species of whale is accordingly quite permissible – at least according to basic chauvinism. But on an environmental ethic it is not (1973/Reference Sylvan, Light and Rolston2003, 50).

He asked whether species or nature more broadly are valuable beyond their potential usefulness for humans. What Sylvan’s famous case suggests is that the permissibility of extinguishing species – as he argued, allowed by traditional Western ethical systems that conceive of nature as something to be used by humans as they please – is an example of what he called ‘human chauvinism’, now better known as ‘anthropocentrism’ (for a critical discussion of the ‘last person’ argument, see Peterson and Sandin, Reference Peterson and Sandin2013). Sylvan’s thought experiment has successively been modified and discussed by many other philosophers such as Mary Ann Warren (Reference Warren, Elliot and Gare1983) and Robin Attfield (Reference Attfield1981, Reference Attfield1983). The latter engaged in this type of argument to scrutinise the possibility of human extinction in the context of nuclear armament and ‘ecocatastrophe’. He aimed to show that non-sentient living nature such as trees has morally relevant interests and that causing their extinction by the ‘last man’ would be morally wrong, even if it would not affect any other humans.

Writing at the same time as Sylvan, Joel Feinberg (Reference Feinberg and Blackstone1974) addressed the ethics of species protection from a different argumentative angle. Because he argued that only (human and nonhuman) individuals with interests can have rights, he rejected the idea that species have a right to exist (for an opposing view, see Staples and Cafaro, Reference Staples, Cafaro, Cafaro and Crist2012). Therefore, he claimed that humans have a duty to protect endangered species, but the ultimate addressees of this duty are future humans, not the species themselves (see also Elliot, Reference Elliot, Mannison, McRobbie and Routley1980). Likewise, Nicholas Rescher (Reference Rescher1980) depicted species conservation ‘as a quintessential humanitarian task’ and John Passmore (Reference Passmore1974) considered wanton eradication of species to be acts of vandalism.

In brief, very early on, there were opposing opinions about why human-caused extinctions are morally wrong, while there was largely agreement on the issue that anthropogenic extinctions are wrong (with exceptions such as the smallpox virus). The similarity between these different views was that they regard extinction as a loss of value, either for humanity or for the universe as considered from a human-independent perspective. Independently of whether one endorses an anthropocentric (i.e. human-focused) or non-anthropocentric rationale for species conservation, both give rise to a range of resulting questions that were formulated in the literature of environmental ethics early on, such as: Are species individual entities or life processes that come to an end with extinction (Rolston, Reference Rolston1985, Reference Rolston and Nierenberg1995) (section “Defining extinction”)? What are acceptable costs for protection efforts (Norton, Reference Norton1987; Naess, Reference Naess and Rothenberg1989), and relatedly, should all species, even the most harmful ones, be conserved (Rolston, Reference Rolston1985; Johnson, Reference Johnson1991) (section “Future generations”)? Are species as collectives more valuable than nonhuman individuals (Russow, Reference Russow1981; Johnson, Reference Johnson1991) and does that therefore justify the culling of individuals that threaten the existence of native populations (Warren, Reference Warren1997; Varner, Reference Varner1998)?

Defining extinction

What constitutes an extinction is a complex subject matter. However, for the purpose of ordinary concerns about extinction and for how moral philosophers discuss its moral relevance, most theorists’ primary concern lies with anthropogenic species extinctions – while treating ‘extinctions’ and ‘species extinctions’ synonymously. Moreover, while many theorists put an emphasis on extinctions on a mass scale (such as Bendik-Keymer, Reference Bendik-Keymer2014; Cafaro, Reference Cafaro2015; Panagiotarakou, Reference Panagiotarakou2016; Baquedano Jer, Reference Baquedano Jer2019), some theorists are also explicitly concerned with the extinction of individual species (such as Rolston, Reference Rolston and Nierenberg1995).Footnote 2 Accordingly, there are four conceptual components found in many accounts of the ethics of extinction.

Firstly, there are different ontological positions on the meaning of ‘species’, that is what a species is (see Delord, Reference Delord2007; Maclaurin and Sterelny, Reference MacLaurin and Sterelny2008; Ereshefsky, Reference Ereshefsky and Zalta2022), which then also have different ethical implications (such as in Hull, Reference Hull1978; Gruen, Reference Gruen2011; Smith, Reference Smith2016). Moreover, because different kinds of species conservation practices change the genetic makeup of the target species (via conventional breeding programmes or synthetic biology) and/or influence their behaviour, it is also necessary to consider (1) whether the resulting population still belongs to the same species (which in turn influences whether we consider it extinct or not) and (2) whether that matters morally (see Preston, Reference Preston2021). Thus, there are different conceptions of species and these impact how extinction is defined (see Maclaurin and Sterelny, Reference MacLaurin and Sterelny2008; Godfrey-Smith, Reference Godfrey-Smith2014; Korsgaard, Reference Korsgaard2018a).

Secondly, the term ‘extinction’ can also be understood in different ways (see Delord, Reference Delord2007; Tanswell, Reference Tanswell2022), which is of ethical relevance because (1) it frames what falls within the ethics of extinction and, in turn, (2) the way extinction is constructed in controversial cases is in itself subject to ethical scrutiny. When speaking about extinctions as something morally problematic, many (not all) authors will refer to ‘final’ extinctions, if not specified further in works of practical ethics. Thus, an emphasis is put on ‘global’ (all individuals of a species are gone) as opposed to ‘local’ (loss of a population) extinctions. However, because a species can be extinct in several senses of the term, some authors also specifically problematise, for example cases where there still exist some (or even many) living individuals belonging to the species of concern. That is, it is not finally extinct, but it may be ‘functionally’ extinct. Drawing on the example of the whitebark pine as a case of a functional extinction, Christopher Preston (Reference Preston2021, 4, italics in original) argues in this regard that ‘[t]he concern with this type of extinction is not that you will never see individuals of the taxon again. The concern centres on the anthropogenic reordering of relationships. Not a loss of life, but a loss of arrangement’. That is, regarding this type of extinction an emphasis is put on changing ecological relationships rather than on the circumstance whether some individual members of the species are still alive.

Thirdly, many positions will argue – in different ways – that there is a moral difference between anthropogenic and non-anthropogenic extinctions. In Holmes Rolston’s III words, ‘[n]atural extinction opens doors, anthropogenic extinction closes them’ (Reference Rolston2012, 139). Independently from whether Rolston’s view on the matter is convincing, some people will intuitively find it morally objectionable that a species in the form of all the individuals belonging to that species abruptly disappears due to human actions (such as in Sylvan’s thought experiment, see section “The history of the concern about extinction in environmental ethics”) and thereby also ending an evolutionary process, instead of taking issue with natural evolutionary processes in themselves. This distinction not only assumes that anthropogenic and non-anthropogenic extinctions are conceptually different (Aitken, Reference Aitken1998), but usually also relies on the judgement that human-caused extinctions are morally more problematic than non-anthropogenic extinctions. So, for many authors it is relevant to know whether human causation is at play for the ethical assessment of the extinction in question (for epistemic barriers to assessing this causation, see Tanswell, Reference Tanswell2022) and that, in turn, is closely related to judgements about moral responsibility (Oksanen, Reference Oksanen2007). Contrasting views consider all species extinctions to be similarly morally problematic (i.e. similar ‘badness’) and thereby downplay the moral relevance of anthropogenic causation by adding ‘wrongness’ (Powell, Reference Powell, Beauchamp and Frey2011).

The fourth conceptual distinction needs to be made between mass extinctions and non-mass extinctions, with mass extinctions differing from an ordinary extinction event in several ways (see Bendik-Keymer and Haufe, Reference Bendik-Keymer, Haufe, Gardiner and Thompson2016). Because of these differences, evaluative judgements about the current ‘sixth mass extinction’ event on earth seem to be often based on the intuition that mass extinctions are morally more problematic than single extinction events. For example, consider how different terms such as ‘environmental atrocities’ (see Card, Reference Card2004) or ‘ecocide’ (see Baquedano Jer, Reference Baquedano Jer2019) can be potentially linked to extinction. While many might think that single extinction events added together are as bad as a mass extinction event involving the same number of species lost, some authors argue that a mass extinction is worse – for example due to additionally involving a ‘planetary shift’ (Sandler, Reference Sandler2021a).

Why (or when) might anthropogenic extinctions be morally problematic?

Returning to our question from the introduction, conservation biologists Soulé and Wilcox famously claimed that ‘[d]eath is one thing; an end to birth is something else’ (Reference Soulé and Wilcox1980, 8). This implies an evaluative judgement about the badness of species extinctions, but what might that mean? In the more recent environmental ethics literature, we can find a variety of reasons given to explain why anthropogenic extinctions might be (or might not be) morally problematic. We will present the main (but not sole) reasons found in this literature focusing on (1) the value of species, (2) harming nonhuman individuals, (3) the value of biodiversity and (4) duties to future (human and nonhuman) generations. In the last part of this section, we will also turn to (5) instances where extinctions might even be morally desirable.

Involving loss of value due to the loss of species

Because species extinctions involve the loss of species, the most obvious place to start is to think about whether this loss is in itself problematic (see Passmore, Reference Passmore1974). A common argumentative route in this regard is to argue that species are valuable and, thus, their extinction involves a loss of something that has been important to someone. For example, certain species might be instrumentally valuable because they are useful for human purposes (see section “Leading to the loss of valuable biological variety”). However, species might also be valuable independently from their actual or potential use value. That is, in contrast they might have intrinsic value as entities that we value in themselves.Footnote 3 Let us briefly introduce three (non-exhaustive) versions of this position (for further examples, see Callicott, Reference Callicott and Callicott1986 [for a critique, see Lo, Reference Lo2001]; Gorke, Reference Gorke2003; for a more general critical analysis of holistic accounts of species value, see Agar, Reference Agar2001).

For one, authors such as Rolston have argued that species – not understood as classes but as ‘living historical forms’ (Rolston, Reference Rolston1985, Reference Rolston2012) – are objectively intrinsically valuable (‘some values are objectively there—discovered, not generated, by the valuer’. Reference Rolston1988, 116), which means that with each species that disappears, we lose something of value even if we fail to recognise this loss. In his words,

[t]he species defends a particular form of life, pursuing a pathway through the world, resisting death (extinction), by regeneration maintaining a normative identity over time. It is as logical to say that the individual is the species’ way of propagating itself as to say that the embryo or egg is the individual’s way of propagating itself. The value resides in the dynamic form; the individual inherits this, exemplifies it, and passes it on (Reference Rolston, Attfield and Belsey1994, 21).

However, only anthropogenic extinctions are subject to moral evaluation (a duty to avoid extinctions) in Rolston’s account. He relies for this purpose on the analogy between ‘natural death’ (i.e. a natural extinction) and ‘murder’ (an anthropogenic extinction), which leads him to assess each anthropogenic extinction as a ‘superkilling’ (Rolston, Reference Rolston and Nierenberg1995). That is, on Rolston’s account the metaphor of a superkilling illustrates the badness of extinctions by putting an end to an evolutionary ‘story’ and precluding its future evolutionary possibilities. Other authors such as Lawrence E. Johnson have spelled out similar ideas, but with less emphasis on evolution and rather in terms of the species’ interests and their resulting moral standing (see Johnson, Reference Johnson1991).

Criticism of accounts such as Rolston’s or Johnson’s position, in turn, has been aimed at different aspects of their theories. Two primary areas of debate stand out. Firstly, the plausibility of the underlying theory of objective intrinsic value in Rolston’s account is a matter of debate (for a critique, see Elliot, Reference Elliot, Mannison, McRobbie and Routley1980; Callicott, Reference Callicott1992). Against the background that intrinsic values were intensely discussed in the field of environmental ethics at the time when Rolston published his account (see O’Neill, Reference O’Neill1992), it should be noted that other authors such as Callicott (Reference Callicott1984, Reference Callicott and Callicott1986) defended alternative value accounts relying on subjective values or human sentiments as the basis of a non-anthropocentric environmental ethic. Secondly, Johnson’s position relies on the idea that species can be considered to be akin to living beings (i.e. it relies on a specific species concept – as a living entity – that has been widely criticised not only by individualist perspectives but also by other holistic accounts; see Smith, Reference Smith2016) and, thus, also be morally considerable in the same way. However, whether that analogy is convincing and whether species have morally relevant interests are also a matter of debate (for a critique, see Sandler and Crane, Reference Sandler and Crane2006; Sandler, Reference Sandler2012). Consequently, in the more recent literature other arguments in favour of the moral value of species that are not based on such an understanding of species are more widespread.

For example, secondly, Ian Smith argues in favour of the view that a species has an ‘intrinsic good’ that ‘consist in its abilities to flourish’, based on a Hennigian species concept that sees species as ‘historical individuals’, which, in turn, gives us reasons to preserve species on Smith’s account because, amongst other things, ‘[a species’] flourishing is a species’ organisms continuing to reproduce successfully (that is, the organisms producing fertile offspring) and the species remaining safe from extinction’ (Reference Smith2016, 14). Smith takes it for granted that ‘species taxa are real’ (Reference Smith2016, 3–4) but subspecies are not. Therefore, only species are of intrinsic value. Critics have seen this presumption, in turn, as a failure to properly consider subspecies and higher categories in taxonomy (Burbrink et al., Reference Burbrink, Crother, Murray, Smith, Ruane, Myers and Pyron2022).

Finally, Ronald Sandler understands species as ‘groups of biologically related organisms that are distinguished from other organisms by virtue of their shared form of life’ (Sandler, Reference Sandler2012, 6, italics in original). What distinguishes organisms in this way, according to Sandler, are, for example, their ways to acquire energy (what they eat), how they move (and whether they move at all), how they reproduce and so on. Because Sandler argues against objective values being applicable to species (understood in this way), he points out that species can be still valuable in other ways. For example, some species are subjectively (finally/non-instrumentally) valuable (i.e. valuable because people actually value them) in two ways: firstly, in the form of ‘preference value’ as the ‘value that something has because people have a preference for it’ (Reference Sandler2012, 23). That value is also sometimes called ‘existence value’, which according to Espen Stabell (Reference Stabell2019, 180) ‘can be understood to involve self-regarding as well as other-regarding and nonanthropocentric preferences’. Secondly, species can also have ‘integral value’ as the ‘value that something possesses when it is valued in a way that flows from one’s worldview of core value commitments’ according to Sandler (Reference Sandler2012, 24).

This last account of the value of species neither relies on species having objective value (like Rolston), nor on species having interests akin to living beings (like Johnson), nor on the premise that species are being able to flourish (like Smith), and thus, it relies on less premises that might be controversial. However, in contrast to those other accounts its scope is much narrower because it concedes that only some anthropogenic species extinctions are lamentable by involving the loss of such value and only if this value is actually held by some humans.

Resulting from harm to nonhuman individuals

Non-anthropocentric individualist accounts within environmental ethics – that is sentientist (i.e. all sentient beings are morally considerable; Singer, Reference Singer1975) or biocentric (i.e. all living beings are morally considerable; Taylor, 1986/Reference Taylor2011) accounts – are only indirectly concerned with extinctions. What primarily matters to such positions is either the harm, impediment to well-being or injustice that is borne by individual nonhuman beings, and thus, the relevant harm involved in extinctions is not found on the species level (Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2011). Yet, it is often argued – for different reasons – that these two levels of analysis are closely related (Agar, Reference Agar2001; Regan, Reference Regan2004; Taylor, Reference Taylor2011; Korsgaard, Reference Korsgaard2018a; Donoso, Reference Donoso, Rivera-Lopez and Hevia2019; Baard, Reference Baard2022). For example, according to animal rights theorist Tom Regan the preservation of the biotic community follows from showing ‘proper respect for the rights of the individuals’ (Regan, 1983/Reference Regan2004, 363) that are part of that community.

As an example of emphasising the current anthropogenic mass extinction within an individualist framework, Anna Wienhues (Reference Wienhues2020) argues in favour of a biocentric theory of interspecies justice. Within this account, anthropogenic extinctions function as indicators of potential previous distributive injustices to nonhuman beings, due to the unjust deprivation of habitat that can ultimately lead to species extinctions. Within this context, extinctions are not injustices in themselves, but an outcome of interspecies injustice – metaphorically speaking she argues that ‘each anthropogenic extinction is a memorial for past injustices’ (Reference Wienhues2020, 157, italics in original).

A commonality of all of these individualist accounts is that they are only indirectly concerned with extinctions and cannot explain why an extinction is in itself morally lamentable (Benton, Reference Benton1993). Moreover, such accounts usually cannot morally distinguish between saving a specimen that belongs to a near-extinct species and one that does not belong to such a species (Sober, 1986/Reference Sober and Elliot1995; Baard, Reference Baard2022). If ethical relevance is placed solely on individual entities rather than species, then the extinction status of the species the entity belongs to does not necessarily count ethically, which could be more of a problem for some individualist accounts (e.g. Singer, Reference Singer1975; Cochrane, Reference Cochrane2012; see Korsgaard, Reference Korsgaard2018b), than for individualist accounts that allow for a degree of value pluralism (as opposed to everything of moral relevance being reducible to, e.g., individual well-being) and/or that allow for a degree of ethical pluralism (e.g. Wienhues, Reference Wienhues2020).

An alternative solution is presented by individualist accounts that conceptualise the individual’s interests as extending to ‘all other organisms that are relatives’ in terms of its species (understood following Mayr’s biological species concept) (Agar, Reference Agar2001, 150). Based on Nicholas Agar’s (Reference Agar2001) account, that consequently allows for an individualist argument that proposes that individuals that are part of endangered species and therefore rare are more valuable than their plentiful counterparts. According to Agar that follows because the value of an individual is not ‘a function only of its own goals. Its demise affects the other-directed and other-requiring goals of its conspecifics, depending on how plentiful its species is’ (Agar, Reference Agar2001, 150), which includes, for example, the ability of individuals to mate and successfully reproduce.

Yet, non-individualist accounts consider a theoretical focus on the individual to be a weakness. As Johnson puts it, ‘[a]n ethic that deals adequately with the issues of extinction must not only avoid being anthropocentric, it must avoid being atomistic’ (Reference Johnson1991, 170, italics in original). That might make one favour again one of the earlier introduced values of species accounts, but an account like Johnson’s faces in turn a range of difficulties in its own as already indicated above.

Leading to the loss of valuable biological variety

Besides accounts that consider the loss of parts of biodiversity to be problematic because of the moral relevance of species or nonhuman individuals, other perspectives consider species extinctions to be problematic due to the involved loss of biological variety. While biodiversity loss does not necessarily follow from species extinctions and vice versa, they are clearly conceptually related and practically implicated in each other. Problematising the loss of (bio)diversity, in turn, is a notable topic in the context of species extinctions because it has been institutionalised on an international level via the Convention of Biological Diversity (established in 1993).

Although the convention text begins with the recognition of ‘the intrinsic value of biological diversity’ (CBD, 1993), it is not obvious what role the intrinsic value in the CBD plays, as it appears only in the preamble. The recognition of intrinsic value is also followed by stating that the parties are conscious of ‘the ecological, genetic, social, economic, scientific, educational, cultural, recreational and aesthetic values of biological diversity’ (CBD, 1993). This shows that there is ambiguity in how the value of biodiversity is to be understood. Moreover, the larger normative international legal framework and even the CBD itself mainly endorse the established resource-focused language and practice (see Oksanen and Vuorisalo, Reference Oksanen, Vuorisalo, Casetta, Vecchi and Marques da Silva2019). Here, again the question arises about how biodiversity-focused claims about value should be interpreted.

So, the extinction of species via the resulting loss of biodiversity seems to involve a loss of value, but reasons for why the loss of variety might be problematic can rest on different argumentative grounds (Oksanen, Reference Oksanen1997; Callicott, Reference Callicott, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017; Heinzerling, Reference Heinzerling, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017; McShane, Reference McShane, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017; Odenbaugh, Reference Odenbaugh, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017; Baard, Reference Baard2022). Moreover, biodiversity can be conceptualised in various ways (CBD, 1993; Norton, Reference Norton, Sarkar and Plutynski2008; Faith, Reference Faith, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017, Reference Faith and Zalta2021; Sarkar, Reference Sarkar, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017; Burch-Brown and Archer, Reference Burch-Brown and Archer2017) and normative emphasis can be put on different kinds of diversity (such as ‘phylogenetic diversity’, Palmer and Fischer, Reference Palmer and Fischer2021). Generally, there are two common (not exhaustive) argumentative routes to choose from, which do not preclude each other but are often found in combination to justify the protection of biodiversity.

Firstly, biological variety as in the variety or abundance of, for example, genes or species might have instrumental value beyond the (instrumental) value of the species themselves (e.g. Maclaurin and Sterelny, Reference MacLaurin and Sterelny2008). While that is a common premise in conservation biology and environmental ethics that can justify why the extinction of many species is problematic due to the loss of valuable variety, different argumentative grounds for such instrumental value such as biodiversity’s contribution to ecosystem functioning or its (potential) agricultural and pharmaceutical benefits have also been critically discussed (see Maier, Reference Maier2012; Deliège and Neuteleers, Reference Deliège and Neuteleers2015; Newman et al., Reference Newman, Varner and Linquist2017; Morrow, Reference Morrow2023). Independent of such critiques, the loss of variety might not be problematic for instrumental value reasons in all circumstances (e.g. consider the loss of variety of certain pathogens), which means that not necessarily all extinctions involve a loss of instrumentally valuable variety.

Yet that needs to be kept distinct from the instrumental value attributed to species themselves (such as their ‘incalculable instrumental value’, see Smith, Reference Smith2022), although not all species will be instrumentally valuable for human purposes either (see section “Future generations”). In so far as these, as well as biological variety, are fundamental grounds for the possibility of human life on earth, a mass extinction can be understood as humanity’s ‘autodestruction’ constituting ‘a wrong in its own category. The wrong is the wrong of putting an end to humankind and all that is of value in it. This is a cataclysmic wrong’ as put by Bendik-Keymer and Haufe (Reference Bendik-Keymer, Haufe, Gardiner and Thompson2016, 7, italics in original). Thus, for such an argument the ‘massness’ (see section “Defining extinction”) of the current extinction event is central and, thereby, it avoids the problem that some individual species might not be instrumentally valuable for human purposes.

The second option is to consider the intrinsic value of biological variety as something that might be valuable in itself – independently of whether it is beneficial for humans or other lifeforms (Mikkelson, Reference Mikkelson2022). There are different versions of what this entails (see McShane, Reference McShane, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017). For example, deep ecologist Arne Naess famously stated that ‘[r]ichness and diversity of life forms (…) are also values in themselves’ (Naess, 1986/Reference Naess, Light and Rolston2003, 264). Providing a more nuanced view on the intrinsic value of biodiversity, Gregory Mikkelson (Reference Mikkelson2011, 186) points out that ‘variety’ is not the sole determinant of value in neither Næss’ deep ecology, nor in Mikkelson’s own preferred richness theory. Both invoke additional determinants such as ‘harmony’ (Mikkelson, Reference Mikkelson2011, Reference Mikkelson2014). To Mikkelson, more related to extinction, ‘anthropogenic species extinctions are decreasing the overall harmony of life on Earth’ (Reference Mikkelson2011, 191).

Philosophical claims about biodiversity’s intrinsic value also get external support. As already mentioned, conservation biologist Soulé considered biotic diversity to have intrinsic value (Reference Soulé1985, 731) and also the Convention on Biological Diversity refers to intrinsic value (for a critical discussion of both, see Baard, Reference Baard2022). Moreover, studies about the environmental values of the public also report intrinsic values being supported (e.g. Leiserowitz et al., Reference Leiserowitz, Kates and Parris2005; discussed by both Mikkelson, Reference Mikkelson2014; Odenbaugh, Reference Odenbaugh, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017) and strong pro-environmental attitudes confirmed empirically have the possibility of generating subjectivist non-instrumental values (see Lo, Reference Lo2006). However, different proposals concerning the intrinsic value of biological variety have also been subject to critical analysis (Sarkar, Reference Sarkar2005; Kraut, Reference Kraut2011; Maier, Reference Maier2012; Newman et al., Reference Newman, Varner and Linquist2017), such as concerning whether intrinsic value can attach to biological variety itself or whether that is better understood in terms of intrinsically valuing parts of biological variety such as species and individual beings (McShane, Reference McShane, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017).

Moreover, in addition to valuing species, nonhuman individuals and biological variety, further (additional or alternative) adjacent reasons grounding the badness of species extinction can be found in the literature. To mention two examples broadly within the realm of biodiversity-focused arguments, that includes, for one, arguments pertaining valuing the ‘irreplaceable design that is embodied by the individuals’ part of a species (Cline, Reference Cline2020, 46, italics in original). The point being that after a long evolutionary process, ‘[e]ach of the wonderful contrivances of nature are (…) unique and irreplaceable. Such irreplaceable design has special value that we recognise when we experience awe and wonderment towards the sophisticated structures and systems and strategies exemplified by living organisms’ (Cline, Reference Cline2020, Reference Elliot, Mannison, McRobbie and Routley59). According to Brendan Cline, that shifts the focus of concern away from the species themselves towards such ‘irreplaceable design’. Secondly, the loss of biodiversity might also be considered problematic due to a lack of respect towards nonhuman living beings and active nature in their natural otherness. Such respect provides us with reasons to protect biodiversity and, consequently, species variety (Wienhues and Deplazes-Zemp, Reference Wienhues and Deplazes-Zemp2022). Subsequently, human-caused extinctions can be interpreted as a lack of such respect.

What is common to all these types of biodiversity-focused arguments – regarding the instrumental value of variety, the intrinsic value of variety and pertaining alternative concepts (harmony, design, otherness, etc.) – is that for them the focus of moral concern shifts from species extinctions towards biological variety or those other concepts. So, like the individualist arguments (section “Resulting from harm to nonhuman individuals”) extinctions are again not problematised because of the loss of species themselves, but rather due to what this loss means for other valued entities or other matters of moral concern.

Future generations

A further reason for why species extinctions might be morally problematic concerns our duties to future human generations (see Feinberg, Reference Feinberg and Blackstone1974; Sandler, Reference Sandler and Gardiner2021b). In essence, if we believe that the interests of future generations put current generations under an obligation to not frustrate these interests, we have a reason to protect species and biodiversity that future generations might (intrinsically and instrumentally) value and, thereby, avoid ‘irreversible loss’ (Spiekermann, Reference Spiekermann and Gardiner2022). While there might be considerable uncertainty about what species, ecosystems and/or ecosystem ‘services’ future generations will actually value and/or need, this ultimately involves again an assessment of different arguments pertaining to the value of species and biodiversity (as seen in sections “Involving loss of value due to the loss of species” and “Leading to the loss of valuable biological variety”). Moreover, considerations about duties towards future generations in terms of species conservation provide a bridge between the ethics of extinction and the ethics of sustainability (see Norton, Reference Norton2003; Armstrong, Reference Armstrong and Gardiner2021).

In addition to these human-focused arguments, we can also consider non-anthropocentric arguments pertaining to the future (building on some of the arguments found in sections “Resulting from harm to nonhuman individuals” and “Resulting from harm to nonhuman individuals”; see also Nolt, Reference Nolt and Gardiner2021; Whyte, Reference Whyte and Gardiner2022). There are two main argumentative routes open in this regard. Firstly, one can consider potential duties towards future nonhuman beings or species in so far as the extinction of other species will affect them negatively (and consider cases where species might benefit from the extinction of other species; related to this, see Palmer, Reference Palmer and Arnold2011 and Cripps, Reference Cripps2013 for reflections about how certain species will benefit from climate change). Like how in intra-human intergenerational ethics a lot of thought has been given to the ‘nonidentity problem’ (see Norton, Reference Norton1982; Parfit, Reference Parfit1986), also here we face a nonhuman nonidentity problem (Palmer, Reference Palmer and Arnold2011), in so far as anthropogenic species extinctions will affect which individuals will come into existence in the future. That is, the extinction of some species will have a knock-on effect on which individuals of still remaining species will meet and mate, which in turn will influence which individuals will live in the future. The underlying philosophical problem is that those future individuals would not have come into existence without the extinction (which, in turn, is relevant for underlying considerations about how the ‘harm’ of extinction is understood). Secondly, the case of extinctions also leads to a ‘non-existence problem’ (Wienhues, Reference Wienhues2020) in so far as nonhuman individuals, species and ecosystems in the future will not only be affected by prior extinctions, but many nonhuman individuals will simply never come into existence.

Can anthropogenic extinctions ever be justified?

Some readers might assume that all anthropogenic extinctions are morally problematic, but does that judgement hold up in all cases? Consider these two examples from species conservation practice. Firstly, concerning ‘local’ (as opposed to ‘global’) extinctions consider restoration-based reasons in favour of the extinction of a population of an ‘invasive’ species (for critical discussions, see Rawles, Reference Rawles2004; Odenbaugh, Reference Odenbaugh2022; Thresher, Reference Thresher2022). Secondly, other conservation practices such as captive breeding and release programmes have in turn been criticised on the grounds of not allowing for a ‘death with dignity’ (Chessa, Reference Chessa2005). While in this case the extinction might still seem morally problematic, such programmes might not present an appropriate response. In both cases, it is possible to claim that an extinction can be all-things-considered better than an alternative course of action, for instance, on ecocentric or sentientist argumentative grounds (which both, in turn, can also be engaged to criticise the moral desirability of such extinctions).

Also, consider the case of disease-transmitting species such as certain mosquitoes that transmit malaria, dengue fever, zika and so on, which is the most discussed case of potentially justified extinction. The global health burden of these diseases is very high (WHO, 2017; Greisman et al., Reference Greisman, Koenig, Barry, Mastroianni, Kahn and Kass2019), which provides a good reason to consider whether the eradication of such disease-transmitting species would be an appropriate means to address this problem (Fang, Reference Fang2010; Bates, Reference Bates2016). While it is an empirical question to decide whether this constitutes an approach that is likely to succeed while minimising the risks in comparison with alternatives, this also generates a range of ethical questions to consider, such as regarding the moral standing of individual nonhuman animals, ethical aspects of risk and the intrinsic and/or instrumental value of species (see Pugh, Reference Pugh2016; Wienhues, Reference Wienhues, Hall and Tamïr2021; Callies and Rohwer, Reference Callies and Rohwer2022). A particular emphasis found in the literature on bioethics concerns questions of research ethics, risk and consent regarding genetically engineering species such as mosquitoes in this context (see Resnik, Reference Resnik2014; Emerson et al., Reference Emerson, James, Littler and Randazzo2017; Resnik, Reference Resnik2017; Neuhaus and Caplan, Reference Neuhaus and Caplan2017; Patrão Neves and Druml, Reference Patrão Neves and Druml2017; Meghani and Boëte, Reference Meghani and Boëte2018). Notably, even some authors who consider anthropogenic extinctions to be highly morally problematic acknowledge exceptions for disease-transmitting species such as malaria-transmitting mosquitoes (e.g. Rolston, Reference Rolston and Jamieson2001; Smith, Reference Smith2016).Footnote 4 While the use of synthetic biology such as gene drives remains controversial (Preston and Wickson, Reference Preston, Wickson and Dressel2019), the health burden of vector-borne diseases constitutes a weighty reason to take them into consideration.

Intended species extinctions are also considered for other – even more controversial – purposes, which include the case of predation raised in animal ethics. While some animal ethicists consider wild animal suffering to be of serious moral concern (Horta, Reference Horta2017), a few authors go as far as arguing that there are reasons speaking in favour of the extinction of predatory species. Footnote 5 The benefit hoped for would be the reduction of (non-anthropogenic) suffering in the ‘wild’ caused by predation (see McMahan, Reference McMahan2010, Reference McMahan, Chignell, Cuneo and Halteman2016). Such proposals to alleviate ‘wild’ animal suffering (by a range of means aimed at ‘dewilding’ or ‘redesigning nature’, see Duclos, Reference Duclos2022; Kianpour and Paez, Reference Kianpour and Paez2022) are in turn not shared by other animal and environmental ethicists on more general terms (see Palmer, Reference Palmer2010, Reference Palmer2015; Donaldson and Kymlicka, Reference Donaldson and Kymlicka2011; Aaltola, Reference Aaltola, Oksanen and Siipi2014; Hettinger, Reference Hettinger2018), as well as specifically on the question of removing predatory species (Vincelette, Reference Vincelette2022). Reasons include the difficulties of implementing such proposals and more principled objections towards such interventions into ‘nature’.

How to respond to extinctions?

Assuming that anthropogenic extinctions are morally problematic, how should they be avoided? What are morally permissible (or even demanded) means of doing so? One way of morally responding to extinctions is to turn our attention to species that have not yet gone extinct, but which are at risk of extinction (related to this, see arguments about the relevance of rarity [e.g. Gunn, Reference Gunn1980; James, Reference James2024] and arguments that emphasise endangered species [e.g. Smith, Reference Smith2016]).

This relates to the much broader body of work on the conservation of species in which new means and policies are being developed and discussed from a multidisciplinary perspective. To give one example (out of many) of philosophical discussion pertaining endangered species, consider ‘assisted migration’ or ‘species translocation’. The discussion about such proposals originated in grassroot activism but was taken up by ecologists, and ethicists soon joined the debate (Sandler, Reference Sandler2010, Reference Sandler2012; Hällfors et al., Reference Hällfors2014; Palmer and Larson, Reference Palmer and Larson2014; Siipi and Ahteensuu, Reference Siipi and Ahteensuu2016; Minteer, Reference Minteer, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017; Preston, Reference Preston2018; Palmer, Reference Palmer2021). The idea is to transfer populations to more suitable habitats where those species did not exist before to prevent them from going extinct. This is a conservation approach that is meant to be appropriate because of climate change (Hällfors et al., Reference Hällfors2014). There are different views on this matter. For example, there are discussions about how intentional translocation affects the value of the target species and its habitats (Siipi and Ahteensuu, Reference Siipi and Ahteensuu2016; Siipi, Reference Siipi, Garson, Plutynski and Sarkar2017). To Sandler, who focuses on the ethics of species, assisted colonisation is only justified in rare occasions in which ‘the translocated species would be ecologically or instrumentally valuable in the recipient site (and this can be reliably predicted in advance), or the species has final value’ (Reference Sandler2012, 85) (see section “Involving loss of value due to the loss of species” regarding Sandler’s understanding of such value). From an animal rights perspective, in turn, Angie Pepper argues that ‘the permissibility of practices like assisted migration hinges on whether or not we can justify imposing risks on animals in order to prevent rights violations further down the line’ (Reference Pepper2019, 602).

Risk of extinction

For the purposes of moral theorising, ‘risk’ refers to the likelihood of a loss or harm taking place, which makes ‘risk’ a value concept referring to an unwanted outcome through human actions, in addition to an epistemological dimension where that outcome is likely to happen with a specific probability (Hansson, Reference Hansson2013). If that probability is unknown, it is referred to as ‘uncertainty’ rather than ‘risk’, which often motivates a precautionary approach. With respect to species extinction, there are two main ways of discussing risks and extinctions: the first focuses on the risk of a single species facing extinction, and the second pays attention to broader systemic and accumulative risks, either in terms of mass extinction or in terms of a collapse of the biospheric system as we know it.

Regarding single species, risk is a premeditative concept that enables us to respond to near-extinction, such as when a species extinction is predicted to happen in the light of best ecological modelling, where the predicted quantity of extinctions has often been referred to as ‘extinction debt’ (Hanski and Ovaskainen, Reference Hanski and Ovaskainen2002; Kuussaari et al., Reference Kuussaari2009). Against this background, deliberations on employing concepts and ideas drawn from ecological sciences and (meta)population biology are taking place within environmental ethics and the philosophy of biology, which includes topics of ethical relevance such as decision-making under uncertainty and the applicability of the precautionary principle, land-use planning, protected area networking and prioritisation (Norton, Reference Norton1987; Sarkar, Reference Sarkar2005).

Risks have value dimensions, and what value is justifiably ascribed to a species will play a part in how it is to be prioritised (see section “Why (or when) might anthropogenic extinctions be morally problematic?”). Most efforts to save near-extinct species require prioritising: global and national Red Lists of Threatened Species are examples of such a conservation policy, as is Bryan Norton’s ‘triage model’ (Reference Norton1987, 258). Yet, prioritisations come with a range of philosophical problems. According to Norton, many of those challenges arise due to the difficulties of reducing the values of species to a single scale (Reference Norton1987, 255).

A broader perspective to the risk landscape emerges when we consider what kinds of systemic risks each extinction gives rise to (which is related to some of the concerns introduced in section “Leading to the loss of valuable biological variety”). A common argument rests on an analogy between species extinctions and the loss of rivets on an airplane wing (Ehrlich and Ehrlich, Reference Ehrlich and Ehrlich1981).Footnote 6 It aims to show that the ethical significance of extinction is due to its potential effects on ecosystems (the loss of too many ‘rivets’), which in turn are prerequisites for human and nonhuman survival. When conjunct with uncertainty regarding the number of rivets, or species, that an airplane wing, or ecosystem, can dispose of without collapsing, it becomes essential to preserve species and avoid their extinction (for a critical discussion of the analogy, see Sarkar, Reference Sarkar2005).

This expresses a form of precautionary principle, which has been discussed both critically and approvingly from different philosophical perspectives (Sandin, Reference Sandin2004; Sarkar, Reference Sarkar2005; Hourdequin, Reference Hourdequin2007; Newman et al., Reference Newman, Varner and Linquist2017; Tanswell, Reference Tanswell2022). The precautionary principle is also a part of the preamble of the Convention of Biological Diversity (CBD, 1993) where it is stated that lack of full knowledge ought not to justify inaction, and it is mentioned in the framework of the Intergovernmental Science-Policy Platform on Biodiversity and Ecosystem Services (IPBES n.d.). The complexity and uncertainty pertaining to how ecosystems work (Regan et al., Reference Regan, Colyvan and Burgman2002; Sarkar, Reference Sarkar2005) provide support for a precautionary principle concerning environmental decision-making. Yet, some authors consider its policy implications problematic due to leading to logical contradictions by potentially recommending two opposing actions (e.g. recommending the development of and simultaneously the prevention of developing genetically modified organisms), failing to account for possible benefits, neglecting that precaution has costs and for lacking conceptual clarity (Newman et al., Reference Newman, Varner and Linquist2017; critiqued in turn in Baard, Reference Baard2022).

De-extinction

What should be done after extinctions have already occurred? Besides more conventional species conservation practices, there is a broader discussion on the ethics of developing and using biotechnologies for conservation purposes and beyond (Ehrenfeld, Reference Ehrenfeld2006; Basl and Sandler, Reference Basl and Sandler2013; Kaebnick and Murray, Reference Kaebnick and Murray2013; Oksanen and Siipi, Reference Oksanen, Siipi, Oksanen and Siipi2014; Preston, Reference Preston2018). Setting these larger concerns aside, more technology-focused conservation approaches – if justifiable in certain cases – should be seen as complementary rather than alternatives to conventional conservation practices (Sandler, Reference Sandler and Gardiner2021b). Accordingly, the subject of debate concerns whether there are certain cases where such technological means are appropriate and desirable at all.

For example, a topic that has recently been gaining attention is the evaluation of the possibility of engineering species (via gene drives, cloning, etc.) either with the purpose of avoiding their extinction, such as by genetically adapting them to new climatic conditions or by increasing the genetic diversity of a population (see discussions by Palmer, Reference Palmer2016; Rohwer, Reference Rohwer2018; Sandler, Reference Sandler2019; Preston, Reference Preston2021; Sandler, Reference Sandler and Gardiner2021b; Welchman, Reference Welchman, Bovenkerk and Keulartz2021), or as means to eradicate invasive species (Thresher, Reference Thresher2022).

Related to proposals in favour (or critiques) of altering species to avoid (or cause) their extinction, a second body of work focuses on how and whether methods such as back-breeding, cross-species cloning and genetic engineering can be employed to appropriately address extinctions once they have occurred. Thus, the possibility of de-extinction by bringing a species ‘back’ from extinction has captured the imagination of many environmental philosophers (amongst many others, see Cohen, Reference Cohen2014; Oksanen and Siipi, Reference Oksanen, Siipi, Oksanen and Siipi2014; Turner, Reference Turner, Oksanen and Siipi2014; Diehm, Reference Diehm2015; Minteer, Reference Minteer2015; Campbell and Whittle, Reference Campbell and Whittle2017; Kasperbauer, Reference Kasperbauer2017; Oksanen and Vuorisalo, Reference Oksanen and Vuorisalo2017; Sandler, Reference Sandler2017; Browning, Reference Browning2018; Preston, Reference Preston2018; Katz, Reference Katz2022; Sandler et al., Reference Sandler, Stabell, Baylon, Lundgren, Weisbeek, Yelle and Zaba2022; for an alternative narrative, see also Odenbaugh’s, Reference Odenbaugh2023 recent review of the ethics of de-extinction).

This topic has become the centre of a lively debate in the ethics of extinction, which is noteworthy in so far as de-extinction is only a minor subject within the broader field of conservation ethics and debates (see also section “Extinction studies”). Of concern are, for example, different moral values and goods that might be supported or hindered by de-extinction projects (e.g. Cohen, Reference Cohen2014; Haught, Reference Haught2017; Smith, Reference Smith2017; Welchman, Reference Welchman2017; Rohwer and Marris, Reference Rohwer and Marris2018), which also include anthropocentric reasons in favour of the de-extinction of certain species, such as their potential value for ecosystem functioning, their economic value or their scientific value.

Non-anthropocentric attempts to provide a qualified justification for this approach include providing a list of criteria for its employment (e.g. Kasperbauer, Reference Kasperbauer2017) or by trying to make the idea useful for other normative purposes such as whether de-extinction might be a way of enacting a reparative duty towards nonhuman species or individual animals after extinctions have occurred. While thinking about de-extinction in terms of reparation or restitution might be intuitively appealing and constitute an argument occasionally engaged by conservation professionals, concerns about de-extinction as a form of reparation or retribution are shared by many authors (such as Oksanen and Siipi, Reference Oksanen, Siipi, Oksanen and Siipi2014; Diehm, Reference Diehm2015; Lean, Reference Lean2020; Welchman, Reference Welchman, Bovenkerk and Keulartz2021; yet for an argument in favour of a prima facie obligation to re-create species, see Jebari, Reference Jebari2016), while more might be said in favour of de-extinction as ecological restoration (Turner, Reference Turner, Oksanen and Siipi2014). Overall, while some authors argue that de-extinction can be ethically permissible in certain circumstances (Sandler, Reference Sandler2019), the debate on the desirability of de-extinction has been rather sceptical. Three common (not exhaustive) critiques of de-extinction fall into the following three categories.

Firstly, it has been frequently pointed out that the resulting species is not the same species as the previously extinct species, but only constitutes a copy (which concerns the species’ ‘identity’, Blockstein, Reference Blockstein2017; Siipi and Finkelman, Reference Siipi and Finkelman2017; Lean, Reference Lean2020). Actual ‘resurrection’ is not considered to be possible – or only possible by drawing on a very specific species concept (Oksanen and Siipi, Reference Oksanen, Siipi, Oksanen and Siipi2014) and related metaphysical commitments to resolve the ‘resurrection paradox’ (Delord, Reference Delord, Oksanen and Siipi2014) – which leaves any de-extinction proposal wanting (Diehm, Reference Diehm2017) and reintroduces the abovementioned considerations about the ontology of species (Beever, Reference Beever2017).Footnote 7 However, other writers argue that de-extinction technologies should not be understood as aiming to re-create extinct species in the first place (Lean, Reference Lean2020), which weakens this critique aimed at de-extinction while also reducing its intuitive appeal.

Secondly, concerns about animal welfare have been raised (Gamborg, Reference Gamborg, Oksanen and Siipi2014; Oksanen and Siipi, Reference Oksanen, Siipi, Oksanen and Siipi2014; Kasperbauer, Reference Kasperbauer2017; Turner, Reference Turner2017; Browning, Reference Browning2018; Browning and Veit, Reference Browning and Veit2022), which regards, for example, the welfare of the animals used for laboratory testing, of the animals that are (re)introduced into ecosystems and of the animals already living in the target ecosystems. Distinct from but related to such worries are also concerns regarding the ecological risks of (re)introducing species into ecosystems and, thus, what this means for ecosystems beyond the de-extinct species in question (Oksanen and Siipi, Reference Oksanen, Siipi, Oksanen and Siipi2014; on the more general relationship between biodiversity conservation and resurrecting species, see Oksanen, Reference Oksanen, Oksanen and Siipi2014).

Thirdly, we can find a range of worries raised against de-extinction on a more abstract level of analysis concerning the human–nature relationship (Kohl, Reference Kohl2017; Katz, Reference Katz2022). That is linked, in turn, to worries about naturalness (Gamborg, Reference Gamborg, Oksanen and Siipi2014) in terms of artificiality and authenticity (Katz, Reference Katz2022; discussed in Campbell, Reference Campbell2022; Lean, Reference Lean2022; Preston, Reference Preston2022; Reydon, Reference Reydon2022; Turner, Reference Turner2022, but for an argument against this concern, see Campbell and Whittle, Reference Campbell and Whittle2017) as well as concerns about instrumentalist ‘techno-optimist’ conservation strategies more generally as exemplified by de-extinction (Diehm, Reference Diehm2015).

Extinction studies

In the previous sections, we have mainly focused on what is commonly termed an analytical moral philosophical approach to the ethics of extinction. Yet, several other philosophical perspectives on extinction and contributions from outside of the fields of moral philosophy and the philosophy of biology also provide insights that are pertinent for thinking about the ethics of extinction that complement and enrich some of the discussions considered throughout this article. For example, there is a vibrant sub-debate in the conservation literature according to which ethical concepts and values should be supplemented or replaced by aesthetic concepts and values (e.g. Passmore, Reference Passmore1974; Sober, 1986/Reference Sober and Elliot1995; Hargrove, Reference Hargrove1989; Thompson, Reference Thompson1995; Tribot et al., Reference Tribot, Deter and Mouquet2018). Thus, one could claim that a species extinction is analogous to the loss of a great work of art.

A particularly notable further area of debate is the philosophical contributions in the interdisciplinary overlap with the environmental humanities and social sciences (e.g. Barad, Reference Barad2007; Haraway, Reference Haraway2008; Sodikoff, Reference Sodikoff2012; Tsing, Reference Tsing2015; Guasco, Reference Guasco2021) in a broad research area called ‘extinction studies’ (e.g. Chrulew et al., Reference Chrulew, Rose and van Dooren2017). Before concluding, we will highlight some elements of this perspective to find areas of convergence and divergence between these different intellectual traditions working on the ethics of extinction.

Scholars working within the extinction studies framework tend to emphasise an understanding of extinctions as a biocultural phenomenon (van Dooren et al., Reference Van Dooren and Rose2017; van Dooren, Reference Van Dooren and Gruen2018) that cuts across reality, inviting a vision of existence that recognises the deep interwoven nature of multispecies communities, experiences and collaborations. In line with this understanding, some writers have conceptualised extinctions as the loss of ways of life, underlining the fact that extinctions represent the demise of distinct forms of mating, nurturing, intergenerational learning, educating, interacting and so on (Rose, Reference Rose2011; Crist, Reference Crist and Bekoff2013; van Dooren, Reference Van Dooren2014; Despret, Reference Despret, Chrulew, Chrulew, Rose and van Dooren2017; Hatley, Reference Hatley, Chrulew, Rose and van Dooren2017).

Influenced by the work of philosophers such as Edmund Husserl, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and others, this perspective emphasises a phenomenological approximation to extinction, opposing a mere behavioural approach to the nonhuman world and, instead, stressing the importance of attentiveness and lived experience in our interactions with the natural world (Lestel et al., Reference Lestel, Bussolini and Chrulew2014). A key point of this approximation is to underline the experiences of those affected by extinction rather than focusing on the abstract disappearance of species. This speaks to the idea that the very experience of living on a biologically impoverished earth is understood as a source of deep concern (Crist, Reference Crist2019). This methodological emphasis, in turn, motivates the interest of extinction studies in individual stories of extinction (e.g. van Dooren, Reference Van Dooren2014) investigated through the tools of so-called field philosophy (Buchanan et al., Reference Buchanan, Bastian and Chrulew2018) and other alternative methods (e.g. Masco, Reference Masco2017).

Another important aspect of this perspective on analysing extinctions is the idea that the consideration of processes and occurrences of extinction cannot be separated from a critique of various forms of colonialism, imperialism and capitalism that inform our extinction-related practices and concepts (Dawson, Reference Dawson2016; Salazar Parreñas, Reference Salazar Parreñas2018). To illustrate, returning to themes introduced in section “Defining extinction”, while extinction studies do not attribute a single, all-encompassing meaning to extinction (De Vos, Reference De Vos, Simmons and Armstrong2007), this phenomenon is regarded as the result, amongst other things, of complications derived from concepts used hegemonically, including the terms ‘species’, ‘biodiversity’, ‘extinctions’ and ‘scientific knowledge’, amongst other notions. It is argued that these concepts represent a conventional classification of the natural world that is tinted by colonialist and anthropocentric biases that universalise Western scientific perspectives, thus privilege some organisational hierarchies over others and naturalise distinct power relations within dominant biodiversity conservation paradigms (Theriault et al., Reference Theriault, Leduc, Mitchell, Rubis and Jacobs Gaehowako2020). These terms employed with the purpose of organising reality ‘exclude myriad forms of life and relations and draw sharp boundaries between “living” and “dead” that confound the basic principles of so many living cosmologies’ (Mitchell, Reference Mitchell2016b).

When thinking about responses to extinction – for example as an ‘ethos of responsiveness towards the phenomenon of mass extinction’ (Michell, Reference Mitchell2016a, 39) – also in extinction studies, there is a general scepticism towards de-extinction projects as shared by the approaches introduced above (see section “De-extinction”). If extinctions are understood not as the demise of the last individual of a population, but as the disappearance of a way of life, de-extinction projects are doomed to fail, because they do not seem capable of capturing the deeply relational nature of life (Friese, Reference Friese2013; Jørgensen, Reference Jørgensen2013). This is interestingly complementary to some of the views discussed in the previous sections that, when examining the wrongness of extinctions and the problems of technological solutions such as de-extinction, emphasise the relevance of ecological and cultural relationships as the basis for what has value. Confronted with the failure of preventing extinctions and the magnitude of the biocultural losses produced by the disappearance of these ways of life, some extinction studies scholars emphasise the importance of mourning and remembrance as a proper response to extinction (van Dooren and Rose, Reference Van Dooren and Rose2017; de Massol de Rebetz, Reference de Massol de Rebetz2020). Rather than undoing loss, the moral significance of reflecting – remembering, mourning, grieving and imagining – the disappearances of deeply interwoven ways of life is underlined, giving rise to a moral psychology aspect to extinction.

Conclusion

This overview of the ethics of species extinctions has not attempted to spell out or critically discuss all topics or argumentative positions in detail. More humbly, our aim has been to provide an initial glimpse into some of the themes relevant for thinking about extinction that are being discussed in the literature of environmental ethics. For that purpose, we have given special attention to the possible philosophical grounds for Michael Soulé’s assertion that the untimely ‘extinction of populations and species is bad’, which does not answer what should be done to prevent extinctions.

While there is no simple or straightforward answer to the question of why anthropogenic extinctions are ‘bad’ or morally wrong, there is clearly largely agreement on the issue that anthropogenic extinctions are in most cases wrong, except for the controversially discussed cases of planned species extinctions in support of human (and nonhuman) health, such as with respect to vector-borne diseases. In such cases, anthropogenic extinctions might even be morally required. Besides such special cases, there is a broad plurality of arguments and perspectives underlying and supporting the need to pursue expansive biological conservation policies. Which conservation strategies and practices should be pursued (and which should not), in turn, remains an additional matter of debate, the subject of the ethics of conservation that supplements the ethics of extinction.

Lastly, there are two remarkable aspects to the literature surveyed. Firstly, most arguments pertaining to the wrongness or badness of species extinctions are not primarily concerned with ‘species’ as such. Rather, the matter of moral concern, such as the locus or source of value, is often located somewhere else: in the nonhuman individuals involved, in people’s relationship to particular species or landscapes, in biodiversity including variability within species and between ecosystems and so on, which reflects that there is more of moral relevance to the ethics of extinction than merely the numerical loss of species and their respective intrinsic or instrumental value. Views on the moral wrongness of anthropogenic extinctions result also, amongst other things, from underlying premises of what constitutes an appropriate human–nature relationship, which is why the current anthropogenic mass extinction event is of significant moral concern.

Secondly, considering how marginal de-extinction technologies still are as a (potential) practice of biodiversity conservation, it is noticeable how much interest the environmental ethics literature has shown on this topic. However, more important than the interrelated questions of whether species can and should be ‘resurrected’ is the uptake of a second set of broader related questions. These questions concern the morally permissible (or impermissible) uses of biotechnology for conservation purposes under conditions of climate change when conventional conservation practices such as habitat preservation and even more proactive approaches such as assisted migration reach their limits of effectiveness. As this is a growing area of interdisciplinary debate, we believe that providing critical analysis of these questions in the intersection between environmental ethics and the ethics of technology will be a significant area of environmental philosophical contribution during the upcoming years.

Open peer review

To view the open peer review materials for this article, please visit http://doi.org/10.1017/ext.2023.21.

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank Timo Vuorisalo and three anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on a previous draft of this manuscript.

Author contribution

A.W. is the lead author. P.B., A.D. and M.O. have all contributed in equal amounts to the writing and revising of this review.

Financial support

The writing of this review was supported for AW by the Forschungskredit of the University of Zurich, grant no. FK-21-081, and AW has also received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (grant agreement no. 948964, project ‘Dynamic Territory’). For PB, this article has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (grant agreement no. 948964, project ‘Dynamic Territory’). AD’s work was supported by the Fondecyt Project No. 11160170 and the ANID Millennium Science Initiative – ICS2019_025.

Competing interest

The authors declare none.

Social media summary

This review provides an overview of the ethics of extinctions drawing on the environmental ethics literature. It thereby gives special attention to the possible philosophical grounds for Michael Soulé’s assertion that the untimely ‘extinction of populations and species is bad’. After providing an explanation of the disciplinary perspective taken, the concept of extinction and its history within that literature are introduced. Then, different reasons for why anthropogenic extinctions might be morally problematic are presented based on (1) the loss of species’ value, (2) harm to nonhuman individuals, (3) the loss of valuable biological variety and (4) duties to future generations. Subsequently, (5) cases where anthropogenic extinctions might be justified are considered. Regarding how to respond to extinctions, a selection of topics is addressed concerning (1) risks and (2) de-extinction. Finally, the review introduces other viewpoints from the ‘extinction studies’ literature.

Footnotes

1 This is often referred to as ‘Hume’s law’ according to which prescriptive conclusions do not follow logically from descriptive premises.

2 A different subject that we set aside concerns anti-natalist perspectives that argue in favour of human extinction (e.g. Lenman, Reference Lenman2002).

3 What is understood as ‘intrinsic value’ can vary considerably between different authors. For good overviews, see O’Neill (Reference O’Neill1992) and McShane (Reference McShane2007). Thus, not all authors will agree on classifying the accounts that we introduce in the following as positions on intrinsic value (e.g. as opposed to extrinsic value). In addition to instrumental and intrinsic values, a third category of value that has been proposed is ‘relational value’, which, in turn, has also been applied to species (see Deplazes-Zemp and Chapman, Reference Deplazes-Zemp and Chapman2021). Also, this latter type of value is interpreted very differently by different authors (for a critique, see Baard, Reference Baard2019, Reference Baard2022), but arguments about relational value can be related to some of the concerns about the loss of species that are discussed in section “Extinction studies”.

4 Distinct but related to these concerns are broader considerations about the ‘ethics of pests’ (see Draney, Reference Draney1997; Winston, Reference Winston1999). Even if there are good moral reasons for anthropogenic extinctions, the full-scale eradication of a so-called ‘pest’ can be infeasible and have unintended consequences in practice. Therefore, some authors such as Mark Winston (Reference Winston1999) consider management and control better options than eradication.

5 Within the animal ethics literature, another additional type of concern relevant for theorising extinctions can be found, which are approaches that argue in favour of the abolition of the use of domesticated animals and, therefore, the extinction of these kinds of animals (e.g. Albersmeier, Reference Albersmeier2014).

6 Another kind of systemic argument relies on the ‘option value’ of species (see Maclaurin and Sterelny, Reference MacLaurin and Sterelny2008; Newman et al., Reference Newman, Varner and Linquist2017), which is a utilitarian concept in which ethical relevance is placed on the overall aggregated outcomes of a decision. In practice, an emphasis on the option value of species could allow for their substitution, if there are other ways of reaching the same results by other means than saving a near-extinct species. Such potential substitutability is problematic, in turn, for a range of ethical views, such as accounts that attribute intrinsic value to species (see section “Involving loss of value due to the loss of species”).

7 It should be noted that these are not necessarily new philosophical questions. For example, in Reference Elliot1994 Robert Elliot already asked whether it is possible to recreate an extinct species.

References

Aaltola, E (2014) Bioengineered domestication: ‘Wild pets’ as species conservation? In Oksanen, M and Siipi, H (eds), The Ethics of Animal Re-Creation and Modification: Reviving, Rewilding, Restoring. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 97116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agar, N (2001) Life’s Intrinsic Value. Science, Ethics, and Nature. New York: University of Columbia Press.Google Scholar
Aitken, GM (1998) Extinction. Biology and Philosophy 13, 393411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Albersmeier, F (2014) In defence of extinctionism. Les Ateliers de L’Ethique 9(3), 6888.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, C (2021) Natural resources, sustainability, and intergenerational ethics. In Gardiner, SM (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Intergenerational Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190881931.013.24.Google Scholar
Attfield, R (1981) The good of trees. Journal of Value Inquiry 15, 3554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Attfield, R (1983) The Ethics of Environmental Concern. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baard, P (2019) The goodness of means: Instrumental and relational values, causation, and environmental policies. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 32(1), 183199. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-019-09762-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baard, P (2022) Ethics in Biodiversity Conservation. Abingdon and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Baquedano Jer, S (2019) Ecocide or environmental self-destruction? Environmental Ethics 41, 237247.Google Scholar
Barad, K (2007) Meeting the Universe Halfway. Durham and New York: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrow, MV (2009) Nature’s Ghosts: Confronting Extinction from the Age of Jefferson to the Age of Ecology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basl, J and Sandler, RL (eds.) (2013) Designer Biology: The Ethics of Intensively Engineering Biological and Ecological Systems. Lanham: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Bates, C (2016) Would it be wrong to eradicate mosquitoes? BBC New Magazine 28 January.Google Scholar
Baxter, B (2007) A Darwinian Worldview. Sociobiology, Environmental Ethics and the Work of Edward O. Wilson. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Beever, J (2017) The ontology of species: Commentary on Kasperbauer’s “should we bring Back the passenger pigeon? The ethics of de-extinction”. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 1820. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291825.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bendik-Keymer, J (2014) Living up to our humanity: The elevated extinction rate event and what it says about us. Ethics, Policy & Environment 17(3), 339354. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2014.955309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bendik-Keymer, J and Haufe, C (2016) Anthropogenic mass extinction: The science, the ethics, and the civics. In Gardiner, SM and Thompson, A (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics, Oxford Handbooks Online. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Benton, T (1993) Natural Relations. Ecology, Animal Rights and Social Justice. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Blockstein, DE (2017) We can’t bring back the passenger pigeon: The ethics of deception around de-extinction. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 3337. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, H (2018) Won’t somebody please think of the mammoths? De-extinction and animal welfare. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31(6), 785803. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-018-9755-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, H and Veit, W (2022) More than zombies: Considering the animal subject in De-extinction. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25 (2): 121–24. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, B, Bastian, M and Chrulew, M (2018) Introduction: Field philosophy and other experiments. Parallax 24(4), 383391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burbrink, FT, Crother, BI, Murray, CM, Smith, BT, Ruane, S, Myers, EA and Pyron, RA (2022) Empirical and philosophical problems with the subspecies rank. Ecology and Evolution 12(7): 117. https://doi.org/10.1002/ece3.9069CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Burch-Brown, J and Archer, A (2017) In defence of biodiversity. Biology and Philosophy 32(6), 969997. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-017-9587-x.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cafaro, P (2015) Three ways to think about the sixth mass extinction. Biological Conservation 192, 387393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callicott, JB (1984) Non-anthropocentric value theory and environmental ethics. American Philosophical Quarterly 21(4), 299309.Google Scholar
Callicott, JB (1986) On the intrinsic value of nonhuman species. In Callicott, JB (ed.),In Defense of the Land Ethic. Essays in Environmental Philosophy. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, pp. 129155.Google Scholar
Callicott, JB (1992) Rolston on intrinsic value: A deconstruction. Environmental Ethics 14, 129143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callicott, JB (2017) What good is it, anyway? In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge, pp. 168182.Google Scholar
Callies, DE and Rohwer, Y (2022) Justifying an intentional species extinction: The case of Anopheles Gambiae. Environmental Values 31(2), 193210. https://doi.org/10.3197/096327121X16081160834786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, DI (2022) Why Katz is wrong: A lab-created creature can still have an ancient evolutionary history. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2), 109112. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, DI and Whittle, PM (2017) Resurrecting Extinct Species: Ethics and Authenticity, 1st Edn. Cham: Springer International Publishing: Imprint: Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69578-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Card, C (2004) Environmental atrocities and non-sentient life. Ethics and the Environment 9(1), 2345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chessa, F (2005) Endangered species and the right to die. Environmental Ethics 27, 2341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chrulew, M, Rose, DR and van Dooren, T (2017) Extinction Studies: Stories of Time, Death and Generations. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Cline, B (2020) Irreplaceable design: On the non-instrumental value of biological variation. Ethics and the Environment 25(2), 4572. https://doi.org/10.2979/ethicsenviro.25.2.03.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cochrane, A (2012) Animal Rights without Liberation. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, S (2014) The ethics of de-extinction. NanoEthics 8(2), 165178. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-014-0201-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD) (1993) Convention Text. Available at https://www.cbd.int/convention/articles/?a=cbd-02 (accessed May 2021).Google Scholar
Cripps, E (2013) Climate Change and the Moral Agent: Individual Duties in an Interdependent World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crist, E (2013) Ecocide and the extinction of animal minds. In Bekoff, M (ed.), Ignoring Nature No More: The Case for Compassionate Conservation. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, pp. 4562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crist, E (2019) Abundant Earth: Toward an Ecological Civilization. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawson, A (2016) Extinction: A Radical History. New York: OR Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Massol de Rebetz, C (2020) Remembrance day for lost species: Remembering and mourning extinction in the Anthropocene. Memory Studies 13(5), 875888.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Vos, R (2007) Extinction stories: Performing absence(s). In Simmons, L and Armstrong, P (eds), Knowing Animals. Leiden: Brill, pp. 183195.Google Scholar
Deliège, G and Neuteleers, S (2015) Should biodiversity be useful? Scope and limits of ecosystem services as an argument for biodiversity conservation. Environmental Values 24(2), 165182. https://doi.org/10.3197/096327114X13947900181275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delord, J (2007) The nature of extinction. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38(3), 656667.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Delord, J (2014) Can we really re-create an extinct species by cloning? A metaphysical analysis. In Oksanen, M and Siipi, H (eds), The Ethics of Animal Re-Creation and Modification: Reviving, Rewilding, Restoring. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 2239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deplazes-Zemp, A and Chapman, M (2021) The ABCs of relational values: Environmental values that include aspects of both intrinsic and instrumental valuing. Environmental Values 30(6), 669693. https://doi.org/10.3197/096327120X15973379803726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Despret, V (2017) Afterword. It is an entire world that has disappeared. Translated by Chrulew, M. In Chrulew, M, Rose, DB and van Dooren, T (eds), Extinction Studies. Stories of Time, Death and Generations. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 217222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diehm, C (2015) Should extinction be forever? Restitution, restoration, and reviving extinct species, Environmental Ethics 37(2), 131143. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics201537214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diehm, C (2017) De-extinction and deep questions about species conservation. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 2528. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291827.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donaldson, S and Kymlicka, W (2011) Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Donoso, A (2019) A territorial mediation in a triangular affair: Towards an ecological territorial sovereignty. In Rivera-Lopez, E and Hevia, M (eds), Controversies in Latin American Bioethics. Cham: Springer, pp. 219235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draney, M (1997) Ethical obligations toward insect pests. Ethics and the Environment 2(1), 523.Google Scholar
Duclos, JS (2022) Wilderness, Morality, and Value. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Ehrenfeld, D (2006) Transgenics and vertebrate cloning as tools for species conservation. Conservation Biology 20(3), 723732.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ehrlich, P and Ehrlich, A (1981) Extinction: The Causes and Consequences of the Disappearance of Species. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Elliot, R (1980) Why preserve species? In Mannison, DS, McRobbie, MA and Routley, R (eds), Environmental Philosophy. Canberra: Australian National University, Research School of Social Sciences, pp. 829.Google Scholar
Elliot, R (1994) Extinction, restoration, naturalness. Environmental Ethics 16, 135144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emerson, C, James, S, Littler, K and Randazzo, F (2017) Principles for gene drive research. Science 358(6367), 11351136. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aap9026.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ereshefsky, M (2022) Species. In Zalta, EN (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/species/ (accessed 6 October 2022).Google Scholar
Faith, DP (2017) A general model for biodiversity and its value. In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. Abingdon and New York: Routledge, pp. 6985.Google Scholar
Faith, DP (2021) Biodiversity. In Zalta, EN(ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/biodiversity/ (accessed November 2021).Google Scholar
Fang, J (2010) A world without mosquitoes. Nature 466, 432434.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Feinberg, J (1974) The rights of animals and unborn generations. In Blackstone, WT (ed.), Philosophy and Environmental Crisis. Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, pp. 4368.Google Scholar
Friese, C (2013) Cloning Wild Life: Zoos, Captivity, and the Future of Endangered Animals. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Gamborg, C (2014) What’s so special about reconstructing a mammoth? Ethics of breeding and biotechnology in re-creating extinct species In Oksanen, M and Siipi, H (eds), The Ethics of Animal Re-Creation and Modification: Reviving, Rewilding, Restoring. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 6076.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P (2014) Philosophy of Biology. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gorke, M (2003) The Death of our Planet’s Species: A Challenge to Ecology and Ethics. Washington, DC: Island Press.Google Scholar
Greisman, L, Koenig, B and Barry, M (2019) Control of mosquito-borne illnesses: A challenge to public health ethics. In Mastroianni, AC, Kahn, JP and Kass, NE (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Public Health Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 458471.Google Scholar
Gruen, L (2011) Ethics and Animals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guasco, A (2021) “As dead as a dodo”: Extinction narratives and multispecies justice in the museum. Environment and Planning E: Nature and Space 4(3), 10551076. https://doi.org/10.1177/2514848620945310.Google Scholar
Gunn, AS (1980) Why should we care about rare species? Environmental Ethics 2(1), 1737.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hällfors, MH, et al. (2014) Coming to terms with the concept of moving species threatened by climate change – A systematic review of the terminology and definition. PLOS One 9, e102979. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0102979.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanski, I and Ovaskainen, O (2002) Extinction debt at extinction threshold. Conservation Biology 16, 666673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansson, SO (2013) The Ethics of Risk: Ethical Analysis in an Uncertain World. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haraway, D (2008) When Species Meet. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Hargrove, EC (1989) Foundations of Environmental Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Hatley, J (2017) Walking with Okami, the large-mouthed pure god. In Chrulew, M, Rose, DB and van Dooren, T (eds), Extinction Studies. Stories of Time, Death and Generations. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 1947.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haught, P (2017) Integral value and the virtue of hospitality: A response to Kasperbauer. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 2932. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291830.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heinzerling, L (2017) Economizing on Nature’s bounty. In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge, pp. 183192.Google Scholar
Hettinger, N (2018) Naturalness, wild-animal suffering, and Palmer on laissez-faire. Les Ateliers de l’éthique 13(1), 6584. https://doi.org/10.7202/1055118ar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horta, O (2017) Animal suffering in nature: The case for intervention. Environmental Ethics 39(3), 261–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hourdequin, M (2007) Doing, allowing, and precaution. Environmental Ethics 29(4), 339–58. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics200729438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D (1978) A matter of individuality. Philosophy of Science 45(3), 335360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Intergovernmental Science-Policy Platform on Biodiversity and Ecosystem Services (IPBES) (n.d.) Glossary: Precautionary principle. IPBES. Available at https://ipbes.net/glossary/precautionary-principle (accessed October 2022).Google Scholar
James, S (2024) Rarity and endangerment: Why do they matter? Environmental Values.Google Scholar
Jebari, K (2016) Should extinction be forever? Philosophy & Technology 29(3), 211222. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-015-0208-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, LE (1991) A Morally Deep World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jørgensen, D (2013) Reintroduction and de-extinction. Bioscience 63(9), 719720.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaebnick, GE and Murray, TH (eds.) (2013) Synthetic Biology and Morality: Artificial Life and the Bounds of Nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kasperbauer, TJ (2017) Should we bring Back the passenger pigeon? The ethics of de-extinction. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 114. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291831.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, E (2022) Considering de-extinction: Zombie arguments and the walking (and flying and swimming) dead. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2), 81103. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kianpour, CK and Paez, E (2022) Red in tooth and claw no more: Animal rights and the permissibility to redesign nature. Environmental Values 31(2), 211231. https://doi.org/10.3197/096327121X16081160834777.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohl, P (2017) Using de-extinction to create extinct species proxies; natural history not included. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 1517. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291832.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, CM (2018a) Fellow Creatures: Our Obligations to the Other Animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, CM (2018b) Species-being and the badness of extinction and death. Zeitschrift für Ethik und Moralphilosophie 1, 143162. https://doi.org/10.1007/s42048-018-0002-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R (2011) Against Absolute Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kuussaari, M, et al. (2009) Extinction debt: A challenge for biodiversity conservation. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 24, 564571.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lean, CH (2020) Why wake the dead? Identity and de-extinction. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 33(3–6), 571589. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-020-09839-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lean, CH (2022) Authenticity and autonomy in De-extinction. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2), 116120. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leiserowitz, AA, Kates, RW and Parris, TM (2005) Do global attitudes and behaviors support sustainable development? Environment 47(9), 2239.Google Scholar
Lenman, J (2002) On becoming extinct. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83, 253269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leopold, A (1949/1989) A Sand County Almanac. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lestel, D, Bussolini, J and Chrulew, M (2014) The phenomenology of animal life. Environmental Humanities 5, 125148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lo, YS (2001) The land ethic and Callicott’s ethical system (1980–2001): An overview and critique. Inquiry 44(3), 331358. https://doi.org/10.1080/002017401316922444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lo, YS (2006) Making and finding values in nature: From a human point of view. Inquiry 49(2), 123–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovejoy, AO (1936) The Great Chain of Being. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
MacLaurin, J and Sterelny, K (2008) What Is Biodiversity? Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maier, DS (2012) What’s So Good about Biodiversity? A Call for Better Reasoning about Nature’s Value. Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-3991-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marsh, GP (1864/2003) Man and Nature. Seattle and London: University of Washington Press.Google Scholar
Masco, J (2017) The six extinctions: Visualizing planetary ecological crisis today. Environmental Philosophy 14(1), 1140. https://doi.org/10.5840/envirophil201611741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayor, A (2011) The First Fossil Hunters. Dinosaurs, Mammoths, and Myth in Greek and Roman Times. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, J (2010) The meat eaters. New York Times, September 19, 2010. Available at https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/09/19/the-meat-eaters (accessed 1 March 2023).Google Scholar
McMahan, J (2016) The moral problem of predation. In Chignell, A, Cuneo, T and Halteman, MC (eds), Philosophy Comes to Dinner. New York and London: Routledge, pp. 268294.Google Scholar
McShane, K (2007) Why environmental ethics Shouldn’t give up on intrinsic value. Environmental Ethics 29(1), 4361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McShane, K (2017) Is biodiversity intrinsically valuable? (and what might that mean?). In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge, pp. 155167.Google Scholar
Meghani, Z and Boëte, C (2018) Genetically engineered mosquitoes, Zika and other arboviruses, community engagement, costs, and patents: Ethical issues. PLoS Neglected Tropical Diseases 12(7), e0006501.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mikkelson, GM (2011) Weighing species. Environmental Ethics 31, 85196.Google Scholar
Mikkelson, GM (2014) Richness theory: From value to action. Les ateliers de l’éthique/The Ethics Forum 9(2), 99109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mikkelson, GM (2022) Abundance and variety in nature: Fact and value. Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00451-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minteer, BA (2015) The perils of de-extinction. Minding Nature 8(1), 1117.Google Scholar
Minteer, BA (2017) What would Leopold do? Considering assisted colonization as a conservation strategy. In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. Abingdon and New York: Routledge, pp. 212225.Google Scholar
Mitchell, A (2016a) Beyond biodiversity and species: Problematizing extinction. Theory, Culture & Society 33(5), 2342. https://doi.org/10.1177/0263276415619219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, A (2016b) Indigenous visions of the global extinction crisis. Worldly 27. Available at https://worldlyir.wordpress.com/2016/05/27/indigenous-visions-of-the-global-extinction-crisis/ (accessed 11 October 2022).Google Scholar
Morrow, KH (2023) A scale problem with the ecosystem services argument for protecting biodiversity. Environmental Values 32(3), 271290. https://doi.org/10.3197/096327122X16569260361751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naess, A (1973) The shallow and the deep, long-range ecological movement: A summary. Inquiry 16, 95100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naess, A (1989) Ecology, Lifestyle, and Community. Translated by Rothenberg, D. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naess, A (1986/2003) The deep ecological movement: Some philosophical aspects. In Light, A and Rolston, H (eds), Environmental Ethics: An Anthology. Malden: Blackwell Publishing, pp. 262274.Google Scholar
Neuhaus, C and Caplan, AL (2017) Ethical lessons from a tale of two genetically modified insects. Correspondence in Nature Biotechnology 35(8), 713716.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Newman, JA, Varner, G and Linquist, S (2017) Defending Biodiversity: Environmental Science and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nolt, J (2021) Long-term non-anthropocentric ethics. In Gardiner, SM (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Intergenerational Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190881931.013.14.Google Scholar
Norton, BG (1982) Environmental ethics and the rights of future generations. Environmental Ethics 4(4): 319337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norton, BG (1987) Why Preserve Natural Variety? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Norton, BG (2003) Searching for Sustainability. Interdisciplinary Essays in the Philosophy of Conservation Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Norton, BG (2008) Biodiversity: Its meaning and value. In Sarkar, S and Plutynski, A (eds), A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub (Blackwell companions to philosophy, 39), pp. 118.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, MC (2011) Creating Capabilities. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Neill, J (1992) The varieties of intrinsic value. The Monist 75(2), 119137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Odenbaugh, J (2017) Protecting biodiversity and moral psychology; or why philosophers are asking the wrong questions. In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge, pp. 193211.Google Scholar
Odenbaugh, J (2022) Owl vs owl: Examining an environmental moral tragedy. Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-022-00521-z.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Odenbaugh, J (2023) Philosophy and ethics of de-extinction. Cambridge Prisms: Extinction 1, e7, 17. https://doi.org/10.1017/ext.2023.4.Google Scholar
Oksanen, M (1997) The moral value of biodiversity. Ambio 26(8), 541545.Google Scholar
Oksanen, M (2007) Species extinction and collective responsibility. In Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 3, 179183. https://doi.org/10.5840/wcp2120073257.Google Scholar
Oksanen, M (2014) Biodiversity and the value of human involvement. In Oksanen, M and Siipi, H (eds), The Ethics of Animal Re-Creation and Modification: Reviving, Rewilding and Restoring. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 150169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oksanen, M and Siipi, H (2014) Introduction: Towards a philosophy of resurrection science. In Oksanen, M and Siipi, H (eds), The Ethics of Animal Re-Creation and Modification: Reviving, Rewilding, Restoring. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oksanen, M and Vuorisalo, T (2017) De-extinct species as wildlife. TRACE∴ Journal for Human-Animal Studies 3, 427. https://doi.org/10.23984/fjhas.59487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oksanen, M and Vuorisalo, T. (2019) Conservation sovereignty and biodiversity. In Casetta, E, Vecchi, D and Marques da Silva, I (eds), From Assessing to Conserving Biodiversity: Beyond the Species Approach. Cham: Springer, pp. 435452. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-10991-2_21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmer, C (2010) Animal Ethics in Context. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Palmer, C (2011) Does nature matter? The place of the nonhuman in the ethics of climate change. In Arnold, DG (ed.), The Ethics of Global Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Palmer, C (2015) Against the view that we are normally required to assist wild animals. Relations 3 2, 203210. https://doi.org/10.7358/rela-2015-002-palm.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmer, C (2016) Saving species but losing wildness: Should we genetically adapt wild animal species to help them respond to climate change? Midwest Studies in Philosophy 40(1), 234251. https://doi.org/10.1111/misp.12058.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmer, C (2021) Assisting wild animals vulnerable to climate change: Why ethical strategies diverge. Journal of Applied Philosophy 38(2), 179195. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmer, C and Fischer, B (2021) Should global conservation initiatives prioritize phylogenetic diversity? Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00422-7.Google Scholar
Palmer, C and Larson, B (2014) Should we move the whitebark pine? Assisted migration, ethics and global environmental change. Environmental Values 23, 641662.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Panagiotarakou, E (2016) Who loves mosquitoes? Care ethics, theory of obligation and endangered species. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 29(6), 10571070. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-016-9648-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D (1986) Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Passmore, J (1974) Man’s Responsibility for Nature. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Patrão Neves, M and Druml, C (2017) Ethical implications of fighting malaria with CRISPR/Cas9. BMJ Global Health 2(3), e000396.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pepper, A (2019) Adapting to climate change: What we owe to other animals. Journal of Applied Philosophy 36(4), 592607. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, M and Sandin, P (2013) The last man argument revisited. The Journal of Value Inquiry 47(1–2), 121133. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-013-9369-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powell, R (2011) On the nature of species and the moral significance of their extinction. In Beauchamp, TL and Frey, RG (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Preston, CJ (2018) The Synthetic Age: Outdesigning Evolution, Resurrecting Species, and Reengineering our World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preston, CJ (2021) Extinct and alive: Towards a broader account of loss. Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00426-3.Google Scholar
Preston, CJ (2022) How worried should I be about zombies? Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2), 129131. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071556.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preston, C and Wickson, F (2019) Ethics and governance. In Dressel, H (ed.), Gene Drives: A Report on their Science, Applications, Social Aspects, Ethics and Regulations. Bern: Critical Scientists Switzerland (CSS) & European Network of Scientists for Social and Environmental Responsibility (ENSSER) & Vereinigung Deutscher Wissenschaftler (VDW), pp. 215253.Google Scholar
Pugh, J (2016) Driven to extinction? The ethics of eradicating mosquitoes with gene-drive technologies. Journal of Medical Ethics 42, 578581.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rawles, K (2004) Biological diversity and conservation policy. In Philosophy and Biodiversity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 199216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regan, T (1983/2004) The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley, CA: The University of California Press.Google Scholar
Regan, HM, Colyvan, M and Burgman, MA (2002) A taxonomy and treatment of uncertainty for ecology and conservation biology. Ecological Applications 12, 618628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rescher, N (1980) Unpopular Essays on Technological Press. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Resnik, DB (2014) Ethical issues in field trials of genetically modified disease- resistant mosquitoes. Developing World Bioethics 14(1), 3746.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Resnik, DB (2017) Field trials of genetically modified mosquitoes and public health ethics. The American Journal of Bioethics 17(9), 2426.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reydon, TAC (2022) Deflating the de-extinction debates: Domination and artifactuality are not the problem. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2), 113115. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rohwer, Y (2018) A duty to cognitively enhance animals. Environmental Values 27(2), 137158. https://doi.org/10.3197/096327118X15162907484448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rohwer, Y and Marris, E (2018) An analysis of potential ethical justifications for mammoth de-extinction and a call for empirical research. Ethics, Policy & Environment 21(1), 127142. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2018.1448043.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rolston, H III (1985) Duties to endangered species. Bioscience 35(11), 718726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rolston, H III (1988) Environmental Ethics: Duties to and Values in the Natural World. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Rolston, H III (1994) Value in nature and the nature of value. In Attfield, R and Belsey, A (eds), Philosophy and the Natural Environment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 36), pp. 1330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rolston, H III (1995) Duties to endangered species. In Nierenberg, WA (ed.), Encyclopedia of Environmental Biology. Cambridge, MA: Academic Press, pp. 517528.Google Scholar
Rolston, H III (2001) Biodiversity. In Jamieson, D (ed.), A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Malden and Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 402415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rolston, H III (2012) A New Environmental Ethics: The Next Millennium for Life on Earth. New York and London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rose, DB (2011) Flying fox: Kin, keystone, Kontaminant. Australian Humanities Review 50, 119136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russow, L-M (1981) Why do species matter? Environmental Ethics 3(2), 101112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salazar Parreñas, J (2018) Decolonizing Extinction: The Work of Care in Orangutan Rehabilitation. Durham: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandin, P (2004) The precautionary principle and the concept of precaution. Environmental Values 13(4), 461–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, RL (2010) The value of species and the ethical foundations of assisted colonization. Conservation Biology 24, 424431.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sandler, RL (2012) The Ethics of Species: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, RL (2017) De-extinction: Costs, benefits and ethics. Nature Ecology & Evolution 1(4), 0105. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41559-017-0105.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sandler, RL (2019) Should we engineer species in order to save them? Environmental Ethics 41(3), 221236. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics201941323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, RL (2021a) On the massness of mass extinction. Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00436-1.Google Scholar
Sandler, RL (2021b) Species conservation, biotechnology, and intergenerational ethics. In Gardiner, SM The Oxford Handbook of Intergenerational Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190881931.013.52.Google Scholar
Sandler, RL and Crane, J (2006) On the moral considerability of homo sapiens and other species. Environmental Values 15(1), 6984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, R, Stabell, ED, Baylon, R, Lundgren, C, Weisbeek, P, Yelle, B and Zaba, M (2022) Eric Katz on “de-extinction”: Ontology, value and normativity. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2), 104108. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, S (2005) Biodiversity and Environmental Philosophy: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, S (2017) Approaches to biodiversity. In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. Abingdon and New York: Routledge, pp. 4355.Google Scholar
Sepkoski, D (2020) Catastrophic Thinking. Extinction and the Value of Diversity from Darwin to the Anthropocene. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siipi, H (2017) Unnatural kinds: Biodiversity and human-modified entities. In Garson, J, Plutynski, A and Sarkar, S (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Biodiversity. New York: Routledge, pp. 125–38.Google Scholar
Siipi, H and Ahteensuu, M (2016) Moral relevance of range and naturalness in assisted migration. Environmental Values 25, 465483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siipi, H and Finkelman, L (2017) The extinction and De-extinction of species. Philosophy and Technology 30, 427441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P (1975) Animal Liberation, 2nd Edn. London: Thorsons.Google Scholar
Smith, IA (2016) The Intrinsic Value of Endangered Species. New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315748405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, IA (2017) De-extinction and the flourishing of species. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 3840. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291834.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, IA (2022) Incalculable instrumental value in the endangered species act. Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00450-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E (1986/1995) Philosophical problems for environmentalism. In Elliot, R (ed.), Environmental Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 226247.Google Scholar
Sodikoff, GM (2012) The Anthropology of Extinction. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Soulé, ME (1985) What is conservation biology? Bioscience 35(11), 727734.Google Scholar
Soulé, ME and Wilcox, BA (1980) Conservation Biology: An Evolutionary-Ecological Approach. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.Google Scholar
Spiekermann, K (2022) Irreversible loss. In Gardiner, SM (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Intergenerational Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190881931.013.26.Google Scholar
Stabell, ED (2019) Existence value, preference satisfaction, and the ethics of species extinction. Environmental Ethics 41(2): 165180. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics201941215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Staples, W and Cafaro, P (2012) For a species right to exist. In Cafaro, P and Crist, E (eds), Life on the Brink. Athens and London: The University of Georgia Press, pp. 283300.Google Scholar
Sylvan, R (1973/2003) Is there a need for a new, an environmental, ethic?. In Light, A and Rolston, H III (eds), Environmental Ethics: An Anthology. Malden: Blackwell, pp. 4752.Google Scholar
Takacs, D (1996) The Idea of Biodiversity. Philosophies of Paradise. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Tanswell, FS (2022) The concept of extinction: Epistemology, responsibility, and precaution. Ethics, Policy & Environment 122. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2133937.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, P (1986/2011). Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. 25th Anniversary Edition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Theriault, N, Leduc, T, Mitchell, A, Rubis, JM and Jacobs Gaehowako, N (2020) Living protocols: Remaking worlds in the face of extinction. Social & Cultural Geography 21(7), 893908.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, J (1995) Aesthetics and the value of nature. Environmental Ethics 17(3), 291305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thresher, AC (2022) When extinction is warranted: Invasive species, suppression-drives and the worst-case scenario. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2): 132152. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2020.1848197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tribot, A-S, Deter, J and Mouquet, N (2018) Integrating the aesthetic value of landscapes and biological diversity. Proceedings of the Royal Society B. http://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2018.0971.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tsing, AL (2015) The Mushroom at the End of the World: On the Possibility of Life in Capitalist Ruins. Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Turner, DD (2014) The restoration argument for extinction reversal. In Oksanen, M and Siipi, H (eds), The Ethics of Animal Re-Creation and Modification: Reviving, Rewilding, Restoring. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 4059.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, DD (2017) Biases in the selection of candidate species for De-extinction. Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 2124. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1291835.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, D (2022) Causal history, environmental art, and biotechnologically assisted restoration. Ethics, Policy & Environment 25(2), 125128. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2022.2071557.Google Scholar
Van Dooren, T (2014) Flight Ways: Life and Loss at the Edge of Extinction. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Van Dooren, T (2018) Extinction. In Gruen, L (ed.), Critical Terms for Animal Studies. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Van Dooren, T and Rose, DB (2017) ‘Keeping Faith with the dead: Mourning and de-extinction’. Australian Zoologist 38(3), 375378. https://doi.org/10.7882/AZ.2014.048.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varner, GE (1998) In Nature’s Interests? Interests, Animal Rights, and Environmental Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vincelette, A (2022) In defense of tigers and wolves: A critique of McMahan, Nussbaum, and Johannsen on the elimination of predators from the wild. Ethics & the Environment 27(1), 1738.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warren, MA (1983) The rights of the nonhuman world. In Elliot, R and Gare, A (eds), Environmental Philosophy: A Collection of Readings. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, MA (1997) Moral Status. Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Welchman, J (2017) ‘How much is that mammoth in the window? Ethics, Policy & Environment 20(1), 4143. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2017.1299674.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welchman, J (2021) Does justice require De-extinction of the heath hen? In Bovenkerk, B and Keulartz, J (eds), Animals in our Midst: The Challenges of Co-Existing with Animals in the Anthropocene. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 513532. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-63523-7_28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whyte, K (2022) Ancestry and crisis: Intergenerational ethics and ecocentrism. In Gardiner, SM (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Intergenerational Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190881931.013.15.Google Scholar
Wienhues, A (2020) Ecological Justice and the Extinction Crisis: Giving Living Beings their Due. Bristol: Bristol University Press. https://doi.org/10.51952/9781529208528.Google Scholar
Wienhues, A (2021) The innocent mosquito? The environmental ethics of mosquito eradication. In Hall, M and Tamïr, D (eds), Mosquitopia. London: Routledge, pp. 195210. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003056034-17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wienhues, A and Deplazes-Zemp, A (2022) Otherness-based reasons for the protection of (bio)diversity. Environmental Ethics 44(2), 161184. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics202271341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, EO (1986) BioDiversity. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.Google Scholar
Winston, ML (1999) Nature Wars. People Vs. Pests. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
World Health Organization (2017) Ethical issues associated with vector-borne diseases. In Report of a WHO Scoping Meeting, Geneva, 23–24 February. Geneva: World Health Organization.Google Scholar

Author comment: The ethics of species extinctions — R0/PR1

Comments

Dear editors,

Thank you for taking our manuscript on the ethics of species extinctions again into consideration.

Review: The ethics of species extinctions — R0/PR2

Conflict of interest statement

Reviewer declares none.

Comments

Whether to publish this paper or not depends entirely on the goals of the journal.

This paper does an admirable job of surveying some of the current and historic literature in extinction ethics. It misses some of the nuances of the field, but that’s difficult to capture in a survey paper. That said, nothing in this paper is novel. The authors advance no new arguments, and do not critically engage with any of the work being done. Overall the paper is a useful tool for people looking to get a rough overview of the field in a western context, but doesn’t advance the conversation beyond this.

There are two significant amendments that I think need to be made before it could be published.

First, it would be useful to acknowledge the extensive environmental ethics that has been done in non-western contexts. This paper notes that it’s only looking at Anglophone literature, but more accurately it’s only considered traditional western environmental ethics. There’s a large number of non-western texts written in English, or that have now been translated, which are impactful on the field. A paragraph at least gesturing at what other work has been done outside of traditional western philosophy, and what sort of topics are covered would be good. Gary Snyder’s Practice of the Wild (1990) deals with species extinction and value from a native American perspective, for example.

Second, the paper would benefit from a slight restructuring. The discussion of risk in section 4 would be better put earlier in the paper, since it has themes which resonate with a number of other points. Instead, in Section 4, there ought to be an explicit section on artificial/assisted adaptation and migration, both of which are standard examples in the ethics literature of work done to mitigate and prevent extinction. While these topics are mentioned, they aren’t given the space they deserve in a review of extinction ethics.

A few other thoughts include that it might be worth mentioning the screw worm in the deliberate extinction section. There’s too much emphasis on diseases, which most people agree have a different set of ethical considerations to animals. Screw worms, which are actively being considered for deliberate extinction, would provide a stronger example of animal extinction alongside malaria-carrying mosquitoes.

I also recognise that while this paper has explicitly set-aside attempts to critically engage with the work being surveyed in this paper, it would be valuable in the conclusion to at least attempt to summarise any strengths or weaknesses observed. This would also increase the novelty of the paper beyond simple summary.

In all, the biggest weakness of this paper is that it doesn’t advance the conversation in any serious way. This is an overview, and if that’s the goal of the journal then it does an admirable job trying to cover significant ground.

Review: The ethics of species extinctions — R0/PR3

Conflict of interest statement

Reviewer declares none.

Comments

Fantastic overview of the Anglophone literature in environmental ethics that bears on efforts to achieve the deliberate extinction of a species. I learned much from it. The authors are right to underscore the complexity of the “concepts, arguments, and forms of analysis” relevant to these efforts.

One complexity overlooked here is what appears to be a widely accepted view among the public that the worth of different kinds of species varies depending roughly on where the species seems to fall in what theologians have sometimes called “the great chain of being.” For many people, the worth of a bacteria or virus species is intuitively less than that of an insect, and that of an insect less than that of a mammal. This may well be part of the reason that extinction of smallpox or polio does not seem concerning. So far as I am aware, this complexity is also overlooked in environmental ethics literature that directly discusses the ethics of extinction; however, it might have been to mentioned in the discussion “Understanding Extinction.” Indeed, among the terms whose definitions need examination is the very concept of “life,” since it is not entirely unclear what the status of viruses is.

Within the review of the environmental ethics literature, one point where I might take issue is over whether claims about the value of species quite captures the concerns that some environmental ethicists have expressed. I agree that this is the plausible place to start. Another way to approach environmental ethics and therefore the normative issues of deliberate extinction is through general principles or ideals about the human relationship to nature. The values-of-species approach typically starts with claims about the conditions that allow things to have value; the principle- or ideal-based approach asks more diffuse questions about moral attitudes toward nature in general or toward the human relationship to nature, or about human intervention into processes, laws, or general features of nature. In my reading, this is what Christopher Preston is thinking about when he laments human intrusion in “arrangements,” for example. It’s also one way of understanding Sylvan’s last-person-on-earth thought experiment: Sylvan can be understood as raising a very general question about “human chauvinism” and destruction. The questions at stake have to do, for example, with the desirability of human domination of nature or the importance of relations of respect or care for nature. I am not convinced that they can be rephrased strictly in terms of claims about the value that attaches to species; but if they can, the value of species is in some sense derivative from values found in other aspects of the human relationship to nature.

Recommendation: The ethics of species extinctions — R0/PR4

Comments

I have received two reviews of this manuscript. Both reviewers engaged with the manuscript in detail and each provides fair and constructive comments that could yield improvements to the manuscript without requiring extensive editing. Given the nature of the comments, I don’t see need for further review but would like the authors to consider and respond to the comments. I agree with Reviewer #1 that the manuscript would benefit from some stance taken by the manuscript (and its authors), even if only in the concluding paragraphs.

Decision: The ethics of species extinctions — R0/PR5

Comments

No accompanying comment.

Author comment: The ethics of species extinctions — R1/PR6

Comments

Please find our cover letter attached as a PDF.

Recommendation: The ethics of species extinctions — R1/PR7

Comments

I am satisfied that the authors addressed the reviewer comments and do not see a need for further review. I have a few small items that the authors can address when they send back a final version of the manuscript.

15: “ask” should be “asks”

41: I’ve usually seen this written as “pertaining to…”. I couldn’t quickly find an authoritative answer on the grammar, but please confirm this usage (here and elsewhere in the ms) is correct.

87: “authors that” should be “authors who”

122: I believe no-longer-existing should be hyphenated here.

187: argumentative is redundant and can be deleted here.

315: “Rolston’s” should be “Roltson” here.

459-460: With use of “not” early in the sentence, I believe this should be followed by either/or rather than neither/nor.

821: “that” should be “than”

Decision: The ethics of species extinctions — R1/PR8

Comments

No accompanying comment.