Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T11:38:18.007Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Weeding Out Flawed Versions of Shareholder Primacy: A Reflection on the Moral Obligations That Carry Over from Principals to Agents

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 August 2019

Santiago Mejia*
Affiliation:
Fordham University

Abstract:

The distinction between what I call nonelective obligations and discretionary obligations, a distinction that focuses on one particular thread of the distinction between perfect and imperfect duties, helps us to identify the obligations that carry over from principals to agents. Clarity on this issue is necessary to identify the moral obligations within “shareholder primacy” (i.e., “shareholder theory”), which conceives of managers as agents of shareholders. My main claim is that the principal-agent relation requires agents to fulfill nonelective obligations, but it does not always require (and sometimes actually prohibits) discharging discretionary obligations. I show that the requirement to fulfill nonelective obligations is more far-reaching than has been acknowledged by most defenders and critics of shareholder primacy. But I also show that managers are not bound by certain discretionary obligations like charity, showing that their moral obligations are more circumscribed than the obligations that apply to human beings in general.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Society for Business Ethics 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Arnold, Denis G. 2003. “Libertarian Theories of the Corporation and Global Capitalism.” Journal of Business Ethics 48 (2): 155–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. L. 1954. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. New York: Noonday Press.Google Scholar
Bakan, Joel. 2004. The Corporation: the Pathological Pursuit of Profit and Power. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Berle, Adolf, and Means, Gardiner C.. 1932. The Modern Corporation and Private Property. Chicago: The Macmillian Company.Google Scholar
Boatright, John R. 1994. “Fiduciary Duties and the Shareholder-Management Relation: Or, What’s so Special about Shareholders?Business Ethics Quarterly 4 (4): 393407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boatright, John R. 2009. Ethics and the Conduct of Business. New Jersey: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Bower, Joseph L., and Paine, Lynn S.. 2017. “The Error at the Heart of Corporate Leadership.” Harvard Business Review 95 (3): 5060.Google Scholar
Bowie, Norman E. 1999. Business Ethics: A Kantian Perspective. Malden: Wiley–Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bowie, Norman E. 2010. “A Kantian Approach to Business Ethics.” In A Companion to Business Ethics, edited by Frederick, Robert E., 316. Oxford: Wiley–Blackwell.Google Scholar
Brenkert, George G. 1992. “Private Corporations and Public Welfare.” Public Affairs Quarterly 6 (2): 155–68.Google Scholar
Brophy, Matthew. 2015. “Spirituality Incorporated: Including Convergent Spiritual Values in Business.” Journal of Business Ethics 132 (4): 779–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 1996a. “Perfecting Imperfect Duties: Collective Action to Create Moral Obligations.” Business Ethics Quarterly 6 (1): 2742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 1996b. “Toward a Theory of the Ethics of Bureaucratic Organizations.” Business Ethics Quarterly 6 (4): 419–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciepley, David. 2013. “Beyond Public and Private: Toward a Political Theory of the Corporation.” American Political Science Review 107 (1): 139–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corporate Watch. 2006. What’s Wrong With Corporate Social Responsibility? Technical report. London: Corporate Watch.Google Scholar
Cummiskey, David. 1996. Kantian Consequentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donaldson, Thomas. 1992. “The Language of International Corporate Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 2 (3): 271–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunfee, Thomas W. 2006. “Do Firms With Unique Competencies for Rescuing Victims of Human Catastrophes Have Special Obligations? Corporate Responsibility and the AIDS Catastrophe in Sub-Saharan Africa.” Business Ethics Quarterly 16 (2): 185210.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Easterbrook, Frank H., and Fischel, Daniel R.. 1982. “Antitrust Suits by Targets of Tender Offers.” Michigan Law Review 80 (6): 1155–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, R. Edward. 1998. “A Stakeholder Theory of the Modern Corporation.” In The Corporation and Its Stakeholders: Classic and Contemporary Readings, edited by Clarkson, Max B. E., 125–38. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, R. Edward, Harrison, Jeffrey S., Wicks, Andrew C., Parmar, Bidhan, and de Colle, Simone. 2010. Stakeholder Theory The State of the Art. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1970. “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profits.” New York Times Magazine, September 13, 1970.Google Scholar
Ghoshal, Sumantra. 2005. “Bad Management Theories Are Destroying Good Management Practices.” Academy of Management Learning & Education 4 (1): 7591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. 1991. “Business Ethics and Stakeholder Analysis.” Business Ethics Quarterly 1 (1): 5373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodpaster, Kenneth E., and Matthews, John B.. 1982. “Can a Corporation Have a Conscience.” Harvard Business Review 60 (1): 132–41.Google Scholar
Hansmann, Henry. 1988. “Ownership of the Firm.” Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization 4 (2): 267304.Google Scholar
Hansmann, Henry, and Kraakman, Reinier. 2001. “The End of History for Corporate Law.” Georgetown Law Journal 89 (2): 439–68.Google Scholar
Hansmann, Henry, and Kraakman, Reinier. 2012. “Reflections on the End of History for Corporate Law.” In The Convergence of Corporate Governance Promise and Prospects, edited by Rasheed, Abdul A. and Yoshikawa, Toru, 3248. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, Oliver, and Zingales, Luigi. 2017a. “Companies Should Maximize Shareholder Welfare Not Market Value.” Journal of Law, Finance, and Accounting 2 (2): 247–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, Oliver, and Zingales, Luigi. 2017b. “Serving Shareholders Doesn’t Mean Putting Profit Above All Else.” Harvard Business Review 1: 26.Google Scholar
Hartman, Edwin M. 2013. Virtue in Business: Conversations With Aristotle. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hasnas, John. 1998. “The Normative Theories of Business Ethics: A Guide for the Perplexed.” Business Ethics Quarterly 8 (1): 1942.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2006. “Business Ethics without Stakeholders.” Business Ethics Quarterly 16 (4): 533–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2007. “An Adversarial Ethic for Business: Or When Sun-Tzu Met the Stakeholder.” Journal of Business Ethics 72 (4): 359–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2009. “The Uses and Abuses of Agency Theory.” Business Ethics Quarterly 19 (4): 497528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2010. Economics Without Illusions: Debunking the Myths of Modern Capitalism. New York: Broadway Books.Google Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2011. “Business Ethics and the ‘End of History’ in Corporate Law.” Journal of Business Ethics 102 (1): 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2014. Morality, Competition and the Firm: the Market Failures Approach to Business Ethics. New York: Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, Joseph, Moriarty, Jeffrey, and Norman, Wayne. 2010. “Business Ethics and (or as) Political Philosophy.” Business Ethics Quarterly 20 (3): 427–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herman, Barbara. 1993. “Mutual Aid and Respect for Persons.” In The Practice of Moral Judgment, 4572. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hessen, Robert. 1979. “A New Concept of Corporations: A Contractual and Private Property Model.” Hastings Law Journal 30, 1327–50.Google Scholar
Hill, Thomas E Jr.. 1971. “Kant on Imperfect Duty and Supererogation.” Kant-Studien 62: 5576.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Thomas E Jr.. 2002. “Meeting Needs and Doing Favors.” In Human Welfare and Moral Worth, 201–43. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hsieh, Nien-he. 2009. “Does Global Business Have a Responsibility to Promote Just Institutions?Business Ethics Quarterly 19 (2): 251–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hsieh, Nien-hê. 2004. “The Obligations of Transnational Corporations: Rawlsian Justice and the Duty of Assistance.” Business Ethics Quarterly 14 (4): 643–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hsieh, Nien-hê. 2017a. “Corporate Moral Agency, Positive Duties, and Purpose.” In The Moral Responsibility of Firms, edited by Orts, Eric W. and Smith, Craig, 188205. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hsieh, Nien-hê. 2017b. “The Responsibilities and Role of Business in Relation to Society: Back to Basics?Business Ethics Quarterly 27 (2): 293314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ireland, Paddy. 1999. “Company Law and the Myth of Shareholder Ownership.” Modern Law Review 62 (1): 3257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, Michael C. 2002. “Value Maximization, Stakeholder Theory, and the Corporate Objective Function.” Business Ethics Quarterly 12 (2): 235–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, Michael C., and Meckling, William H.. 1976. “Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure.” Journal of Financial Economics 3 (4): 305–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaler, John. 2003. “Differentiating Stakeholder Theories.” Journal of Business Ethics 46 (1): 7183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Gregor, Mary J.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kochan, Thomas. 2002. “Addressing the Crisis of Confidence in Corporations: Root Causes, Victims and Strategies.” Academy of Management Perspectives 16 (3): 139–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegstein, Hasko von. 2016. “Professionalism, Agency, and Market Failures.” Business Ethics Quarterly 26 (4): 445–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langtry, Bruce. 1994. “Stakeholders and the Moral Responsibilities of Business.” Business Ethics Quarterly 4 (4): 431–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lea, David. 2004. “The Imperfect Nature of Corporate Responsibilities to Stakeholders.” Business Ethics Quarterly 14 (2): 201–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mansell, Samuel. 2013. “Shareholder Theory and Kant’s ‘Duty of Beneficence.’ Journal of Business Ethics 117 (3): 583–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mansell, Samuel. 2015. Capitalism, Corporations and the Social Contract. A Critique of Stakeholder Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Marcoux, Alexei M. 2003. “A Fiduciary Argument against Stakeholder Theory.” Business Ethics Quarterly 13 (1): 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahon, Christopher. 1981. “Morality and the Invisible Hand.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 10 (3): 247–77.Google Scholar
Moriarty, Jeffrey. 2019. “On the Origin, Content, and Relevance of the Market Failures Approach.” Journal of Business Ethics. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s1055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norman, Wayne. 2011. “Business Ethics as Self-Regulation: Why Principles That Ground Regulations Should Be Used to Ground Beyond Compliance Norms as Well.” Journal of Busisness Ethics 102 (1): 4357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ohreen, David E., and Petry, Roger A.. 2012. “Imperfect Duties and Corporate Philanthropy: A Kantian Approach.” Journal of Business Ethics 106 (3): 367–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rainbolt, George. 2000. “Perfect and Imperfect Obligations.” Philosophical Studies 98 (3): 233–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodin, David. 2005. “The Ownership Model of Business Ethics.” Metaphilosophy 36 (1/2): 163–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schneewind, J. B. 1990. “The Misfortunes of Virtue.” Ethics 101 (1): 4263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, S. Andrew. 2014. “Imperfect Duties, Group Obligations, and Beneficence.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (5): 557–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharplin, Arthur, and Phelps, Lonnie D.. 1989. “A Stakeholder Apologetic for Management.” Business & Professional Ethics Journal 8 (2): 4153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, Abraham. 2018. “Justice Failure: Efficiency and Equality in Business Ethics.” Journal of Business Ethics 149 (1): 97115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinberg, Etye. 2017. “The Inapplicability of the Market-Failures Approach in a Non-Ideal World.” Ethics Journal Review 5 (5): 2834.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sternberg, Elaine. 2000. Just Business: Business Ethics In Action . Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sternberg, Elaine. 2010. “The Need for Realism in Business Ethics.” Reason Papers 31: 3348.Google Scholar
Stohr, Karen. 2011. “Kantian Beneficence and the Problem of Obligatory Aid.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (1): 4567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stout, Lynn. 2012. The Shareholder Value Myth. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Publishers.Google Scholar
Strudler, Alan. 2017. “What to Do with Corporate Wealth.” Journal of Political Philosophy 25 (1): 108–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Target. 2012. “$4 Million Every Week: A Brief History of Target’s Community Giving.” October 30, 2012. https://corporate.target.com/article/2012/10/4-million-every-week-a-brief-history-of-Target-s-c.Google Scholar
Von Kriegstein, Hasko. 2015. “Shareholder Primacy and Deontology.” Business and Society Review 120, no. 3: 465–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1981. “Persons, Character and Morality.” In Moral Luck , 1–19. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, and Smart, J. J. C.. 1973. Utilitarianism for & Against. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar