Hostname: page-component-f554764f5-246sw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-22T23:28:37.648Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Egophoricity in Central Stau copular clauses

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 April 2025

Sami Honkasalo*
Affiliation:
University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article demonstrates that the Central Stau language (Horpa < Gyalrongic < Sino-Tibetan/Trans-Himalayan) possesses a binary egophoricity contrast in its copular system in affirmative clauses not described and analysed in detail before. It examines the functions of the egophoric copula ŋu and its non-egophoric counterpart ŋə. Of these, the former signals the relevant speech act participant’s personal involvement, epistemic authority or a portrayed stance of a close bond in the proposition. Despite the differences in their functions and differing prototypical domains of use, reflecting patterns of “canonical” egophoricity, the choice between the copulas shows great flexibility and frequently reflects how the speakers wish to encode their epistemic stance. In brief, situation-dependent discourse pragmatics, rather than grammatical person encoded by the copular subject, determines copular use in Stau. The article thus concurs with other recent research on egophoricity that highlights the versatility of this epistemic category.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of SOAS University of London.

1. Introduction

This article investigates copular clauses in the Central Stau language (Horpa < West Gyalrongic < Gyalrongic < Sino-Tibetan/Trans-Himalayan) (henceforth Stau).Footnote 1 With the help of primary source materials, and a focus on epistemicity, it argues that the copular clauses manifest an egophoric contrast not discussed and analysed in these terms and to a sufficient extent in earlier research. The introduction defines the goals of the article (1.1), briefly discusses its sources and methodology (1.2) and concludes by laying out the structure of the article (1.3).

1.1. Goals of the article

This fieldwork-based article offers an analysis of egophoricity in Stau copular clauses. It builds on earlier and currently rapidly growing West Gyalrongic scholarship, such as Gates (Reference Gates2021) on Central Stau, Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2019) on Eastern Geshiza and Tunzhi (2019) on Zhangda Northwestern Stau copular systems.

The article has the following three primary goals. First, in order to lay the foundations for later analysis and the arguments, it identifies the copular forms and their argument indexation properties in Stau. The findings are compared with the interpretations of earlier research. Second, by analysing the use of the Stau copulas, the article demonstrates that the distribution of the affirmative copulas exhibits an intersubjective phenomenon analysable with the notion of egophoricity. Finally, with accompanying illustrative examples, it describes the use and functional domains of both the egophoric and non-egophoricFootnote 2 copulas in Stau. It also compares the system of Stau with “canonical” egophoricity established in the first wave of egophoricity research and with the principles of “flexible” egophoricity gaining focus in more recent scholarship.

Egophoricity has been researched intensively in Sino-Tibetan in recent decades, although the grammatical notion is now receiving increasing attention outside the language family as well. Besides the well-known cases of the Tibetic languages with almost universal egophoricity (see Tournadre and Suzuki Reference Tournadre and Suzuki2023: 416), egophoricity is attested in various other branches of the language family, such as Himalayish (e.g. Newar, see Hale Reference Hale and Trail1980), “Qiangic” (e.g. Wadu Pumi, see Daudey Reference Daudey2014) and Sinitic (e.g. Wutun, see Sandman Reference Sandman2016).

Egophoricity in West Gyalrongic, however, remains a neglected topic, both in terms of the copular systems and more generally in grammatical investigations of the relevant languages. Also, the simultaneous presence of argument indexation and egophoricity is typologically very rare, and the Gyalrongic branch of Sino-Tibetan constitutes the only case with fully fledged person indexation and egophoricity coexisting in the language family (Jacques Reference Jacques2019: 515–16). As argued in the article, this applies to Stau as well. While earlier studies report no egophoricity in the language, its relatively complex argument indexation system has been described in detail by Gates (Reference Gates2021) and Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2020). In sum, this article addresses the existing lacuna in current research and, at the same time, aims to expand our knowledge about egophoricity and copular behaviour in Horpa languages. As the brief comparison towards the end of the article suggests, egophoricity may be present more broadly among the Horpa languages.

1.2. Sources and methodology

In addition to the author’s fieldwork in the Stau homeland, most of the source materials on which the article builds have been collected ex situ in India where Stau exile communities reside. All research partners in India have left the Stau homeland (Ch. 道孚县, Tib. rta’u rdzong) as adult native speakers and continue to use the language daily. It goes without saying that while working with exile communities is not free from risk, the form of Stau that appears in this article is both grammatically and lexically highly homogeneous with other existing descriptions of the language, including Gates (Reference Gates2021). In addition to staying in communities with other Stau speakers whenever this is feasible, the exiled Stau frequently take advantage of the possibilities offered by smartphone applications, such as the Chinese WeChat (微信), to stay in touch with other Stau speakers. Such activities clearly support language maintenance among Stau migrants. The situation, however, differs strikingly among the ethnic Stau born abroad, among whom the intergenerational transmission of Stau is now at risk.

The principal Stau partners in this research project originate from Poxiu (Ch. 坡修, Tib. phog sho) and Yepo (Ch. 也坡, Tib. gyas phyogs) villages of Mazi (Ch. 麻孜, Tib. ma zur) in the Stau homeland. To indicate their respective contributions in the examples, the former is coded as (P) and the latter as (Y). The examples offered in this article are a fortuitous side-product of the author’s morphosyntactic and lexicographic study of the Stau language,Footnote 3 rather than materials collected with the specific aim of copular clause research.

In collecting the source materials, in addition to Stau, the author has used Dharamshala Central Tibetan as a lingua franca. The fact that Central Tibetan possesses egophoricity makes it convenient to explain certain features of the Stau copular system through this auxiliary language. On rare occasions, Y also expressed some of his insights in English. Due to its well-known risks, the article does not apply translation elicitation whereby the research partners would be asked to translate sentences from any language into Stau as the main method of investigation. Translation from Tibetan to Stau, however, has been used to further clarify and illustrate contexts where a phenomenon has been identified from primary data. In addition, acceptability judgements have been frequently implemented and indicated as such in the examples. As the article argues, egophoricity in Stau is largely a discourse-pragmatic phenomenon, and the acceptability judgements should be seen from this perspective.

1.3. Structure of the article

This article has the following structure. Section 2 addresses the theoretical key concepts the article relies on, namely egophoricity and territory of information. Then, Section 3 offers an overview of the copular system in Stau and discusses earlier studies of copulas in the language, highlighting existing issues that the article aims to tackle. In turn, Section 4, which forms the core of the article, investigates the use of the two Stau copulas and reflects the findings against “canonical” egophoricity and discourse-pragmatic based stance taking. Section 5 compares the copular system of Stau with those of other Gyalrongic languages, arguing for the need to pay attention to egophoricity in future research. Finally, Section 6 concludes the article by summarizing its key findings and arguments.

2. Key concepts: egophoricity and territory of information

This section is dedicated to the two key concepts this article relies on: territory of information (2.1) and egophoricity (2.2).

2.1. Territory of information

The article follows the pioneering study of the Japanese linguist Akio Kamio concerning “territory of information” as an epistemic and interpersonal notion. As defined by Kamio (Reference Kamio1997: 2), information that speakers consider “proximal” to themselves falls into their territory of information. For instance, it is natural for a speaker to say that she is 36 years old and lives with her two children in Daofu, the Stau homeland. In many languages, however, such a statement requires a highly specific pragmatic condition to be uttered in the second person, a potentially unacceptable intrusion into the epistemic territory in which one has no authority. Analogous to territorial animals (or pre-modern states and other political entities), participants in a linguistic discourse constantly track their own and other participants’ territories of information that are continuously negotiated. The “heartland” in territories of information, such as a speaker’s knowledge regarding his name, identity and other matters to which he has primary epistemic access and high epistemic authority, remain uncontested most of the time. On the other hand, more peripheral territory can be gained, lost, shared or even trigger a “territorial conflict” (Honkasalo Reference Honkasalo2023: 206; see also Bristol and Rossano Reference Bristol and Rossano2020 on the hierarchical structure of epistemic territory). In all, as a metaphor, the notion of “territory of information” aids in conceptualizing matters of epistemic authority and primacy relevant for this article.

2.2. Egophoricity

Also known as conjunct/disjunct marking in earlier research, “egophoricity” in broad terms refers to the linguistic encoding of “personal knowledge, experience, or involvement of a conscious self” (San Roque et al. Reference San Roque, Floyd, Norcliffe, Floyd, Norcliffe and Roque2018: 2).Footnote 4 Phenomena with some or all of these characteristics are sometimes discussed under the label of evidentiality (i.e. grammaticalized encoding of the information source; see Aikhenvald Reference Aikhenvald2004), and the mutual relationship of evidentiality and egophoricity remains debated. The article considers evidentiality and egophoricity as separate grammatical categories that nevertheless possess similar discourse functions, a view adopted from Sandman and Grzech’s (Reference Sandman and Grzech2022) insightful comparison of Wutun (divergent Sinitic) and Upper Napo Kichwa (Quechuan).Footnote 5 Similarly, egophoricity should be regarded as distinct from person marking, despite some functional overlap between the two (Bergqvist and Kittilä Reference Bergqvist and Kittilä2017, Reference Bergqvist, Kittilä, Bergqvist and Kittilä2020: 3).

While the phenomenon is also attested in other language families, Sino-Tibetan languages form the context in which egophoricity has been studied most extensively. A pair of examples from Central Tibetan below briefly illustrates the key principle of “canonical” egophoricity. In (1), the speaker uses the egophoric copula yin, since he discusses his self-identity, and thus has higher epistemic authority, privileged access to knowledge and personal involvement in the matter expressed by the proposition. On the other hand, in (2), the speaker uses the non-egophoric form red, since the identity of a third person outside the EGO of the speaker is discussed and the four conditions listed for (1) above are not fulfilled, at least not in full and to the same extent.

3. Stau copulas and previous research

A copular clause includes a copular subject (CS) and a copular complement (CC) that, in addition to a “zero copula”, may be linked with a copula, the formal properties of which vary across languages of the world. Stau is a language with compulsory copular use where the copulas manifest the morphosyntactic properties of verbs. The Stau copular system includes three copulas: the affirmative copulas ŋə and ŋu together with the suppletiveFootnote 6 negative copula mɲæmjæ, as identified by Gates (Reference Gates2021: 379) in his descriptive grammar of Mazi Stau.Footnote 7 Wengmu (Reference Wengmu2019: 173) also addresses the copular system of Stau by identifying ŋə as an affirmative and mja as a negative copula in the language, although her grammatical treatise only briefly deals with the copulas. In addition, Wengmu’s examples include a form Gates and this article classify as copula, namely ŋu (3), but no further explanation regarding this form is offered. In sum, prior to this article, Gates’s (Reference Gates2021: 379–84) analysis of Mazi Stau copulas presents the most extensive analysis of the copular system and copular clauses in Stau.

In Gates’s (Reference Gates2021: 379) analysis, ŋu is termed as an SAP copula, indexing “first and second person singular with ŋu, first person plural with ŋõ Footnote 8 and second person plural with ŋun”. For instance, in (4), the first person pronoun is SAP, which consequently triggers the use of the copula ŋu. On the other hand, in (5), the proposition falls outside the scope of SAPs, with the result that the non-SAP copula ŋə must be used.

In sum, the SAP copula is restricted to speech-act participants, namely, first and second person.Footnote 9 While the singular forms are identical, a contrast arises in the plural forms. Gates (Reference Gates2021: 261) does not illustrate with paradigmatic examples the argument indexation properties of the other two analysed copulas, namely ŋə and mjæ, although he states that copulas belong to the verb class 2b (discussed below) in Stau, a notation already sufficient for grasping how the copulas conjugate. To help the reader, the full paradigm of the interpretation for ŋu is offered in Table 1.

Table 1. Gates’s (Reference Gates2021) analysis of the argument indexation properties of the SAP copula ŋu

On the one hand, Gates’s analysis of ŋu with a focus on SAPs gets close to the egophoric interpretation of this article without applying the term and qualifies for a foundational insight in Stau copular studies. Markers in egophoric systems interact with the speech-act roles (Sandman and Grzech Reference Sandman and Grzech2022: 82; Bergqvist and Kittilä Reference Bergqvist and Kittilä2017: 19; see also Dahl Reference Dahl2000 on a broader and slightly different approach to egophoricity as a discourse phenomenon). On the other hand, the analysis results in an anomalous and irregular intransitive verb with number contrasts in addition to person contrasts not attested elsewhere in Central Horpa.Footnote 10

Three primary explanations may be offered. First, the Stau language is known for internal variation, and Gates’s sources, which differ from those of this author, might explain the copula’s behaviour.Footnote 11 Second, copulas often behave in idiosyncratic ways, which may explain the peculiar argument indexation properties claimed for ŋu. Discussing copulas from a typological perspective, Dixon (Reference Dixon2010: 178) states that they frequently manifest irregular behaviour. Finally, as this article proposes, it is possible to reanalyse the copular system in an alternative way. As an unintended side product of this analysis, the copulas also appear as completely regular verbs fully compatible with the Horpa verb classification system proposed by Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2020).

In addition to the SAP forms, Gates (Reference Gates2021: 379) shows that SAP copula ŋu also appears with third person copular subjects, as in (6). This apparent distributional discrepancy is explained in terms of the SAPs where “I” as the speaker is part of the third person’s company. The copular subject, however, falls outside the scope of SAPs in terms of strictly grammatical encoding. Similarly to Gates’s realization, this article will demonstrate that discourse pragmatic factors, rather than independent morphosyntactic rules, ultimately determine the use of the two copulas in many instances where variation is possible. Finally, in Gates’s terminology, if the non-SAP copula ŋə were used in (6) it would imply that “I” as the speaker is not part of the third person’s company.

This article offers an alternative analysis of the copular system from the viewpoint of egophoricity and territory of information. Stau has three copulas: affirmative egophoric, affirmative non-egophoric and their negative counterpart with no egophoricity distinctions. Table 2 summarizes the existing copular forms and their argument indexation properties, as present in the source materials of this article. As the table demonstrates, egophoricity in Stau exists as a binary system in affirmative clauses, egophoricity distinction being neutralized in negative clauses. This manifests a typological tendency where fewer grammatical distinctions appear in negative than in affirmative clauses (see Miestamo and van der Auvera Reference Miestamo and van der Auwera2011 for the neutralization of grammatical distinctions in the negative).

Table 2. The forms of the copulas in Stau

Using Honkasalo’s (Reference Honkasalo2020) classification of Horpa verbs, the affirmative egophoric copula ŋu lacks any argument indexation properties and always surfaces in the shape of ŋu, regardless of the person and number of the copular subject, as in (7–11). Consequently, it belongs to the intransitive verb class 1b with other non-stative verbs lacking any argument indexation, such as “inanimate existential verb” and sko “to manage, be able” (see Honkasalo Reference Honkasalo2020).

On the other hand, the affirmative non-egophoric copula ŋə belongs to the intransitive verb class 2b, which means that it indexes the person of the copular subject but not its number, like verbs, such as dʑi “animate existential verb” and ɕə “to go”. This results in a paradigm of three distinct forms (12–14).

The negative copula mɲæ with no egophoricity distinctions also belongs to the verb class 2b. As Table 2 demonstrates, and as expected of class 2b verbs, the Stau varieties analysed in this article generally distinguish between first and non-first (namely, second and third) person in intransitive scenarios, which also applies to the negative copula. From this, it follows that most intransitive verbs lack a distinction between second and third person in their argument indexation properties. As argued by Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2020) addressing the reduction of paradigmatic forms, this results from a partial loss of argument indexation marking in second person forms historically encoded with the eroding -n, which often renders the second and third person forms identical in intransitive verbs. The second person marking is retained most faithfully with the imperative and prohibitive forms (Honkasalo Reference Honkasalo2020), as illustrated by (15) where -n indexes the second person.

The negative copula, however, cannot be used in commands (16). As a result, no contexts exist where the second person argument indexation morpheme -n attaches to it, which results in slight formal asymmetry when seen against the copula ŋə with three distinct forms in its paradigm.

4. Use of the copulas

This section forms the core of this article; it describes and analyses the use of the Stau copulas. It is divided into the following sections: egophoricity and person (4.1), egophoricity and the sensory evidential -rə (4.2), egophoricity and the knowable attributes of the first person (4.3), egophoricity and personal relations (4.4), egophoricity with objects and entities (4.5) and egophoricity and general facts (4.6).

4.1. Egophoricity and person

Stau speakers use the egophoric copula ŋu when they wish to express personal involvement or privileged epistemic authority, also known as epistemic primacy (“the right to know and to discuss something”; see Stivers et al. Reference Stivers, Mondada, Steensig, Stivers, Mondada and Steensig2011: 13), regarding the proposition, the information of which lies in the territory of information of the SAP whose perspective is adopted. In practice, this is often the first person, the primary domain in all models of “canonical” egophoricity. To illustrate, stating one’s personal identity qualifies as something about which the speaker him or herself has the highest epistemic authority (17).

The non-egophoric copula also appears with the first person. When no evidentials are present, the difference between the two affirmative copulas in this context remains minute, and in many circumstances, the two are interchangeable. The major difference lies in the projected epistemic stance, namely what kind of attitude the speaker expresses regarding the information of the proposition. It is proposed that while (17) emphasizes that being a lama is closely connected to the speaker’s EGO and the speaker thus highlights his personal involvement, the use of the non-egophoric copula presents the same information in a more matter-of-fact fashion (18).Footnote 14

As discussed earlier, the egophoric distinctions are neutralized in negative clauses. Both copular clauses are thus negated identically with the negative copula in its dedicated first person form (19).

The mind of the second person remains inaccessible to cognitive outsiders. Consequently, it is more common to ask questions than to make statements when addressing the second person in the Horpa languages. Stau second-person questions manifest a pattern of “canonical” egophoricity termed the “anticipation rule” by Tournadre and LaPolla (Reference Tournadre and LaPolla2014: 244),Footnote 15 also known as “perspective shift” (San Roque et al. Reference San Roque, Floyd, Norcliffe, Floyd, Norcliffe and Roque2018). If the topic of interrogation is perceived to lie firmly inside the territory of information of the addressee’s EGO, the egophoric copula is chosen in anticipation of the addressee’s epistemic perspective, as in (20, 21). In the affirmative, the addressee will most likely equally answer with the egophoric copula, as illustrated above in (17).

The negative copula is not compatible with the interrogative prefix æ- (22), resulting in structural asymmetry in negative questions. Instead, infrequently occurring negative questions must be formed with the interrogative enclitic =a, as in (23).

While it was stated above that questions, rather than statements, are more common in the second person, statements also occur. This is possible in circumstances where the information is not exclusively in the epistemic territory of the addressee, such as describing the addressee with adjective copular complements. In (24), the speaker states a value judgement concerning the addressee and uses the non-egophoric copula. In contrast, (25) does the same with the egophoric copula. Again, the pragmatic effect of the two differs and is explainable by means of projecting a different epistemic stance, and (24) takes the form of a general statement paying no attention to the interpersonal relationship between the speaker and the addressee. Conversely, (25) is deemed pragmatically ungrammatical unless the addressee has a particularly strong relationship with the speaker, such as being a family member of a close friend.Footnote 17 In sum, the speaker has epistemic authority to judge the addressee’s character by using the egophoric form only in cases of strong personal involvement and personal bonds.

Both the egophoric and non-egophoric forms occur with the third person as the copular subject, which proves that the contrast between the copulas in Stau should not be interpreted from the viewpoint of person marking/argument indexation of the grammatically encoded SAPs.Footnote 18 In (26), the speaker knows that there is no money in his pocket. If, on the other hand, this comes as a sudden realization, for instance by putting one’s hand inside the pocket to take out the money that should be there but failing to do so, the egophoric form is deemed ungrammatical. Instead, the non-egophoric copula must be used with the sensory evidential suffix (discussed below), as in (27).

4.2. Egophoricity and the sensory evidential -rə

Stau exhibits both grammaticalized egophoricity and evidentiality, which makes the language important for the study of these categories. Moreover, the two interact with each other.Footnote 19 Before analysing the interplay between the copulas and the sensory evidential, it is necessary to offer an overview of the latter in Stau. The sensory evidential is used for marking information that prototypically lies outside the EGO and is gained through the senses, as in (28) where it indicates that the speaker saw the flying bat.Footnote 20

In addition, the evidential possesses a special use with information directly in the domain of the EGO where it encodes “endophatic processes”, a term coined by Tournadre (Reference Tournadre1996a: 226; Reference Tournadre and Guentchéva1996b: 206–07) to refer to internal sensations that cannot be observed directly by outsiders, such as such as hunger (29), thirst (30), pain (31) and fear (32).

Finally, the sensory evidential accompanies states and actions, over which the subject has no direct control, such as the mental activities of liking and understanding something, as in (33) and (34) (cf. also Honkasalo Reference Honkasalo2019: 603 on Geshiza).

Returning to the interplay of the copulas and evidentiality, the use of the sensory evidential suffix -rə encoding information received through the senses renders the statements (17–19) ungrammatical (35–37). Personal identity belongs to the core of one’s territory of information, yet the sensory evidential typically encodes information that one has received externally through the senses. As a result, the egophoric copula ŋu is incompatible with the sensory evidential. While it is also pragmatically ungrammatical with the non-egophoric form in (36), the article will subsequently demonstrate that contexts exist where the two are compatible.

Table 3 summarizes the compatibility of the copulas with the sensory evidential suffix -rə. As can be seen, all restrictions concern the affirmative egophoric copula only, since both the affirmative non-egophoric copula ŋə and the negative copula mɲæ may host the evidential suffix -rə in all their personal forms.

Table 3. Compatibility of the copular forms with the sensory evidential suffix -rə

To illustrate briefly, in (38), a mother comments on her child’s tendency to bite. Rather than emphasizing the close connection between the mother and the child, discussed in the next section, the focus is found in the mother’s sensory observation of her child’s behaviour expressed by the suffix -rə. In turn, in (39), the speaker expresses a generally known fact that cuckoos start appearing in Daofu in April and marks this piece of information with the sensory evidential suffix that here plays a broader role of encoding general knowledge, discussed at the end of this section.

To conclude, Gates (Reference Gates2021: 383) states that the sensory evidential obligatorily accompanies the copula ŋə in non-SAP copula verb constructions, which roughly correspond to the non-egophoric copular clauses of this article (see Section 3).Footnote 21 Our investigation confirms this distributional insight. At the very least, it is a very strong tendency. Exclamations where the modal discourse enclitic =væ can be thought to replace the sensory evidential constitute the only potentially unambiguous exception in the source materials, as in (40), but it remains to be analysed further whether such exclamations can be classified as canonical copular clauses.

In any case, the frequent co-occurrence of the non-egophoric copula and the sensory evidential in the third person non-SAP forms arises naturally from the fact that since the speaker admits lacking direct epistemic access or personal involvement by not using the egophoric copula, an evidential is needed to specify the source of information.

4.3. Egophoricity and the knowable attributes of the first person

Sometimes personal information exists in the territory of information of the EGO, but it is still relatively accessible to the addressee, which downplays the EGO’s privileged epistemic access. Thus, such information cannot be considered to be located at the core of the territory of the speaker, but more at the periphery, with potentially some territorial overlap with the addressee. In such cases, the Stau copular complement is typically an adjective characterizing a property of the copular subject. To illustrate, while one’s stature or body weight are closely connected with one’s EGO, they are also something observable to outsiders. Consequently, the speaker may adopt a non-EGO perspective to describe his or her stature (41), but equally, the egophoric copula may be used in this context (42), depending on one’s stance whether to underline a strong connection with the EGO or not.

In (43), a speaking trickster rabbit in a well-known folktale warns the boy protagonist that he (the rabbit) is very heavy. The utterance is encoded with the non-egophoric form of the copula. As it happens, the same story has been recorded by Gates (Reference Gates2021) where the egophoric copula appears at the same point in the folktale (44). In sum, the property of weight is something that can often be observed outwardly, at least to an extent, which justifies the alternation attested here.

4.4. Egophoricity and personal relations

When the bond between people is represented as very strong, the use of the egophoric copula ŋu can be extended to other people outside the EGO, encoded as third person forms grammatically. This use, going beyond “canonical” egophoricity, corresponds to Gawne’s (Reference Gawne, Gawne and Hill2017) “broad scope” of egophoricity.

The “broad scope” use occurs particularly frequently with one’s family members in Stau. In (45), the speaker discusses her maternal aunt who is skilled at knitting sweaters. Although the maternal aunt is clearly distinct from the speaking SAP and a separate person, the use of the egophoric form emphasizes the closeness of the relationship between the two, which grants the speaker epistemic authority to discuss her aunt with the egophoric coding of knowledge.

There are limits to the usability of the egophoric forms when discussing people, related to the notions of epistemic upgrading and downgrading. Rather than being binary (i.e. either/or), epistemic access may manifest to varying degrees, and speakers may thus “upgrade” or “downgrade” the access they claim, e.g. by tag questions and uncertainty markers (maybe, probably) in English (Stivers et al. Reference Stivers, Mondada, Steensig, Stivers, Mondada and Steensig2011: 12).

In (46), the husband of the addressee is praised for his skills as a carpenter. Since the husband and his skills clearly fall within the territory of information of the addressee, rather than the speaker, the non-egophoric copula (46) and not the egophoric copula (47) must be used so that the speaker does not intrude into the epistemic territory of the addressee and claim it as her own. In other words, the speaker lacks epistemic authority to state (47), which renders it pragmatically incorrect in most circumstances.Footnote 23 In sum, the speaker “downgrades” her own authority by choosing the non-egophoric copula.

When discussing personal relations, the choice of the copula serves as a mechanism of stance taking, for which I borrow Häsler’s (Reference Häsler1999: 151–52) terms “strong empathy” and “weak empathy”.Footnote 24 Both (48) and (49) below convey the moral judgement that the speaker’s friend is a bad person. The choice of the copula, however, conveys additional information concerning the speaker’s relationship with the addressee. With the egophoric form, the speaker wishes to express that the relationship between the two is strong, a manifestation of strong empathy. Despite his or her flaws, the person remains the speaker’s dear good friend. On the other hand, adopting the non-egophoric copular form indicates that the friend is not particularly close to the speaker, a manifestation of weak empathy.

The example pair (50) and (51) offers a similar scenario, but this time concerning the territory of information of the second person addressee. With (50), the speaker takes the addressee’s viewpoint by anticipating the answer with the egophoric copula. In contrast, the same question can be posed with the use of the non-egophoric copula that does not anticipate the addressee’s viewpoint.

The Stau language has the means to simultaneously mark a piece of information as inside the speaker’s privileged territory of information and yet downplay the closeness of the personal relationship involved. In (52), by using the egophoric copula, the speaker expresses that Akhu Stonpa is a great trickster. Since he, however, is a legendary folklore figure, attempts to use only the egophoric form are deemed as incorrect (53). In such a case, Stau speakers interpret the sentence as incorrect due to its pragmatic implausibility. The speaker claims direct and personal knowledge of Akhu Stonpa who is a legendary folk hero and not a real person who is currently alive.Footnote 25

To gain pragmatic acceptance among Stau speakers, (52) requires the addition of the suffix -gə to the predicate verb. The suffix plays a modal function of distancing and uncertainty in the utterance. While by using the egophoric copula the speaker claims epistemic authority and deep personal knowledge of Akhu Stonpa, most likely through having heard many folk stories, the suffix -gə indicates that the person has not directly met Akhu Stonpa and thus cannot be quite sure of matters concerning him. The phenomenon can be further illustrated by two replies to a common Stau question (54). In the first reply without -gə, the speaker implies that she has met her mother and is thus sure that she is doing well. On the other hand, the reply with the suffix -gə insinuates that the person supposes that her mother is doing well, but she cannot be fully sure, since she has not met her for some time, which impedes full certainty.

4.5. Egophoricity with objects and entities

As has become increasingly clear, while the egophoric forms typically occur in the context of the first person, they also surface with the second and third persons because of stance projection. This goes beyond human relationships and applies equally to objects and other more abstract entities. To illustrate, the speaker discusses her shoes with the egophoric form in (57), since this underlines the connection between the object and its owner. The shoes were most likely bought by her and, in any case, she is the one who wears them and has deep personal knowledge about them. Consequently, the use of the egophoric copula instead of the non-egophoric copula emphasizes the bond between the object and its owner.

In (58), the speaker originates from Daofu, and can thus be expected to know her home thoroughly. Consequently, the statement is coded with the egophoric copular form. On the other hand, the non-egophoric counterpart of this sentence in (59) can be uttered by an outsider, such as the author, who is not a native Daofu, but nevertheless possesses some limited knowledge of the place. The use of the non-egophoric form demonstrates to the addressee the speaker’s weaker connection with the place. Again, the choice of the copula enables the speakers to express the degree of their epistemic authority and bond with the information offered in the proposition.

In (60), the speaker takes the addressee’s perspective and asks about her village with the egophoric form. This is because, in the case of an (affirmative) answer, the egophoric copula is expected to be used.

The example pair (61) and (62) provides a further point of comparison. Both utterances convey the meaning that eggplant dishes are somewhat tasty. In (61), however, the speaker has cooked eggplant dishes before so that her familiarity with the dish justifies coding the utterance with the egophoric form. This highlights the speaker’s involvement in the cooking process, resulting in privileged knowledge and authority to discuss the taste, unlike someone who cooks such a dish for the first time. Using the egophoric form as a first-time cook would mislead the addressee due to its implications of earlier experience.

In contrast, (62) represents eggplant dishes’ tastiness in a general fashion with no implied involvement of the speaker or her earlier experience. This relates directly to the next topic of the article, namely the expression of general facts, discussed below.

4.6. General facts

Following Kittilä (Reference Kittilä2019), general knowledge refers to information that belongs to the speaker’s established world view, is referable without any external evidence and its original sources do not need to or even cannot be specified.Footnote 26 Stau encodes general knowledge using the sensory evidential discussed earlier in this article.

The egophoric copula cannot be used for general facts that are supposed to be known for everyone and thus cannot be located inside any individual speaker’s private territory of information, but rather in an epistemic shared territory everyone can access. To illustrate, (63) states a general fact, namely that rabbits are fast-running animals, something most people with at least cursory knowledge regarding them can reasonably be expected to know. Consequently, when referring to rabbits as a class of animals, the use of the egophoric copula is deemed ungrammatical by Stau speakers (64). An attempt to do so is tantamount to claiming that the information regarding rabbits’ fast running belongs to the speaker’s territory of information only. Further examples regarding the interplay of the sensory evidential and the non-egophoric copula in marking general knowledge are given in (65) and (66).

The use of the copula also affects the interpretation of the utterance. In (67), the non-egophoric copula results in a general interpretation applicable to fields in general: “Fields are very green.” Replacing the copula with its egophoric counterpart requires the interpretation that the speaker is discussing his/her own fields (68). This is because the other interpretation, namely that the speaker makes a claim that the greenness of fields is something exclusive to his/her territory of information, is pragmatically not expected and thus considered incorrect, as in (64) above that can only be considered pragmatically correct in a peculiar case where the utterance refers to a particular rabbit as an individual and a strong bond of some kind exists between it and the speaker. Perhaps the speaker has a pet rabbit s/he loves dearly, resulting in a special bond between the two. This would render (64) readable as “(My dear pet) rabbit is fast.”

Moreover, in (69), the speaker uses the non-egophoric copula to make a claim concerning a general fact supposedly known to speakers of Stau who live in an environment where Chinese alcoholic drinks are widely available. In contrast, the use of the egophoric copular form emphasizes that the speaker knows from his personal experience that Chinese baijiu (白酒) alcohol is strong (70). In other words, the statement ceases to be merely a general statement and becomes more personal.

5. Comparative remarks

This section briefly compares Stau with other Gyalrongic languages in terms of their copular systems. It argues that while this article focuses on Central Stau, egophoricity distinctions can possibly be identified in other related Gyalrongic languages as well, which highlights the need for further research.

Table 4 provides a comparison of affirmative and negative copulas in selected Gyalrongic languages.Footnote 27 The listing is not meant to be exhaustive, and since several of the languages remain seriously under-researched, future investigation may consequently discover new copulas or attribute new functions to already known copulas. It is not possible illustrate each language in detail in this article. In what follows, I offer some highlights and underline the possibility for discovering Central Stau like phenomena of egophoric contrast.

Table 4. A comparison of copulas in Gyalrongic languages

Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2019: 476–79, 650–53) discusses copular clauses in Geshiza. The language possesses two copulas: the affirmative ŋuə (71) and its negative counterpart mɲa (72). Unlike Stau, however, the language lacks egophoricity distinctions in its copular system. The same seems to apply to Dandong (personal fieldwork), although for a full confirmation, a thorough morphosyntactic description of this understudied Horpa variety is needed. Dandong possesses some Stau-like features (see also Gates et al. Reference Gates, Honkasalo and Lai2022: 214 on the geographically close Dangling variety as a “hinge dialect” between Geshiza and Stau), but in its copular system, the lect resembles Geshiza more.

The Geshiza general affirmative copula ŋuə is a direct cognate with the Stau non-egophoric copula ŋuə. Their argument indexation properties are almost identical, as Table 5 illustrates (see Table 2 for comparison). In Geshiza, the second person form mɲa-n nevertheless retains the morpheme -n discussed earlier in this article.

Table 5. Argument indexation properties of the Geshiza copulas

Tunzhi (2019: 292–99) identifies two affirmative copulas for Northwestern Stau: ŋo and to, and based on the available examples, mɲa, a cognate with the Central Stau negative copula, can be analysed to share a copular function. In Tunzhi’s interpretation, ŋo is a suppletive form of to in the first person. As the offered examples illustrate, however, both copulas can be used with the first person, highlighting their flexibility. The roles and functions of the two copulas appear strikingly similar to egophoric distinctions in Stau analysed in this article. In other words, to resembles a non-egophoric copula that codes the act of giving neutrally in (73) while ŋo manifests an egophoric function by highlighting the close connection with the speaker’s EGO in the act of giving (74). Northwestern Stau remains under-researched, and the issue of egophoricity needs to be addressed in detail in future studies.

Together with Horpa, the Khroskyabs languages form the second branch of West Gyalrongic. They resemble Horpa in copular use. For instance, Wobzi Khroskyabs possesses a binary system with an affirmative copula and its negative counterpart (Lai Reference Lai2017: 247–49). No egophoricity distinctions, however, have been identified.

Equally, East Gyalrongic languages possess multiple affirmative copulas (see Jacques Reference Jacques2021 on ŋu and ɕti), yet they seem not to make egophoric distinctions in their copular system. In sum, the Horpa languages, particularly those with a close relationship with Central Stau, such as Northwestern Stau and Erkai, offer the “lowest hanging fruit” for ascertaining the spread of egophoricity in the language cluster. In addition, other languages of the Horpa cluster should be investigated concerning this feature. Also, further investigation of the Khroskyabs varieties is necessary to analyse conclusively the spread of egophoricity in West Gyalrongic.

6. Conclusion

Building on earlier copula studies in the Horpa lects, particularly Gates (Reference Gates2021) on Central Stau, Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2019) on Geshiza and Tunzhi (2019) on Northwestern Stau, the present fieldwork-based article offers the first comprehensive description of Central Stau copulas from an interpersonal epistemic viewpoint. Through an analysis of the Stau copular system, the article argued that the language manifests distinctions in copular choice commonly discussed in terms of egophoricity. Although it showed the connection of egophoricity with SAPs, co-occurrence with the SAPs is not a defining feature of the copula ŋu. Consequently, Gates’s term “SAP copula” for ŋu can be adjusted as “egophoric copula”, which yields an additional benefit of making the discussed phenomenon more recognizable and comparable typologically.

Studies on egophoricity have proposed a “canonical” egophoric patterning whereby the first person statements and the second person questions as a result of an “anticipation rule” accompany an egophoric form, a non-egophoric form being used elsewhere. As San Roque et al. (Reference San Roque, Floyd and Norcliffe2017) explain, this perspective shift forms the focus in “canonical” definitions of egophoricity. Table 6 summarizes this distribution and illustrates how it is realized in Stau. As this table and the examples in this article demonstrate, Stau copulas can appear in a distributive pattern expected in “canonical egophoricity” and often do so.

Table 6. “Canonical” egophoric patterning and the Stau affirmative copular forms

Nevertheless, Table 6 by itself would offer a distorted idea of copular distribution in Stau, forcing it into a preconceived idea regarding how egophoric distribution “must” look in a language. This article revealed that, in many instances, both the egophoric and non-egophoric copular forms are acceptable, and their distribution manifests discourse-pragmatically controlled flexibility of a high degree.

A comparison of Table 7 with Table 6 underlines this considerable flexibility. In other words, the speakers often have the freedom to choose between the egophoric and non-egophoric forms, depending on how they wish to encode their epistemic stance towards the proposition. In this, the findings of this article align with those of other recent research on egophoricity, such as Sandman and Grzech (Reference Sandman and Grzech2022). Despite the frequent egophoric marking in the contexts of first person affirmative statements and second person questions as a result of a “perfective shift”, egophoricity in Stau is independent from grammatical person and may be used with any person as the copular subject.Footnote 31 To conclude, the ultimate determining factor in copular distribution in the language lies in the speaker’s desire to signal his or her epistemic stance vis-à-vis the proposition. Accordingly, when applying the parameter of “flexibility” discussed by San Roque et al. (Reference San Roque, Floyd, Norcliffe, Floyd, Norcliffe and Roque2018: 27–28), Stau clearly qualifies as a language with flexible, rather than rigid, egophoric marking.Footnote 32

Table 7. Additional distribution of the affirmative copular forms in Stau

While copular egophoricity exists in other Qiangic languages and more broadly in other Sino-Tibetan languages, Stau offers the first documented instance of the phenomenon in the Horpa language cluster. Hale’s (Reference Hale and Trail1980) research on Kathmandu Newar has been pivotal in shaping the image of how egophoricity is conceptualized, but as subsequent investigations of egophoric systems have demonstrated, egophoricity manifests variation in the purportedly defining features proposed for the grammatical category in earlier research (Bergqvist and Knuchel Reference Bergqvist and Knuchel2017). Also, egophoric copulas have been investigated most extensively in Tibetic languages. Against this backdrop, Stau from a different branch of Sino-Tibetan and with an evolved argument indexation system often absent in egophoric languages offers not only new perspectives to the research on Sino-Tibetan egophoricity but also contributes to the ongoing task of clarifying the key features and functional domain(s) of egophoricity.

Abbreviations

The abbreviations follow the Leipzig Glossing Rules. New abbreviations have been coined largely based on Gates (Reference Gates2021) and Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2019). The full list of abbreviations is as follows:

1

first person

2

second person

3

third person

adjz

adjectivizer

aux

auxiliary

clf

classifier

cop

copula

dem

demonstrative

dim

diminutive

dir

orientation

ds

different subject

ego

egophoric

erg

ergative

exv

existential

gen

genitive

inalien

inalienable

indef

indefinite

instr

instrumental

int

intensifier

interj

interjection

ipfv

imperfective

loc

locative

log

logophoric

lv

light verb

mod

modal

mod.neg

modal negation

nat

nativity suffix

neg

negative

nmlz

nominalizer

npst

non-past

pl

plural

proh

prohibitive

prox

proximal

q

interrogative

S/A

S or A argument

sap

speech act participants

sem

semelfactive

sens

sensory evidential

sg

singular

top

topic

topn

toponym

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Nedron Lhamo (ཉི་སྒྲོན་ལྷ་མོ) and Tsultrim Jungney (ཚུལ་ཁྲིམས་་འབྱུང་གནས) for their collaboration in researching the Stau language. Nedron Lhamo and Tsultrim’s intuition and great linguistic insight have made this article possible. I also thank others who have helped me with Stau during my long and arduous march in getting acquainted with this language. In addition, Erika Sandman’s perceptive comments and expertise in egophoricity greatly contributed to polishing the draft of this article into a more approachable form. Also, Jesse Gates’s support in helping me obtain some research materials only accessible with difficulty greatly supported this project. Furthermore, Bettina Zeisler kindly read through the draft and offered some valuable comments.

Funding statement

Part of this research has been funded by Suomen Kulttuurirahasto (The Finnish Cultural Foundation, grant number 00200357).

Footnotes

1 Central Stau is group of Horpa dialects spoken predominantly in Daofu County of Sichuan by approximately 27,000 individuals (see Gates Reference Gates2021: 1 for the estimate, derived from Tunzhi 2017, Tunzhi 2019 and Tunzhi et al. Reference Tunzhi, Roche, Sonntag and Turin2019). In addition to Central Stau, Northwestern Stau, spoken mostly in the adjacent Luhuo County, forms a separate Horpa variety, although dialectal continuity between the two must be researched further. The findings of this article apply to Central Stau only, and Stau is used as a shorthand to refer to this dialect group.

2 Previous research has adopted various terms for the counterpart of the egophoric form in egophoric systems, such as “allophoric” (e.g. Widmer and Zúñiga Reference Widmer and Zúñiga2017), “alterphoric” (e.g. Post Reference Post, Thornes, Andvik, Hyslop and Jansen2013) and “exophoric” (e.g. Aikhenvald and LaPolla Reference Aikhenvald and LaPolla2007), of which the last term also possesses other more common uses. For the sake of clarity and simplicity, the article refers to such forms as “non-egophoric”, a term in common use.

3 In analysing the collected lexicon, the speaker is given Stau words that s/he may freely use in building factual or imaginary examples with contexts. The findings, however, are additionally confirmed from recorded conversations, narratives, procedures and folktales that originate both from the Stau homeland and India.

4 The term “egophoricity” presents certain challenges. Since it is now often used in precisely the same way as the earlier notion of conjunct/disjunct marking, it is advisable to avoid it in many contexts (Zeisler Reference Zeisler2024, p.c.). Acknowledging such issues, this article nevertheless uses “egophoricity” to describe the epistemic phenomenon observed in Stau, which should not be interpreted in terms of the “conjunct/disjunct systems”, as illustrated in what follows in Section 4.

5 From this, it follows that a language may manifest both evidentiality and egophoricity. This applies to Stau where the two surface in different domains. As the article argues, egophoricity in Stau is encoded in the copular system and manifests itself through the choice of the appropriate copula. In turn, evidentiality in Stau is marked by verbal suffixes (see Gates Reference Gates2021: 344–50).

6 The Stau copulas are incompatible with standard negation, namely way(s) of negating verbal declarative main clauses that are general and productive (Miestamo Reference Miestamo2005; Payne Reference Payne and Shopen1985). Geshiza and other documented Horpa languages also manifest the same feature (see Honkasalo Reference Honkasalo2019: Chapter 11).

7 Gates (Reference Gates2021) uses the transcriptional form mjæ since this form appears in Shesnyag Stau documented in his grammar. Taking a pandialectal view, Stau dialects show variation in the consonant cluster of the copula: mɲæmjæ. As described by Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2019), identical alternation is also attested in Geshiza where the forms mɲamja occur. This article adopts the form mɲæ as the representative one since it occurs in the varieties spoken by the author’s research partners.

8 Unlike Honkasalo’s (Reference Honkasalo2020) system with vowel and velar nasal combinations (Vŋ), that of Gates (Reference Gates2021 and elsewhere) uses a nasalized vowel for the argument indexation morpheme of the first person. While the notation has some consequences, especially in the domain of phonological interpretation, such as the existence or lack thereof of nasal vowels, it plays no major role when analysing argument indexation from a synchronic viewpoint. Consequently, both systems appear as equally valid. This article follows the system of Honkasalo that facilitates comparison with other Horpa varieties. For instance, Yang (Reference Yang2021) on Bawang Horpa transcribes the corresponding ending with the velar nasal, which is also its historical origin.

9 Gates (Reference Gates2021: 379) applies the notion of SAP broadly, as example (6) discussed below in this article demonstrates.

10 At least in the Central branch of Horpa, intransitive verbs lack number contrasts in their argument indexation system. Many transitive verbs, however, contrast number in addition to person in their paradigms. Additionally, the analysis of Gates (Reference Gates2021) portrays the copular verbs as incompatible with the verb classes of Honkasalo (Reference Honkasalo2020).

11 Gates’s data and Y’s contribution in this article originate from speakers of Shesnyag and Yepo village lects, respectively. The two villages neighbour each other in Mazi, with less than three kilometres between the two. Since this area in Mazi is not an abrupt dialect transition zone, no major differences should be expected. On the other hand, Stau manifests noticeable internal diversity, and minor differences seem to exist between the two dialects.

12 This article could not discover any circumstances where the copula ŋu would display any argument indexation properties. The non-changing nature of the copula is additionally confirmed with the native intuition of the Yepo Stau speaking research partner who reports that it never changes its shape.

13 The first person form ŋoŋ < *ŋə-Vŋ is fusional with vowel alternation that characterizes argument indexation in Horpa. For this reason, it is not segmented in the examples in this article, unlike the fully segmentable second person form ŋə-n with the second person argument indexation morpheme -n. This also applies to the negative copula: mɲaŋ < *mɲə-Vŋ.

14 Y, however, states that such alternation is not always possible. The pragmatic conditions for the types of copular complements that allow or disallow copular alternation should be discovered further. As the first step towards this goal, subsection 4.3. argues that adjectival copular complements describing outwardly knowable attributes of the first person often allow variation. Also, while vlæmæ “lama” allows alternation, somewhat perplexingly, some speakers prefer the non-egophoric form when the copular complement is pubæ “Tibetan” (see example 7).

15 In the definition of Tournadre and LaPolla (Reference Tournadre and LaPolla2014: 244), “whenever the speaker asks a direct question of the hearer, she should anticipate the access/source available to the hearer and select the evidential auxiliary/copula accordingly”. Also, see Hill (Reference Hill2020) for a critique of the “anticipation rule” as an explanatory notion with descriptive power.

16 As an anonymous reviewer remarked, in Shesnyag Stau, the use of the interrogative enclitic =a is not acceptable here for forming a negative question. Instead, æ-ŋu (q-cop.ego) is needed for this purpose: ɲi pubæ mɲæ-ɡə æ-ŋu “Are you not a Tibetan?” This might reflect either differences in individual preferences or dialectal variation even in geographically proximate Stau varieties.

17 Future research should investigate whether the use of the egophoric form in such contexts may carry an affective or jocular pragmatic function emphasizing that the words should not be taken literally.

18 Earlier scholarship tended to interpret egophoricity as a means of person marking. For instance, Aikhenvald (Reference Aikhenvald2004) categorizes conjunct/disjunct (i.e. egophoric) systems as person marking, an approach that was relatively common at the time. It is worth noting, however, that she has changed her approach since: Aikhenvald (Reference Aikhenvald2023: 2) defines egophoricity as “speaker’s personal involvement in the action and access to information”.

19 This brief article focuses only on sensory evidentiality. It remains for future study to investigate the interplay of other types of evidentiality and egophoricity in Stau.

20 Since the sensory evidential covers all the senses, other less unlikely information sources, such as hearing some sounds and recognizing them as those made by a flying bat, are also, technically speaking, possible and thus cannot be ruled out.

21 Horpa copulas have additional grammatical functions besides their role in copular clauses, which mirrors the multifunctional behaviour of the Tibetan copulas yin and red. Such functions beyond copular clauses in Stau remain outside the scope of this article.

22 While the example here is short, exclamations with both copular subjects and compliments, such as “That child is very cute!” can be elicited.

23 Again, highly specific discourse-pragmatic conditions convert (47) into at least a theoretically acceptable utterance. The speaker and the carpenter may be siblings who have known each other since childhood. Therefore, the strength of their personal bond, exceeding even that of marriage, can be emphasized with the use of the egophoric copula ŋu. Such use, however, is rare in practice.

24 In analysing the equative copulas of Tibetan, Häsler (Reference Häsler1999: 151) interprets their respective empathy values as one distinguishing factor: jĩ̠ː manifests a strong empathy value, while re̠ː conversely has a weak empathy value. The former corresponds to Written Tibetan yin and the latter to red, respectively.

25 Consequently, if the speaker really wishes to lie or joke about having personal knowledge of Akhu Stompa, (53) is acceptable, although such a joke would not be common in the Stau culture. Again, the rejection of (53) results from pragmatic factors only.

26 The original definition is more comprehensive than the simplification offered here. See Kittilä (Reference Kittilä2019: 1277) for details.

27 Egophoric contrast exists more broadly in the “Qiangic” languages and in Southwestern China. For instance, Lamo (unclassified Qiangic) possesses an egophoric copula ʹŋo and its non-egophoric counterpart ʹtɕʰʉ (Suzuki and Tashi Nyima Reference Suzuki and Nyima2016; Suzuki and Tashi Nyima Reference Suzuki, Nyima, Nagano and Ikeda2021). Due to constraints of space, this article omits discussions concerning copular systems in the regional languages that are more distantly related to Stau.

28 GLD refers to the rGyalrongic Languages Database by Nagano and Prins (Reference Nagano and Prins2013).

29 This form surfaces very rarely in Stau. It can nevertheless be used in highly specific scenarios. For instance, we may suppose that the author of this article fainted during his trip to Daofu and subsequently woke up in a hospital with a temporary memory loss, including a weakened knowledge regarding his personal identity. Had he retained his command of the Stau language at least, he could consequently ask the Stau-speaking nurses ŋa sami æ-ŋoŋ-rə (1SG Sami Q-COP.NONEGO-SENS) “Am I Sami?”

30 Stau speakers rarely interrogate the EGO even as rhetorical device. Also, at least in the light of presently existing documentation and description, the language lacks any dedicated devices for “auto-interrogation”, in contrast to Geshiza (see Honkasalo Reference Honkasalo2019: 618–19). First person questions coded with egophoricity, such as *ŋa pubæ æ-ŋu (1SG Tibetan Q-COP.EGO) “Am I Tibetan?”, are deemed incorrect in Stau. This is most likely because the egophoric copula ŋu implies that there is a high degree of personal involvement and epistemic authority on the part of the enquirer, while the act of literally interrogating the first person concerning matters that are marked to stand at the core of their territory of information stands in a glaring contradiction with these presuppositions. Importantly, this differs from interrogating the first person with the non-egophoric copula, as in “Am I short?”, where the first person enquirer claims no epistemic authority with an implication of already knowing the answer beforehand. Such questions may be asked as genuine attempts to gain new information, although pragmatically speaking, they might target a second person addressee. For instance, in asking “Am I short?”, the enquirer may feel unsure of his/her stature and wishes to hear the opinion of another person who is present.

31 See also Sandman (Reference Sandman, Floyd, Norcliffe and Roque2018: 182) on Wutun reporting that, despite a strong correlation with person, egophoricity is not fully tied to it in the language.

32 The authors show that languages with grammaticalized egophoricity vary in terms of the “flexibility” of the markers. Languages with less “flexible” distributional properties for the egophoric marker(s) align closely with their canonical distribution whereas languages with more “flexibility” may contradict the distributional pattern (see also Bergqvist and Knuchel Reference Bergqvist and Knuchel2017: 362).

References

Aikhenvald, Alexandra. 2004. Evidentiality. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aikhenvald, Alexandra. 2023. “Speaking about knowledge: evidentiality and the ecology of language”, Studies in Language, 48/3, .Google Scholar
Aikhenvald, Alexandra and LaPolla, Randy. 2007. “New perspectives on evidentials: a view from Tibeto-Burman”, Linguistics of the Tibeto-Burman Area 30/2, 116.Google Scholar
Bergqvist, Henrik and Kittilä, Seppo. 2017. “Person and knowledge: introduction”, Open Linguistics 3, 1830.Google Scholar
Bergqvist, Henrik and Kittilä, Seppo. 2020. “Epistemic perspectives: evidentiality, egophoricity, and engagement”, in Bergqvist, Henrik and Kittilä, Seppo (eds), Evidentiality, Egophoricity, and Engagement, 121. Berlin: Language Science Press.Google Scholar
Bergqvist, Henrik and Knuchel, Dominique. 2017. “Complexity in egophoric marking: from agents to attitude holders”, Open Linguistics 3, .Google Scholar
Bristol, Rachel and Rossano, Federico. 2020. “Epistemic trespassing and disagreement”, Journal of Memory and Language 110, .Google Scholar
Dahl, Östen. 2000. “Egophoricity in discourse and syntax”, Functions of Language 7, 3377.Google Scholar
Daudey, Henriëtte. 2014. “A grammar of Wadu Pumi”, PhD thesis, La Trobe University.Google Scholar
Dixon, R.M.W. 2010. Basic Linguistic Theory. Volume 2: Grammatical Topics. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gates, Jesse. 2021. “A grammar of Mazur Stau”, PhD thesis, Ecole doctorale de l’EHESS and Centre de recherche linguistiques sur l’Asie (CRLAO).Google Scholar
Gates, Jesse, Honkasalo, Sami and Lai, Yunfan. 2022. “From transitive to intransitive and voiceless to voiced in Proto-Sino-Tibetan: new evidence from Stau, Geshiza, and Khroskyabs”, Language and Linguistics 23/2, .Google Scholar
Gawne, Lauren. 2017. “Egophoric evidentiality in Bodish languages”, in Gawne, Lauren and Hill, Nathan (eds), Evidential Systems in Tibetan Languages, 6194. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Hale, Austin. 1980. “Person markers: finite conjunct and disjunct verb forms in Newari”, in Trail, Ronald (ed.), Papers in South-East Asian Linguistics, 7: 95106. Canberra: Australian National University.Google Scholar
Häsler, Katrin. 1999. “A grammar of the Tibetan Sde.dge (སེ་དགེ) dialect”, PhD thesis, University of Bern.Google Scholar
Hill, Nathan. 2020. “A review of Egophoricity by Simeon Floyd, Elisabeth Norcliffe, and Lila San Roque”, Linguistic Typology 24/1, 18.Google Scholar
Honkasalo, Sami. 2019. “A grammar of Eastern Geshiza: a culturally anchored description”, PhD thesis, University of Helsinki.Google Scholar
Honkasalo, Sami. 2020. “Verb classes in Horpa: a study of Balang Geshiza and Poxiu Stau”, Linguistics of the Tibeto-Burman Area 43/2, .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honkasalo, Sami. 2023. “Managing interpersonal common ground in Dungan, Uyghur, and Uzbek: a study of =Ku”, International Journal of Eurasian Linguistics 5, 199232.Google Scholar
Jacques, Guillaume. 2019. “Egophoric marking and person indexation in Japhug”, Language and Linguistics 20/4, .Google Scholar
Jacques, Guillaume. 2021. A Grammar of Japhug. Berlin: Language Science Press.Google Scholar
Kamio, Akio. 1997. Territory of Information. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kittilä, Seppo. 2019. “General knowledge as an evidential category”, Linguistics 57/6, 12711304.Google Scholar
Lai, Yunfan. 2017. “Grammaire du khroskyabs de Wobzi”, PhD thesis, Université Paris III.Google Scholar
Lai, Yunfan, Gong, Xun, Gates, Jesse and Jacques, Guillaume. 2021. “Tangut as a West Gyalrongic language”, Folia Linguistica 54/s41-s1, 171203.Google Scholar
Miestamo, Matti. 2005. Standard Negation: The Negation of Declarative Verbal Main Clauses in Typological Perspective. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Miestamo, Matti and van der Auwera, Johan. 2011. “Negation and perfective vs. imperfective aspect”, Cahiers Chronos 22, 6584.Google Scholar
Nagano, Yasuhiko and Prins, Marielle (eds). 2013. rGyalrongic Languages Database, available at: http://htq.minpaku.ac.jp/databases/rGyalrong/.Google Scholar
Payne, John. 1985. “Negation”, in Shopen, Timothy (ed.), Language Typology and Syntactic Description. Volume I: Clause Structure, 197–242. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Prins, Marielle. 2016. A Grammar of rGyalrong, Jiaomuzu (Kyom-kyo) Dialects: A Web of Relations. Leiden and Boston: Brill.Google Scholar
Post, Mark. 2013. “Person-sensitive TAME marking in Galo: historical origins and functional motivation”, in Thornes, Tim, Andvik, Erik, Hyslop, Gwendolyn and Jansen, Joana (eds), Functional-Historical Approaches to Explanation: In Honor of Scott DeLancey, . Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Taylor-Adams, Allison and Lhawa, Yulha. 2020. “A sketch grammar of Siyuewu Khroskyabs”, Himalayan Linguistics Archive 9.Google Scholar
Sandman, Erika. 2016. “A grammar of Wutun”, PhD thesis, University of Helsinki.Google Scholar
Sandman, Erika. 2018. “Egophoricity in Wutun”, in Floyd, Simeon, Norcliffe, Elisabeth and Roque, Lila San (eds), Egophoricity, . Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Sandman, Erika and Grzech, Karolina. 2022. “Egophoricity and evidentiality: different categories, similar discourse functions. Insights on conversational data from the Tibetan plateau and the Amazonian foothills”, Interactional Linguistics 2/1, 79109.Google Scholar
San Roque, Lila, Floyd, Simeon and Norcliffe, Elisabeth. 2017. “Evidentiality and interrogativity”, Lingua 186–7, .Google Scholar
San Roque, Lila, Floyd, Simeon and Norcliffe, Elisabeth. 2018. “Egophoricity: an introduction”, in Floyd, Simeon, Norcliffe, Elisabeth and Roque, Lila San (eds), Egophoricity, 177. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Stivers, Tanya, Mondada, Lorenza and Steensig, Jakob. 2011. “Knowledge, morality and affiliation in social interaction”, in Stivers, Tanya, Mondada, Lorenza, and Steensig, Jakob (eds), The Morality of Knowledge in Conversation, 324. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Suzuki, Hiroyuki and Nyima, Tashi. 2016. “’Bo skad, a newly recognised non-Tibetic variety spoken in mDzo sgang, TAR: a brief introduction to its sociolinguistic situation, sounds, and vocabulary”, paper presented at the Fourth Workshop on Sino-Tibetan Languages of Southwest China (STLS-2016), University of Washington, Seattle, 8–10 September 2016.Google Scholar
Suzuki, Hiroyuki and Nyima, Tashi. 2021. “Evidential system of copulative and existential verbs in Lamo”, in Nagano, Yasuhiko and Ikeda, Takumi (eds), Link Languages and Archetypes in Tibeto-Burman (Grammatical Phenomena of Sino-Tibetan Languages 4), . Kyoto: Institute for Research in Humanities, Kyoto University.Google Scholar
Tournadre, Nicolas. 1996a. L’ergativité en tibétain moderne: Approche morphosyntaxique de la langue parlée. Paris et Leuven: Peeters.Google Scholar
Tournadre, Nicolas. 1996b. “Comparaison des systèmes médiatifs en tibétain central, ladakhi, dzongkha et amdo”, in Guentchéva, Zlatka (ed.), L’Énonciation médiatisée, 195213. Paris et Leuven: Peeters.Google Scholar
Tournadre, Nicolas and Suzuki, Hiroyuki. 2023. The Tibetic Languages: An Introduction to the Family of Languages Derived from Old Tibetan. Villejuif: LACITO-Publications.Google Scholar
Tournadre, Nicolas and LaPolla, Randy. 2014. “Towards a new approach to evidentiality”, Linguistics of the Tibeto-Burman Area 37/2, .Google Scholar
Tunzhi. 2017. “Language vitality and glottonyms in the Ethnic Corridor: the rTa’u language”, International Journal of the Sociology of Language 245, .Google Scholar
Tunzhi. 2019. “Outline of Bra‘go variety of rTa’u (Horpa)”, PhD thesis, La Trobe University.Google Scholar
Tunzhi, Hiroyuki Suzuki and Roche, Gerald. 2019. “Language contact and the politics of recognition amongst Tibetans in the People’s Republic of China: the rTa’u speaking ‘Horpa’ of Khams”, in Sonntag, Selma and Turin, Mark (eds), The Politics of Language Contact in the Himalaya, 1748. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers.Google Scholar
Wengmu, Genga (根呷翁姆). 2019. 四川道孚尔龚语 [The Sichuan Daofu Ergong Language]. Beijing: The Commercial Press.Google Scholar
Widmer, Manuel and Zúñiga, Fernando. 2017. “Egophoricity, involvement, and semantic roles in Tibeto-Burman languages”, Open Linguistics 3/1, .Google Scholar
Yang, Chih-Fan. 2021. “巴旺霍爾語時、體、示證、情態範疇的形態句法 [The morpho-syntax of tense, aspect, evidentiality and modality in Bawang Horpa]”, PhD thesis, National Taiwan Normal University.Google Scholar
Zeisler, Bettina. “What if the ‘ego-phoric’ also bears upon the non-ego – and the non-‘ego-phoric’ on the ego?”, paper presented at the SLE 57, University of Helsinki, 21–24 August 2024.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Gates’s (2021) analysis of the argument indexation properties of the SAP copula ŋu

Figure 1

Table 2. The forms of the copulas in Stau

Figure 2

Table 3. Compatibility of the copular forms with the sensory evidential suffix -rə

Figure 3

Table 4. A comparison of copulas in Gyalrongic languages

Figure 4

Table 5. Argument indexation properties of the Geshiza copulas

Figure 5

Table 6. “Canonical” egophoric patterning and the Stau affirmative copular forms

Figure 6

Table 7. Additional distribution of the affirmative copular forms in Stau