Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T21:59:28.477Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justice, Disagreement and Democracy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 July 2012

Abstract

Is democracy a requirement of justice or an instrument for realizing it? This article argues that the correct answer to this question depends on the background circumstances against which democracy is defended. In the presence of thin reasonable disagreement about justice, we should value democracy only instrumentally (if at all); in the presence of thick reasonable disagreement about justice, we should value it also intrinsically, as a necessary demand of justice. Since the latter type of disagreement is pervasive in real-world politics, the conclusion is that theories of justice designed for our world should be centrally concerned with democracy.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

University College, London (email: [email protected]). The author is grateful to the participants at the UCHV Fellows’ Seminar (Princeton), the conference ‘Justice: Between Ideals and Reality’ (Frankfurt), the CPSA Annual Convention (Montreal), the workshop on ‘Justice and Equality’ (Exeter), and the Workshop on Federalism, Security and Democracy (McGill, Montreal) for discussion. Many thanks also to Sara Amighetti, Enrico Biale, Emanuela Ceva, Zsuzsanna Chappell, Thomas Christiano, David Estlund, Nannerl Keohane, Cécile Laborde, Patti Lenard, Andrew Lister, Joseph Mazor, Valeria Ottonelli, Alan Patten, Philip Pettit, Anna Stilz and Patrick Tomlin for their detailed comments on previous versions of this article. Finally, the author is especially grateful to Hugh Ward and the anonymous reviewers of this article for their constructive criticisms and suggestions, and to Christian List for his feedback and continued encouragement.

References

1 For references, see the next section.

2 Dowding, Keith, Goodin, Robert E. and Pateman, Carol, eds, Justice and Democracy: Essays for Brian Barry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Gould, Carol, Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Christiano, Thomas, The Constitution of Equality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Dworkin, Ronald, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000)Google Scholar

4 McMurrin, S. M., ed., Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980)Google Scholar

5 Kymlicka, Will, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001)Google Scholar

6 Waldron, Cf. Jeremy, ‘Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism’, Philosophical Quarterly, 37 (1987), 127150 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999)Google Scholar

8 Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue. Dworkin's theory is complex, and includes a hypothetical insurance scheme whereby each pays to insure against natural disadvantages. The sum raised is then allocated to the naturally disadvantaged (e.g., the untalented and the disabled) to compensate for their plight.

9 Gaus, Gerald F., Justificatory Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar

10 Cf. the distinction between concept and conception in Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 5.

11 Sen, Amartya, Development as Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999)Google Scholar

Martha Nussbaum, Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000)Google Scholar

12 Weale, Albert, Democracy (New York: St Martin's Press, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 Goodin, Dowding and Pateman, eds, Justice and Democracy, pp. 40–58Google Scholar

14 Unless we stipulate (implausibly from a liberal perspective) that the only requirement of justice is democracy.

15 Barry, Brian, Justice as Impartiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995)Google Scholar

16 Cf. Rawls's characterization of ‘reasonable’ liberal conceptions of justice in The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999).

17 Some may find the idea of a right to subsistence too controversial, if by a right to subsistence we mean an unconditional right to basic income. But this right can also be understood, less controversially, as one to meaningful opportunities for subsistence.

18 Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, chaps 3 and 4, and Law's Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986)Google Scholar

Fabre, Cécile, ‘A Philosophical Argument for a Bill of Rights’, British Journal of Political Science, 30 (2000), 7798 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Ely, John H., Democracy and Distrust (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980)Google Scholar

19 Nick Cumming-Bruce and Steven Erlanger, ‘Swiss ban building of minarets on mosques’, New York Times, 29 November 2009, http://www.nytimes.com/2009/11/30/world/europe/30swiss.html (last accessed 29/12//2011).

20 For an overview of different justifications of democracy, see Christiano, ‘Democracy’.

21 Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, p. 186Google Scholar

Philippe Van Parijs, ‘Justice and Democracy: Are They Incompatible?’ Journal of Political Philosophy, 4 (1996), 101117 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Beitz, Charles R., Political Equality (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1989)Google Scholar

23 I am here following an example (and argument) by Ryan Davis in ‘Justice: Do It.’, www.ryanwdavisphilosophy/research/working-papers (last accessed 1 July 2012).

24 P. Laslett and J. Fishkin, eds, Philosophy, Politics and Society, 5th series (Oxford: Blackwell, 1979), pp. 97133 Google Scholar

25 This is not counter-intuitive at the level of some decisions. For example, whether a municipality should build a football pitch or a tennis court may entirely depend on the majority's preferences. But on more fundamental political questions we do tend to think that there is a procedure-independent truth of the matter.

26 David Estlund also considers doctors to be paradigmatic examples of experts. See his Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2007), chap. 1.

27 As a reviewer has pointed out to me, people may disagree about the truth conditions of statements about justice, and yet agree about which policies are just (or unjust). For example, both atheists and Catholics typically believe that it is unjust to torture convicted offenders, the former in virtue of certain interests sentient beings have, the latter in virtue of human beings’ status as creatures made in the image of God. I am not explicitly considering cases of agreement about policy and disagreement about truth conditions, because, absent any actual or prospective disagreement about how a just society ought to be organized, there is little reason to resort to democratic procedures. Moreover, it is plausible to suppose that complete and full agreement about justice can hardly obtain when there is disagreement about the truth conditions of justice claims. This is logically possible, but empirically unlikely.

28 Fabre, Cécile, ‘The Dignity of Rights’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 20 (2000), 271282 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29 Waldron, Jeremy, ‘Moral Truth and Judicial Review’, American Journal of Jurisprudence, 43 (1998), 7597 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

30 Clayton, Matthew, Justice and Legitimacy in Upbringing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Antony, Louise M., ed., Philosophers without Gods (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007)Google Scholar

McMahon, Christopher, Reasonable Disagreement: A Theory of Political Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

31 Estlund, ‘Jeremy Waldron on Law and Disagreement, Philosophical Studies, 99 (2000), 111128 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

32 Enoch, David, ‘Taking Disagreement Seriously: On Jeremy Waldron's Law and Disagreement, Israel Law Review, 39 (2006), 2235 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

33 I am not suggesting that Christiano and Waldron are unaware that, in the real world, disagreements about justice are often what I call thick, and that this has important implications. (See especially Waldron's remarks about the lack of uncontroversial/reliable epistemic procedures for arriving at the moral truth, and his related rejection of judicial review in Law and Disagreement, pp. 176ff.) I am only claiming that they do not systematically explore how thick v. thin disagreements affect the prospects for a justice-based defence of democracy.

34 Waldron, Law and Disagreement, pp. 1–4Google Scholar

Christiano, Thomas, ‘Waldron on Law and Disagreement’, Law and Philosophy, 19 (2000), 513543 Google Scholar

Fabre, ‘The Dignity of Rights’, pp. 275ffGoogle Scholar

35 Christiano, ‘The Authority of Democracy’, p. 269Google Scholar

36 Christensen, David, ‘Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good News’, Philosophical Review, 116 (2007), 187217 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

37 Estlund, Democratic Authority, p. 29Google Scholar

Dahl, Robert A., Democracy and Its Critics (New Haven, Conn./London: Yale University Press, 1989)Google Scholar

Goldman, Alvin I., ‘Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust?’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63 (2001), 85110 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

38 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for raising this challenge.

39 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for raising these points.

40 Arneson, ‘Democracy Is Not Intrinsically Just’, p. 40Google Scholar

41 Cohen, Joshua, ‘An Epistemic Conception of Democracy’, Ethics, 97 (1986), 2638 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

42 List, Christian and Goodin, Robert E., ‘Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 9 (2001), 277306 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

43 Talisse, Robert B., Democracy and Moral Conflict (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

44 Peter, Fabienne, ‘Democratic Legitimacy and Proceduralist Social Epistemology’, Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 6 (2007), 329353 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

45 Estlund, Democratic Authority, pp. 3ffGoogle Scholar

Waldron, Law and Disagreement, pp. 176ffGoogle Scholar

Dahl, Democracy and Its Critics, pp. 65–70Google Scholar

46 Gaus, Justificatory Liberalism, pp. 185ffGoogle Scholar

47 John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, edited by David Bromwich and George Kateb (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 2003 [1859])Google Scholar

48 Estlund makes this point in his Democratic Authority, chaps 11–12. Despite this, he still believes that the authority of democracy is largely grounded in its tendency to deliver right answers (though he expresses scepticism about the Jury Theorem in particular).

49 Estlund, Democratic Authority.

50 Notice that a similar problem would not occur if the disagreement were only about whether policy X or Y is just. For we do not need to know what the substantive right answer is in order to decide whether a particular procedure is good at tracking the truth. (On this see Estlund's critique of Waldron in ‘Jeremy Waldron on Law and Disagreement’, p. 122.) What makes resort to epistemic procedures problematic is the fact that we lack an account of the truth conditions of statements about justice.

51 Estlund, Democratic Authority, p. 5Google Scholar

52 Waldron, Law and Disagreement, pp. 253–254Google Scholar

53 For a somewhat similar view, which also emphasizes mutual justifiability but with a much greater focus on epistemic considerations, see Gaus, Justificatory Liberalism, part III. Unlike Christiano and me (more on which later), Gaus does not consider democracy – i.e., the roughly equal distribution of political power – as a demand of distributive justice, but analyses it in connection with the problem of political authority (pp. 249–51). Moreover, Gaus defines his defence of democracy as ‘essentially epistemic’, rather than as primarily intrinsic (p. 258). He first endorses the general category of ‘widely responsive’ law-making procedures on epistemic grounds (chap. 13). He then selects democracy in particular, because of its compatibility with political equality (chap. 14). This suggests interesting parallels between Gaus's position and Estlund's epistemic proceduralism (discussed earlier in the text). Finally, note that, for Gaus, democracy does not straightforwardly entail majority rule (pp. 240–3).

54 See Davis, ‘Justice: Do It.’

55 List, Christian, ‘Two Concepts of Agreement’, The Good Society, 11 (2002), 7279 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

56 Cf. Waldron, Law and Disagreement.

57 Christiano, ‘The Authority of Democracy’, pp. 272ffGoogle Scholar

58 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, p. 6Google Scholar

Campbell, Tom, ‘Review of The Constitution of Equality, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89 (2011), 169171 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

59 Of course, by arguing that democracy treats citizens with equal respect, Christiano may appear to offer a straightforwardly intrinsic defence of democracy (The Constitution of Equality, pp. 75–6). But the intrinsic nature of this defence, it seems to me, is rather superficial. Once the general idea of equal respect is articulated in terms of public equal advancement of interests, it emerges that, for Christiano, the value of democracy is largely instrumental. Interestingly, Christiano shows some awareness of this. See The Constitution of Equality, p. 71.

60 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, p. 191Google Scholar

61 There are exceptions to this general reliability, such as the case of persistent minorities, which Christiano explicitly discusses in The Constitution of Equality, pp. 296ff.

62 In my discussion so far I have looked at Christiano's most recent work on democracy. In his earlier The Rule of the Many (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996) his understanding of justice was slightly different, in terms of equal consideration of interests, rather than in terms of equal public advancement of interests. Equal consideration, however, does not seem to offer a plausible outlook on justice (which, I suppose, explains Christiano's move away from it). A society which considered everyone's interests equally, but consistently only advanced the interests of a small subset of its citizenry, would hardly count as just.

63 Saunders, Democracy as Fairness (doctoral thesis, University of Oxford, 2008)Google Scholar

Barbara Goodwin, Justice by Lottery, 2nd edn (Exeter, Devon: Imprint Academic, 2005)Google Scholar

64 E.g., its outcomes are likely to be more stable, because in line with the majority's view.

65 Gibbard, Allan, ‘Manipulability of Voting Schemes: A General Result’, Econometrica, 41 (1973), 587601 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Satterthwaite, Mark Allen, ‘Strategy-Proofness and Arrow's Conditions: Existence and Correspondence Theorems for Voting Procedures and Social Welfare Functions’, Journal of Economic Theory, 10 (1975), 187217 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Riker, William, Liberalism against Populism (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1982)Google Scholar

66 Dryzek, John and List, Christian, ‘Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation’, British Journal of Political Science, 33 (2003), 128 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

67 Arthur Lupia and Mathew D. McCubbins, The Democratic Dilemma: Can Citizens Learn what They Need to Know? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)Google Scholar

68 Valentini, Laura, ‘On the Apparent Paradox of Ideal Theory’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 17 (2009), 332355 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

69 Miller, Cf. David, ‘Two Ways to Think about Justice’, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 1 (2002), 528 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

70 A version of this view is arguably defended by Gaus in Justificatory Liberalism, chap. 10 (but see sec. 10.5), where the fundamental commitments of liberalism are said to be ‘conclusively justified’.

71 Ronzoni, Cf. Miriam and Valentini, Laura, ‘On the Meta-Ethical Status of Constructivism: Reflections on G.A. Cohen's “Facts and Principles”’, Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 7 (4) (2008), 403422 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

72 Cf. Rawls's method of reflective equilibrium as discussed in A Theory of Justice.

73 Cf. Christiano's account of the ‘division of labour’ between citizens (choosing the aims) and experts/officials (choosing the means) in a democratic society in The Rule of the Many, chap. 5.