Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T13:57:35.479Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Concepts of power: natural philosophy and the uses of machines in mid-eighteenth-century London

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Alan Q. Morton
Affiliation:
Science Museum, South Kensington, London SW7 2DD.

Extract

How may scientific research contribute effectively to industrial development? This question has been debated for many years. However, a recent development in this discussion has come from a number of eminent scientists and others who have become concerned with what has become known as the public understanding of science. According to them, a greater understanding of science by members of the public would result in a higher value being placed on scientific research, which, eventually, would result in both increased social status for scientists and growing funding from government and industry for their work. Thus, in part, concern about the public understanding of science is an indirect way of influencing the outcome of discussions about the science budget.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For a recent survey, see Durant, J. and Gregory, J. (eds.), Science and Culture in Europe, London, 1993Google Scholar. For another view, see Cooter, R. and Pumfrey, S., ‘Separate spheres and public places: reflections on the history of science popularization and science in popular culture’, History of Science (1994), 32, 237–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 In Britain during the First World War, for example, these concerns led to the formation of the Department of Scientific and Industrial Research, the first government department to have that sole remit. See Cardwell, D. S. L., The Organization of Science in England, London, 1972Google Scholar. Cardwell points to a similar interest in public understanding of science in the 1930s. See also Edgerton, David in National Military Establishments and the Advancement of Science (ed. Forman, Paul and Sanchez-Ron, J. M.), Dordrecht, 1994.Google Scholar

3 This sequence of events has intrigued several historians. See Musson, A. E. and Robinson, E., Science and Technology in the Industrial Revolution, Manchester, 1969Google Scholar; Cardwell, D. S. L., Technology, Science and History, London, 1972Google Scholar; Jacob, M. C., The Cultural Meaning, of the Scientific Revolution, New York, 1988Google Scholar; Inkster, Ian, Science and Technology in History: An Approach to Industrial Development, London, 1991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Stewart, Larry, The Rise of Public Science, Cambridge, 1992.Google Scholar

5 See Morton, A. Q. and Wess, J. A., Public and Private Science: The King George III Collection, Oxford, 1993, ch. 3Google Scholar. See also Hall, A. Rupert, ‘What did the Industrial Revolution in Britain owe to science?’, in Historical Perspectives: Studies in English Thought and Society in Honour of J H Plumb (ed. McKendrick, Neil), London, 1974, 129–51.Google Scholar

6 See Briggs, R., ‘The Académie Royale des Sciences and the pursuit of utility’, Past and Present (1991), no. 131, 3888.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 See Cardwell, D. S. L., from Watt to Clausius, London, 1971, 3457Google Scholar and Donovan, A. L., Philosophical Chemistry in the Scottish Enlightenment, Edinburgh, 1975, 250–65.Google Scholar

8 The changing ways machines were perceived can be tied in with many changes in systems of classification in general. See Pickstone, John, ‘Ways of knowing: towards a historical sociology of science, technology, and medicine’, BJHS (1993), 26, 433–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Frängsmyr, Tore, Heilbron, J. L. and Rider, Robin E. (eds.), The Quantifying Spirit in the 18th Century, Berkeley, CA, 1990.Google Scholar

9 One interesting demarcation involving machines was common to both natural philosophy and legislation. Steam-engines were openly discussed in natural philosophy lectures and their export was not prohibited by legislation ; whereas textile machinery was neither discussed in lectures nor covered by legislation prohibiting the export of machinery. Thus natural philosophy went against commercial secrecy, up to a point.

10 Golinski has discussed the development of lectures on chemistry as a form of public culture, shaped by the needs and aspirations of the audience. See Golinski, Jan, Science as Public Culture, Cambridge, 1992Google Scholar. The argument of this paper is that changes in the way science was portrayed to an audience also depended on industrial developments.

11 Harris, J. R., Essays in Industry and Technology in the Eighteenth Century: England and France, Aldershot, 1992, 18Google Scholar. Harris has drawn attention to the dearth of information about machinery in books of the period, including texts on natural philosophy, which he takes to be a sign of the unimportance of such sources, compared with the influence of craft-skills in his own discussion of the coal-based technologies. These practical craft-skills are transmitted ‘on the job’ and are precisely of the kind which are not or cannot be written down or published. I concede this point for information about technical processes. My argument makes narrower claims about natural philosophy being important only for some aspects of the improvement of machines and ways of talking about machines.

12 For example, Braudel, Fernand, Civilization and Capitalism (tr. Reynolds, S.), 3 vols., London, 1984, iiiGoogle Scholar, and Berg, Maxine, The Age of Manufactures: Industry, Innovation and Work in Britain 1700–1820, London, 1985Google Scholar, amongst other historians of eighteenth-century industry have drawn attention to this lack of discussion on the effects of machinery by contemporary writers on industry and commerce.

13 Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (ed. Campbell, R. H., Skinner, A. S. and Todd, W. B.), 2 vols., Oxford, 1976, i, 1415 and 20–1.Google Scholar

14 Ricardo, David, On the Principles of Political Economy, and Taxation, 3rd edn, London, 1821Google Scholar. By this edition Ricardo had changed his mind about the effects of the introduction of new machinery. He now thought ‘That the opinion entertained by the labouring class, that the employment of machinery is frequently detrimental to their interests, is not founded on prejudice and error, but is conformable to the correct principles of political economy’, p. 474.Google Scholar

15 As a result, as Berg has argued, political economy became a distinct academic discipline, rather than a branch of legislation or statesmanship. See Berg, Maxine, The Machinery Question and the Making of Political Economy, Cambridge, 1980, 17.Google Scholar

16 See Tribe, Keith, Land, Labour and Economic Discourse, London, 1978, 67Google Scholar, who points out that around the mid-eighteenth century enclosure came to be seen more as an economic relation, rather than simply to do with technical issues about surveying etc.

17 Connections between natural philosophy and political economy in the nineteenth century are explored in M. Norton Wise with the collaboration of Smith, Crosbie, ‘Work and waste: political economy and natural philosophy in nineteenth-century Britain (I)’, History of Science (1989), 27, 263301Google Scholar, ‘Work and waste (II)’, History of Science (1989), 27, 391449Google Scholar, ‘Work and waste (III)’, History of Science (1990), 28, 221–61.Google Scholar

18 See Morton, and Wess, , op. cit. (5)Google Scholar. For an earlier version see Morton, A. Q., ‘Lectures on natural philosophy in London, 1750–1765: S. C. T. Demainbray (1710–1782) and the “Inattention” of his countrymen’, BJHS (1990), 23, 411–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 See Morton, and Wess, , op. cit. (5), ch. 1.Google Scholar

20 Stewart, , op. cit. (4).Google Scholar

21 ‘The Ignorant, if he be honest, is more dangerous that the thorough-pac'd Knave; for the Conceit of the Ignorant will give him such a Confidence, as easily to persuade those of his Skill, who profess to have none of their own’. See Desaguliers, J. T., A Course of Experimental Philosophy, 2 vols., London, 17441745, ii, 490Google Scholar. Desaguliers also cited the example of a water-engine with a fly which actually hindered its working rather than being an improvement as its constructor claimed (ii, p. 413).

22 See Stewart, , op. cit. (4), ch. 10.Google Scholar

23 These devices had been known since antiquity. By combining them, they could also be used to explain the workings of more complex machines, as Galileo had pointed out.

24 Desaguliers, , op. cit. (21), i, 69Google Scholar. He continued ‘But yet the Science of Mechanics is not to be rejected as useless’. Galileo had earlier made a similar point about a mechanism not increasing power. See Poni, Carlo, ‘The craftsman and the good engineer in technical practice and theoretical mechanics in J. T. Desaguliers’, History and Technology (1993), 10, 215–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25 For the case of Rowley, an instrument maker who believed in perpetual motion, see Desaguliers, , op. cit. (21), i, 183Google Scholar. For a discussion of perpetual motion, see Schaffer, Simon, ‘The show that never ends: displays of perpetual motion in the early eighteenth century’, BJHS, forthcoming.Google Scholar

26 See Desaguliers, , op. cit. (21), ii, 537.Google Scholar

27 For a discussion about time see Thompson, E. P., ‘Time, Work-discipline and industrial capitalism’, in Customs in Common, London, 1991, 352403.Google Scholar

28 Desaguliers, , op. cit. (21), i, 70.Google Scholar

29 Calculated from data in Kanefsky, J. and Robey, J., ‘Steam engines in 18th-century Britain: a quantitative assessment’, Technology and Culture (1980), 21, 161–86, on 185CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Kanefsky and Robey also point out that calculations comparing men and horses with steam-engines crop up in the archives of mining companies. Desaguliers himself compared the engine at Griff to 200 men or 50 horses. Desaguliers, , op. cit. (21), ii, 467.Google Scholar

30 Smith, Crosbie and Wise, M. Norton, Energy and Empire: A Biographical Study of Lord Kelvin, Cambridge, 1989, ch. 9.Google Scholar

31 My reason for emphasizing the ‘place’ of particular machines relates to a point made by Pickstone, John, op. cit. (8)Google Scholar, that we should look out for different systems of classification, such as those based on geography, in use at different times (similar to those used for cheese and wine).

32 See Desaguliers, , op. cit. (21), ii, 535Google Scholar, who reprints Beighton's table of 1717. This table was originally published by Beighton in the Ladies Magazine, which he edited. The table was reprinted by Desaguliers and others down the century. It was printed in the Encyclopœdia Britannica, 3rd edn, Edinburgh, 1797Google Scholar, in the article on the steam-engine.

33 For Robins, see Steele, Brett, ‘Muskets and pendulums: Benjamin Robins, Leonhard Euler, and the ballistics revolution’, Technology and Culture (1994), 35, 348–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Mathematical Tracts of the Late Benjamin Robins, Esq…, 2 vols., London, 1761Google Scholar; Smeaton, John, Experimental Enquiry Concerning the Natural Powers of Wind and Water, London, 1794Google Scholar. See also Reynolds, T. S., Stronger than a Hundred Men: A History of the Vertical Waterwheel, Baltimore, 1983Google Scholar. For a more detailed version of the discussion of the case of Robins, Smeaton and Watt, see Morton, A. Q., ‘Men and machines in mid-18th century London’, Transactions of the Newcomen Society (19931994), 64, 4756.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

34 See Hankins, Thomas L., ‘Eighteenth century attempts to resolve the vis-viva controversy’, Isis (1965), 56, 281–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Iltis, Carolyn, ‘Leibniz and the vis viva controversy’, Isis (1971), 62, 2135CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pacey, A. J. and Fisher, S. J., ‘Daniel Bernoulli and the vis viva of compressed air’, BJHS (1967), 3, 388–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

35 Hankins, , op. cit. (34), 285–6.Google Scholar

36 Desaguliers, , op. cit. (21), i, 253 and 264.Google Scholar

37 Science Museum MS 552, ‘A course of experimental philosophy by S. Triboudet Demainbray in the year 1755’. Demainbray's maximum machine is Science Museum inventory number 1927–1634, see Morton, and Wess, , op. cit. (5), 155, catalogue D22.Google Scholar

38 Ironically, it became more difficult for Demainbray and his colleagues-cum-competitors to earn a living from lecturing. In fact, Demainbray gave up lecturing within a few years, in the early 1760s.

39 For this reason they objected to monopolies restricting trade in order to keep prices artificially high.

40 Coats, A. W., ‘Changing attitudes to labour in the mid-eighteenth century’, in Essays in Social History (ed. Flinn, M. W. and Smout, T. C.), Oxford, 1974, 87Google Scholar. See also Linebaugh, Peter, The London Hanged, Harmondsworth, 1993, 222Google Scholar, who says about the third quarter of the eighteenth century, ‘To say that the factory was introduced in this period would be misleading if by “factory” is meant machine production, but if the term is understood to mean a hierarchical organization of production under the eye of a single authority, then it calls attention to a major and decisive development.’

41 See Linebaugh, , op. cit. (40), 305–9Google Scholar; and George, M. Dorothy, ‘The London coal-heavers’, Economic Journal (19261929), 1, 229–48.Google Scholar

42 Adam Smith used the coal-heavers as an example of how harsh working conditions could lead to high wages. See Smith, , op. cit. (13), i, 121.Google Scholar

43 Machine for Discharging Ships' Cargoes, Patent No. 712, 1757.

44 Switzer, Stephen, An Introduction to a General System of Hydrostaticks and Hydraulicks…, London, 1729, ii, 284, pl. 10, fig. X.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

45 Mayhew, Henry, London Labour and the London Poor, 3 vols., London, 18611862, iii, 244.Google Scholar

46 Lloyds Evening Post, 17–20 02 1764.Google Scholar

47 Royal Society of Arts, Archives, vol. 5, item 86. See also Cooney, E. W., ‘Eighteenth-century Britain's missing sawmills: a blessing in disguise’, Construction History (1991), 7, 2946.Google Scholar

48 Appleby, John H., ‘Robert Dingley, FRS (1710–1781)’, Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London (1991), 45, 139–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

49 A similar point can be made about the coal-heavers, for they petitioned Parliament to regulate their position but did not get what they wanted. Even then the undertakers found ways round the legislation which was introduced.