Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T02:04:25.017Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Biology as Social Theory: John Scott Haldane and Physiological Regulation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Steve Sturdy
Affiliation:
Wellcome Unit for the History of Medicine, Department of Science and Technology Policy, The University, Manchester M13 9PL, U.K.

Extract

During the first forty years of this century, the concept of a living organism was discussed widely and publicly by biologists and philosophers. Two questions in particular excited discussion. In what ways should organisms be considered different from or the same as dead matter? And what can we learn about the nature of human society by regarding it as analogous to a living organism? Inevitably, these questions were closely related; the conclusions to be drawn about the social organism would depend upon the particular properties attributed to the biological organism. In more recent years, discussion of these issues has largely been in abeyance, as biologists have with-drawn from debate over social policy into a more remote academia. A few biologists who still see their work as relevant to a wider social agenda have continued to treat the nature of life as a contentious issue. But the focus of interest has shifted away from the organismic analogy, which concerns the organization of society as a whole, to issues like sociobiology and evolutionary theory, which emphasize social differentiation and the treatment of out-groups and minorities.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the Winter Meeting of the British Society for the History of Science, 4 January 1986, and at the Joint Atlantic Seminar in the History of Biology, University of Maryland, 26 April 1986. I am particularly grateful to David Bloor, Steven Shapin, Christopher Lawrence,Malcolm Nicolson, John T. Edsall, David Boucher and John Pickstone for their comments on earlier drafts.

1 See Allen, Garland E., Life Science in the Twentieth Century, Cambridge, 1978Google Scholar, chapter VI; Haraway, Donna J., Crystals, Fabrics, and Fields: Metaphors of Organicism in Twentieth-Century Developmental Biology, New Haven, Conn., 1976.Google Scholar

2 See, for example, Rose, Steven (ed.), Against Biological Determinism, London, 1982Google Scholar; Rose, (ed.), Towards a Liberator? Biology, London, 1982Google Scholar; Levins, Richard and Lewontin, Richard C., Dialectical Biologist, Cambridge, Mass., 1985.Google Scholar

3 Pickstone, John V., ‘Bureaucracy, liberalism and the body in post-revolutionary France: Bichat's physiology and the Paris school of medicine’, History of Science, (1981), 19, pp. 115142CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Figlio, Karl, ‘The metaphor of organization: an historiographical perspective on the bio-medical sciences of the early nineteenth century’, History of Science, (1976), 14, pp. 1753CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Cooter, Roger, ‘The power of the body: the early nineteenth century’, in Barnes, Barry and Shapin, Steven (eds), Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture, London, 1979, pp. 7392Google Scholar; Manuel, Frank E., ‘From equality to organicism’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1956), 17, pp. 5469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Stephen Cross, J. and Albury, William R., ‘Walter B. Cannon, L.J. Henderson, and the organic analogy’, Osiris, (1987) II, 3, pp. 165192CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Heyl, Barbara S., ‘The Harvard “Pareto circle”Journal of the History of the Behavioural Sciences, (1968), 4, pp. 3163343.0.CO;2-Z>CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Parascandola, John, ‘Organismic and holistic concepts in the thought of L.J. Henderson’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1971), 4, pp. 63113.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed Stella Butler has explored the use of the organismic metaphor in the work of the English physiologist, Ernest Starling, in chapter VI of her dissertation on ‘Science and the education of doctors in the nineteenth century: a study of British medical schools with particular reference to the development and uses of physiology’, unpublished Ph.D., University of Manchester, 1981, pp. 265297.Google Scholar

5 The only published biography of Haldane of any length is Douglas, C.G., ‘John Scott Haldane 1860–1936’, Obituary Notices of Fellows of the Royal Society, (1936), 2, pp. 115139CrossRefGoogle Scholar; reprinted with a very comprehensive bibliography, in Cunningham, D.J.C. and Lloyd, B.B. (eds), The Regulation of Human Respiration: the Proceedings of the J.S. Haldane Centenary Symposium, Oxford, 1963, pp. xxvxli, 332.Google Scholar On Haldane's scientific work, see Haldane, J.B.S., ‘The scientific work of J.S. Haldane’, in Barnett, S.A. and MacLaren, Anne (eds), Penguin Science Survey 1961, Harmondsworth, 1961, pp. 1133.Google Scholar See also Sturdy, Steven Waite, ‘A co-ordinated whole: the life and work of J.S. Haldane’, unpublished Ph.D. thesis, University of Edinburgh, 1987.Google Scholar

6 These later writers did not accept the particular metaphysical framework on which Haldane based his philosophy of organisms, and which is outlined in the following section of this paper. Nevertheless, in pioneering a theoretical alternative to both mechanism and dualistic vitalism, Haldane was the first to articulate the sophisticated version of scientific naturalism which they endorsed, and can more fruitfully be identified with their school of thought than with either of these previous positions. A useful discussion of the different varieties of organicism developed at this time is Phillips, D.C., ‘Organicism in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1970), 31, pp. 413432.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Allen, Garland E., ‘J.S. Haldane: The development of the idea of control mechanisms in respiration’, Journal of the History of Medicine, (1967), 22, pp. 392412.Google Scholar

8 Details of Haldane's university courses are from the Edinburgh University Calendar, 1876/18771884/1885Google Scholar, and the Class Lists, 1876/18771885/1886Google Scholar, held in Edinburgh University Library, Special Collections Department.

9 Haldane, R.B. and Haldane, J.S., ‘The relation of philosophy to science’, in Seth, Andrew (later Andrew Seth Pringle-Pattison) and Haldane, R.B. (eds), Essays in Philosophical Criticism, London, 1883, pp. 4166Google Scholar; Pringle-Pattison, A.S., ‘Richard Burdon Haldane (Viscount Haldane of Cloan) 1856–1928’, Proceedings of the British Academy, (1928), 14, pp. 405441.Google Scholar

10 On the Haldanes' childhood, see Haldane, R.B., Richard Burdon Haldane. An Autobiography, London, 1929Google Scholar, chapter 1; Mitchison, Naomi, ‘The Haldanes: personal notes and historical lessons’, Proceedings of the Royal Institution of Great Britain, (1974), 47, pp. 122Google Scholar; Haldane, M.E., Mary Elizabeth Haldane. A Record of a Hundred Years, 1825–3925. Edited by her daughter, London, 1925.Google Scholar While at University, John Haldane frequently wrote to his mother about the theology of the sermons he had heard and the Churches he attended. These letters are held in the National Library of Scotland, Haldane Papers, MS 20231.

11 cf. Budd, Susan, ‘The loss of faith. Reasons for unbelief among members of the secular movement in England, 1850–1950’, Past and Present, (1967), 36, pp. 106125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 Campbell, Andrew James, Two Centuries of the Church of Scotland, 1707–1929, Paisley, 1930, p. 172.Google Scholar

13 Haldane, J.S., The Sciences and Philosophy. Gifford Lectures, University of Glasgow, 1927 and 1928, London, 1929, p. 290Google Scholar; Haldane, J.S., Religion and the Growth of Knowledge (reprinted from Guy's Hospital Gazette. 04 1924), London, 1924, p. 18.Google Scholar

14 John Haldane resigned his Free Church membership in a letter to his minister, Ross, Hugh, dated 25 02 1883.Google Scholar A draft of this letter is held in the J.S. Haldane Papers, Woodward Biomedical Library, University of British Columbia. I am grateful to the Welcome Trust for a travel grant which enabled me to examine these and other papers in Canada. For further material on the idealists' crisis of faith, see Davie, George Elder, The Democratic Intellect: Scotland and her Universities in the Nineteenth Century, 2nd edn, Edinburgh, 1964, p. 329Google Scholar; Drummond, Andrew L. and Bulloch, James, The Church in Late Victorian Scotland 1874–1900, Edinburgh, 1978, pp. 231235Google Scholar; Wenley, R.M., ‘An unborn idealism’, in Adams, G.P. and Montague, W.P. (eds), Contemporary American Philosophy: Personal statements, 2 vols., London, 1930, II, pp. 385411Google Scholar; Muirhead, John Henry, Reflections by a Journeyman in Philosophy, London, 1942, p. 32.Google Scholar

15 Hennock, E.P., ‘Poverty and social theory in England: the experience of the 1880s’, Social History, (1976), 1, pp. 6791CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Paul, Ellen F., Moral Revolution and Economic Science: The Demise of Laissez-faire in Nineteenth-Century British Political Economy, Westport, Conn., 1979Google Scholar; Hall, Stuart and Schwarz, Bill, ‘State and society, 1880–1930’, in Langan, Mary and Schwarz, Bill (eds), Crises in the British state 1880–1930, London, 1985, pp. 732.Google Scholar

16 On the connection between utilitarianism and empiricism, see Halévy, Elie, The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism (1928), tr. Morris, Mary, London, 1972.Google Scholar

17 Haldane, R.B. and Haldane, J.S., op. cit. (9), pp. 4344.Google Scholar Also Seth, Andrew, ‘Philosophy as criticism of categories’, in Seth and Haldane (eds), op. cit. (9), pp. 840.Google Scholar

18 Haldane, R.B. and Haldane, J.S., op. cit. (9), p. 61.Google Scholar For a reiteration of this position late in life, see Haldane, J.S., The Philosophy of a Biologist, 2nd edn, Oxford, 1936, p. 152.Google Scholar

19 Haldane, R.B. and Haldane, J.S., op. cit. (9), p. 57.Google Scholar cf. Muirhead, , op. cit. (14), pp. 2930.Google Scholar

20 Haldane, J.S., Materialism, London, 1932, p. 140.Google Scholar

21 Such arguments clearly owed much to a broader liberal movement in theology which was gaining ground in Scotland in the wake of Essays and reviews, and brought with it the German Biblical criticism and a generally more naturalistic world view. See Campbell, , op. cit. (12), pp. 280288Google Scholar; Drummond, and Bulloch, , op. cit. (14)Google Scholar, chapter V.

22 Haldane, , Religion and the Growth of Knowledge, op. cit. (13), p. 17.Google Scholar cf. Rowell, Geoffrey, Hell and the Victorians: A Study of the Nineteenth-Century Theological Controversies Concerning Eternal Punishment and the Future Life, Oxford, 1974.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23 Certain members of the Scottish school of Common Sense philosophy had previously shown inclinations towards German idealist thought, most notably J.F. Ferrier, who incorporated elements of Kantian and Hegelian thought into his metaphysics, and James Hutchison Stirling, whose obscure but influential book on The Secret of Hegel, being the Hegelian system in Origin, Principle, Form and Matter was published in 1865Google Scholar (2 vols, London). The latter author in particular owed much to the more general interest in German thought promoted by his friend, Thomas Carlyle. But while the Scottish idealists later chose to trace their intellectual lineage to this tradition, they diverged markedly from the Common Sense writers in the antiecclesiastical conclusions they drew from their philosophy.

24 For a statement of the Oxford version of this view, see Bosanquet, Bernard, The Philosophical Theory of the State, London, 1899.Google Scholar

25 Vincent, Andrew and Plant, Raymond, Philosophy, Politics and Citizenship: The Life and Thought of the British Idealists, Oxford, 1984.Google Scholar For a valuable overview of the political discourse within which these arguments were articulated, see Collini, Stefan, ‘Individualism and collectivism’, chapter I of his Liberalism and Sociology: L.T. Hobhouse and Political Argument in Britain 1880–1914, Cambridge, 1979.Google Scholar

26 Haldane, J.S. to Trotter, L.K., 14 10 1890Google Scholar, 16 Oct. 1890, letters in the possession of Naomi Mitchison; Haldane, R.B., op. cit. (10)Google Scholar, chapter III; Jones, Henry and Muirhead, J.H., The Life and Philosophy of Edward Caird, Glasgow, 1921, pp. 1617Google Scholar; Muirhead, , op. cit. (14), p. 61.Google Scholar The Scottish idealists were not all Home Rulers, however. For example, Andrew Seth was at best ambivalent, and gradually moved towards the Unionist party under the influence of another Scottish metaphysician, A.J. Balfour: see Barbour, G.F., ‘Memoir of the author’, in Pringle-Pattison, A.S., The Balfour Lectures on Realism Delivered at the University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, 1933, pp. 3159.Google Scholar

27 Green's philosophy and politics have received considerable attention from historians. See, for example, Richter, Melvin T., The Politics of Conscience: T.H. Green and his Age, London, 1964Google Scholar; Vincent, Andrew (ed.), The Philosophy of T.H. Green, London, 1986Google Scholar; Jenks, C.B., ‘T.H. Green, the Oxford philosophy of duty and the English middle class’, British Journal of Sociology, (1977), 28, pp. 481497CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Harris, Frederick Phillip, The Neo-Idealist Political Theory. Its Continuity with the British Tradition, New York, 1944.Google Scholar

28 Haldane, R.B., ‘The Liberal creed’, Contemporary Review, (1888), 54, pp. 461474Google Scholar; Haldane, R.B., ‘The New Liberalism’, Progressive Review, (1896), 1, p. 141Google Scholar; Freeden, Michael, The New Liberalism: An Ideology of Social Reform, Oxford, 1978Google Scholar; Emy, H.V., Liberals, Radicals and Social Politics, 1892–1914, London, 1973.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29 On the important continuities between the old Liberal policies and the moralized views put forward by idealists like R.B. Haldane, see: Vincent, and Plant, , op. cit. (25), p. 77Google Scholar; and Sutton, David, ‘Liberalism, state collectivism and the social relations of citizenship’, in Langan and Schwarz (eds), op. cit. (15), pp. 6179.Google Scholar

30 Muirhead, J.H., The Platonic Tradition in Anglo-Saxon Philosophy. Studies in the History of Idealism in England and America, London, 1931, p. 174Google Scholar; Barbour, G.F., op. cit. (26), p. 38.Google Scholar

31 Haldane, J.S. to Trotter, L.K., 10 07 1891Google Scholar; letter in the possession of Naomi Mitchison.

32 Turner, F.M., Between Science and Religion: The Reaction to Scientific Naturalism in Late-Victorian England, New Haven, Conn., 1974Google Scholar, chapter I; Jacyna, L.S., ‘Scientific naturalism in Victorian Britain: An essay in the social history of ideas’, unpublished Ph.D. thesis, University of Edinburgh, 1980.Google Scholar

33 According to James R. Moore, it was only more liberal theologians, chiefly in the university towns, who were perturbed by the mechanistic implications of Darwin's theory: Moore, , The Post-Darwinian Controversies: A Study of the Protestant Struggle to Come to Terms with Darwin in Great Britain and America, 1870–1900, Cambridge, 1979CrossRefGoogle Scholar, passim. See also Baxter, Paul, ‘Science and belief in Scotland, 1805–1868: The Scottish evangelicals’, unpublished Ph.D., University of Edinburgh, 1985Google Scholar; Drummond, A.L and Bulloch, J., The Church in Victorian Scotland, 1843–1874, Edinburgh, 1975Google Scholar, chapter VIII; Drummond, and Bullock, , op. cit. (14), pp. 1828Google Scholar; Wenley, , op. cit. (14), pp. 389398.Google Scholar

34 Goodman, D.C., ‘Alexander Crum Brown’, D.S.B., ii, pp. 514516, on p. 515.Google Scholar

35 See Stewart, Balfour and Tait, P.G., The Unseen Universe; or, Physical Speculation on a Future State, London, 1875.Google Scholar

36 Lonsdale, Henry, ‘Biographical memoir’, in Turner, William (ed.), The Anatomical Memoirs of John Goodsir, 2 vols., Edinburgh, 1868, i, pp. 1203Google Scholar, on p. 146; Goodsir, John, ‘On the dignity of the human body’Google Scholar, ibid., i, pp. 207–285.

37 Huxley, T.H., ‘On the physical basis of life’, (1868)Google Scholar, in Huxley, , Collected Essays, volume 1, Method and Results, London, 1893, pp. 130165Google Scholar; Goodsir, Joseph, The Bases of Life: A Discourse in Reply to Professor Huxley's Lecture on ‘The Physical Basis of Life’, London, 1868Google Scholar; Stirling, James Hutchison, As Regards Protoplasm: in Relation to Professor Huxley's Essay on the Physical Basis of Life, Edinburgh, 1869.Google Scholar

38 Haldane, J.S., The Philosophical Basis of Biology. Donnellan Lectures, University of Dublin, 1930, London, 1931, p. 128.Google Scholar

39 Haldane, R.B. to Haldane, J.S., 19 01 1882Google Scholar, 28 Feb. 1882, letters in the possession of Naomi Mitchison.

40 See, e.g., Haldane, J.S., ‘Vitalism’, Nineteenth Century, London, (1898), 44, pp. 400413Google Scholar; Haldane, , op. cit. (38), p. 14.Google Scholar

41 Haldane, J.S., ‘Autobiographical notes’Google Scholar, (n.d.), National Library of Scotland, M/S 20235, f. 181.

42 Haldane, R.B. and Haldane, J.S., op. cit. (9), p. 52.Google Scholar

43 Ibid., p. 54.

44 Haldane, J.S., ‘Life and mechanism. Two lectures delivered at the Physiological Laboratory, Guy's Hospital, May 17 & 24, 1906’, Guy's Hospital Reports, (1906), 60, pp. 89123, on p. 104.Google Scholar Haldane's conception of the category of teleology, and its apprehension in the biological world, drew heavily on Kant's arguments: see Kant, Immanuel, The Critique of Judgement (tr. Meredith, James Creed), Oxford, 1952Google Scholar, part II, ‘The critique of teleological judgement’. For a discussion of the profound impact which this Kantian notion had on German biology during the first half of the nineteenth century, see Lenoir, Timothy, The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanics in 19th-century German Biology, Dordrecht, 1982.Google Scholar

45 Haldane, R.B. and Haldane, J.S., op. cit. (9), p. 59.Google Scholar

46 Ibid., pp. 54–55.

47 Haldane, J.S., ‘Life and mechanism’, Mind, (1884), 9, pp. 2747, on p. 31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48 Ibid., p. 40.

49 See, e.g., Haldane, J.S., The Sciences and Philosophy, op. cit. (13), p. 60.Google Scholar

50 Haldane, , Religion and the Growth of Knowledge, op. cit. (13), p. 8.Google Scholar

51 Haldane, , op. cit. (47), p. 36.Google Scholar

52 Haldane, R.B., ‘The metaphysical foundations of natural science’, Nature, (11 10 1883), 28, pp. 561562, on p. 562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

53 Haldane, J.S., The Sciences and Philosophy, op. cit. (13), pp. 7071.Google Scholar

54 It is interesting to note that, far from seeing scientific empiricism and religion as incompatible, Haldane recognized that ‘the association … of a mechanistic theory of life with orthodox theology’ was an important aspect of natural theological doctrine: Haldane, , The Philosophy of a Biologist, Oxford, 1935, p. 36.Google Scholar

55 Haldane, L.K., Friends and Kindred. Memoirs, London, 1961, p. 154Google Scholar; ‘Biology at the British Association’, Nature, (12 10 1893), 48, pp. 574576.Google Scholar Two almost complete drafts of Haldane's book are held in File XIII of the J.S. Haldane Papers, Woodward Biomedical Library, University of British Columbia; it is not clear why the book was never published.

56 Haldane, J.S. and Smith, J. Lorrain, ‘The physiological effects of air vitiated by respiration’, Journal of Pathology and Bacteriology, (1893), 1, pp. 168186, on p. 179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

57 Haldane, J.S. and Priestley, J.G., ‘The regulation of the lung-ventilation’, Journal of Physiology, (1905), 32, pp. 225266.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

58 Haldane, J.S. and Priestley, J.G., Respiration, 2nd edn, Oxford, 1935, p. 42.Google Scholar

59 Haldane, J.S., Organism and Environment as Illustrated by the Physiology of Breathing, New Haven, Conn., 1917, pp. 317.Google Scholar

60 Haldane, J.S., Mechanism, Life and Personality. An Examination of the Mechanistic Theory of Life and Mind, London, 1913, p. 88.Google Scholar

61 In particular, this work formed the basis for his renewed attempts to spread his anti-mechanistic views among physiologists, for example in his talks at the Physiological Laboratory at Guy's Hospital; Haldane, , op. cit. (44).Google Scholar

62 See for example Haldane, J.S., ‘The axiom of biology’Google Scholar, chapter I in The Philosophical Basis of Biology, op. cit. (38)Google Scholar; Haldane, , op. cit. (44), pp. 100104.Google Scholar

63 Campbell, J.M.H., Douglas, C.G., Haldane, J.S. and Hobson, F.G., ‘The response of the respiratory centre to carbonic acid, oxygen, and hydrogen ion concentrations’, Journal of Physiology, (1913), 46, pp. 301318CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Haldane, J.S. and Priestley, J.G., ‘The regulation of excretion of water by the kidneys’, Journal of Physiology, (1916), 50, pp. 296303CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Douglas, C.G. and Haldane, J.S., ‘The regulation of the general circulation rate in man’, Journal of Physiology, (1922), 56, pp. 69100.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

64 See for example: Haldane, J.S., ‘Some recent advances in the physiology of respiration, renal secretion, and circulation’, British Medical Journal, (1921), i, pp. 409413CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Haldane, , ‘Biological method illustrated’, chapter II in The Philosophical Basis of Biology, op. cit. (38).Google Scholar

65 A good account of the literature is given in Haldane, and Priestley, , op. cit. (58)Google Scholar, passim.; see also Allen, , op. cit. (7), pp. 394397.Google Scholar

66 Head, Henry, ‘On the regulation of respiration. Part I. Experimental’, and ‘Part II. Theoretical’, Journal of Physiology, (1889), 10, pp. 170, 279290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

67 See, inter alia, Fearing, Franklin, Reflex Action. A Study in the History of Physiological Psychology, Baltimore, 1930, pp. 146186Google Scholar; Lowry, Richard, ‘The reflex models in psychology: origins and evolution’, Journal of the History of the Behavioural Sciences, (1970), 6, pp. 64693.0.CO;2-3>CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Smith, Roger, ‘The background of physiological psychology in natural philosophy’, History of Science, (1973), 11, pp. 75123CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Daston, Lorraine J., ‘British responses to psycho-physiology, 1860–1900’, Isis, (1978), 69, pp. 192208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

68 Haldane, J.S., op. cit. (47), pp. 3132, 3940.Google Scholar

69 Haldane, , op. cit. (44), pp. 47, 118, 121.Google Scholar Sherrington was himself sympathetic to the concept of teleology, at least as a heuristic for guiding physiological research. Thus, when talking about his work on the scratch reflex, he acknowledged that ‘we here trench on a kind of teleology’: Sherrington, C.S., The Integrative Action of the Nervous System, New Haven, Conn., 2nd edn, 1947, pp. 236238.Google Scholar Metaphysically, however, he dissented from Haldane's anti-mechanism, claiming that the perception of teleology is a psychological artifact, not an apprehension of reality, and animals (at least, decerebrate ones) are really only reflex automata: Sherrington, , Man on his Nature: The Gifford Lectures, Edinburgh, 1937–1938, Cambridge, 2nd edn, 1951, p. 182.Google Scholar

70 Indeed, Haldane's functional understanding of physiological phenomena suggested substantive objections to Head's claim to have identified a regulatory reflex mechanism. By slowing down any increase in breathing rate, the reflex inhibition described by Head as ‘vagus apnoea’ would actually lead to a reduction of ventilation just when oxygen was most needed by an organism. As Haldane later observed, ‘from the teleological point of view the existence of vagus apnoea seems extremely improbable. Nothing is more unlikely than that the amount of air breathed should be regulated by nervous impulses acting directly contrary to physiological requirements.’ See Haldane, and Priestley, , op. cit. (57), p. 259Google Scholar; also Haldane, and Priestley, , op. cit. (58), p. 15.Google Scholar

71 Haldane, and Smith, , op. cit. (56), p. 178.Google Scholar

72 Haldane, and Priestley, , op. cit. (57), pp. 256257.Google Scholar

73 Haldane, J.S. and Mavrogordato, A., ‘The vagus regulation of breathing’, Journal of Physiology, (1916), 50, pp. xlixliiipGoogle Scholar, on p. xliii. cf. Douglas, C.G. and Haldane, J.S., ‘The regulation of normal breathing’, Journal of Physiology, (1909), 38, pp. 420440CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Christiansen, J. and Haldane, J.S., ‘The influence of the distention of the lungs on human respiration’, Journal of Physiology, (1914), 48, pp. 272277.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

74 Haldane himself repeatedly stressed the importance of his anti-mechanistic commitment in determining the direction of his research programme. See for example Haldane, , op. cit. (20), London, 1932, pp. 3536Google Scholar; Haldane, , The Sciences and Philosophy, op. cit. (13), p. 86Google Scholar; Haldane, and Priestley, , op. cit. (58), pp. 1415.Google Scholar

75 Thus, Pnina Abir-Am recalls the opinion of the historian of biochemistry, Edsall, John T.: ‘in his experimental work as a physiologist, Haldane was a mechanist though he opposed mechanism in his philosophically oriented writings’.Google Scholar Cited in Abir-Am, , ‘Recasting the disciplinary order in science: A deconstruction of rhetoric on “biology and physics” at two international congresses in 1931’, Humanity and Society, (1985), 9, pp. 388427CrossRefGoogle Scholar, on p. 420 n. 29.

76 Most recently Nils Roll-Hansen has presented a version of this argument, suggesting that the only real difference between holists and mechanists is that the former set limits to biological inquiry and explanation which are not required by the latter: Roll-Hansen, , ‘E.S. Russell and J.H. Woodger: The failure of two twentieth-century opponents of mechanistic biology’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1984), 17, pp. 399428CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Roll-Hansen, , ‘Critical teleology. Immanuel Kant and Claude Bernard on the limitations of experimental biology’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1976), 9, pp. 5991.Google Scholar

77 See for example Pringle-Pattison, A.S., The Idea of God in the Light of Recent Philosophy. Gifford Lectures, Aberdeen, 1912 and 1913, Oxford, 1917, pp. 7075Google Scholar; Stout, G.F., Mind and Matter. The First of Two Volumes Based on the Gifford Lectures, University of Edinburgh, 1919 and 1921, Cambridge, 1931, pp. 4042, 107109.Google Scholar

78 Allen, Garland E., op. cit. (1)Google Scholar; Bowler, Peter J., The Eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian Evolution Theories in the Decades Around 1900, Baltimore, 1983.Google Scholar

79 Haldane laid claim to familiar rhetoric when he argued that scientific progress had been retarded by the adoption, not only of dualistic vitalism, but also of dogmatic mechanism: see for example Haldane, , op. cit. (44), p. 92Google Scholar; and Haldane, , op. cit. (38), pp. 8182.Google Scholar This view was endorsed in two influential histories of science of that time: Singer, Charles Joseph, A Short History of Biology: A General Introduction to the Study of Living Things, Oxford, 1931Google Scholar, chapter XI; Nordenskiöld, Erik, The History of Biology: A Survey (tr. Eyre, L.B.), London, 1929, pp. 603612.Google Scholar M.Y. Johari has documented the sympathetic reception of Haldane, 's writings in an M.Sc. thesis on ‘The impact of social and philosophical crisis upon scientific knowledge: The case of British biologists on mechanist—vitualist debate at the beginning of the twentieth century and the First World War’, (University of Manchester, 1979)Google Scholar, chapter II, ‘The mechanist—vitalist debate and John Scott Haldane’. For a contemporary assessment of Haldane's place in the wider organicist movement, see McDougall, William, ‘The philosophy of J.S. Haldane’, Philosophy, (1936), 11, pp. 419432.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

80 From accounts of similar cases of the reinterpretation of experimental results, Hilde Hein has argued that conflicts between mechanists and anti-mechanists cannot in principle be decided one way or another by scientific evidence. Individual scientists' preferences must be explained, according to Hein, in terms of wider philosophical and social commitments: Hein, , ‘The endurance of the mechanism—vitalism controversy’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1972), 5, 159188.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed Donna Haraway endorses Hein's view of mechanism and vitalism in her discussion of early twentieth-century embryology: op. cit. (1), pp. 193–206.

81 Haldane, , op. cit. (59), pp. 1617.Google Scholar

82 Haldane himself argued that his work differed from that of the mechanists, not in the methodologies he employed in the laboratory, but in the questions he asked: Haldane, , op. cit. (60), pp. 8283.Google Scholar His claims are born out by recent studies of mid-nineteenth-century German mechanists and vitalists, which failed to discover any divergence of methodology: Benton, E., ‘Vitalism in nineteenth-century scientific thought: a typology and reassessment’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, (19741975), 5, pp. 1748CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Mendelsohn, Everett, ‘Physical models and physiological concepts: explanations in nineteenth century biology’, British Journal for the History of Science, (1965), 2, pp. 201219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Elsewhere, however, I have argued that Haldane's methodology did in fact differ from that of many of his professedly mechanistic contemporaries, notably in his use of unviolated subjects, chiefly humans, rather than vivisectioned animal subjects. Moreover, in a somewhat different debate over oxygen secretion, when participants on both sides recognized that the outcome of that debate would have implications for the controversy over mechanistic biology, the adequacy of Haldane's physiological methods was explicitly called into question. For a fuller discussion of this debate, see Sturdy, , op. cit. (5), pp. 216241.Google Scholar

83 Huxley, T.H., ‘Administrative nihilism’ (1871)Google Scholar, in Huxley, , Method and Results, op. cit. (37), pp. 251289.Google Scholar On Spencer's use of the organismic analogy, see Peel, J.D.Y., Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist, New York, 1971Google Scholar, chapter VII, ‘The organic analogy’.

84 Jones, Henry, ‘The social organism’, in Seth and Haldane (eds), op. cit. (19), pp. 187213.Google Scholar

85 Geddes, Patrick, ‘On the application of biology to economies’, Report of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, (1885), 55, pp. 11661167.Google Scholar

86 Haldane, J.S. to Haldane, E.S., 4 10 [?1883]Google Scholar, National Library of Scotland, MS 20232, ff.16–17.

87 Haldane, R.B. and Haldane, J.S., op. cit. (9), pp. 48, 56.Google Scholar

88 Haldane, J.S., The Sciences and Philosophy, op. cit. (13), p. 248.Google Scholar

89 Haldane, J.B.S., op. cit. (5), p. 32Google Scholar; Markham, Violet Rosa, Friendship's Harvest, London, 1936.Google Scholar Another mining friend and Liberal activist was Sir Richard Redmayne, H.M. Chief Inspector of Mines: see his Men, Mines and Memories, London, 1942.Google Scholar

90 As Freeden put it in his study of the New Liberalism, ‘For liberals, … socialism pertained first to the ethical and only then to the economic sphere … an intellectual and moral revolution had to precede a social and industrial one.’ Freeden, , op. cit. (28), p. 28.Google Scholar

91 This phrase is coined by Jones, Gareth Stedman, Outcast London: A Study of the Relationship Between Classes in Victorian Society, Oxford, 1971, p. 7.Google Scholar See also Vincent, and Plant, , op. cit. (25), pp. 3133, 8387.Google Scholar

92 Haldane, J.B.S., ‘Materialism and its opponents’, in A Banned Broadcast and Other Essays, London, 1946, pp. 253258, on p. 258.Google Scholar

93 Haldane, J.S., Russell, E.S. and MacKenzie, Leslie, ‘Symposium: The relations between biology and psychology’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (1923)Google Scholar, Supplement 3. Relativity, Logic and Mysticism, pp. 5694Google Scholar, on pp. 66–67; cf. Haldane, , The Sciences and Philosophy, op. cit. (13), p. 251.Google Scholar

94 Haldane, J.S., ‘The risks attending the use of carburetted water-gas for domestic lighting purposes’, Public Health, (1900), 12, pp. 490509, on p. 505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

95 This was essentially the same stance as his brother had taken on negotiations over the eight-hour day for miners, some forty-six years previously: Haldane, R.B., ‘The eight hours question’, Contemporary Review, (1980), 57, pp. 240255.Google Scholar

96 Haldane, J.S., ‘Values in industry’Google Scholar, in Haldane, , op. cit. (20), pp. 187207, on pp. 191–192.Google Scholar

97 Haldane, , op. cit. (54), pp. 127128.Google Scholar

98 Haldane, J.S., ‘Lung irritant gas poisoning and its sequelae’, Journal of the Royal Army Medical Corps, (1919), 33, pp. 494507Google Scholar, on pp. 502–507. See also Haldane, J.S. to Douglas, C.G., 21 03 1918Google Scholar, letter in the possession of Dr D.J.C. Cunningham.

99 Miller, Jonathan, ‘The dog beneath the skin’, The Listener, (20 07 1972), 88, pp. 7476.Google Scholar cf. Geison, Gerald L., Michael Foster and the Cambridge School of Physiology: The Scientific Enterprise in Late Victorian Society, Princeton, N.J., 1978, pp. 338355.Google Scholar For an earlier but comparable metaphorical use of the nervous system, see Lawrence, Christopher J., ‘The nervous system and society in the Scottish Enlightenment’, in Barnes and Shapin (eds), op. cit. (3), pp. 1940.Google Scholar

100 While at Oxford, Hobhouse went to Haldane for special tuition in biology ‘for the sake of philosophy’: Haldane, J.S. to Haldane, M.E., [autumn 1888]Google Scholar, letter in the possession of Naomi Mitchison. Hobhouse shared Haldane's concern to refute Spencer's social theories, and presumably his biological views as well. Hobhouse subsequently diverged considerably from the philosophical position which Haldane maintained: see Haldane, J.S., Thompson, D'Arcy W., Mitchell, P. Chalmers and Hobhouse, L.T., ‘Symposium: Are physical, biological and psychological categories irreducible?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (19171918), 18, pp. 419478.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

101 Hobson, J.A., ‘The re-statement of democracy’, Contemporary Review, (1902), 81, pp. 262272.Google Scholar

102 MacDiarmid, Hugh, ‘Third Hymn to Lenin’, in MacDiarmid, Selected Poems, Craig, David and Manson, John (eds), Harmondsworth, 1970, pp. 102111Google Scholar, on pp. 108–109. I am grateful to Malcolm Nicolson for showing me this quotation.