Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T07:36:32.817Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Person as scientist, person as moralist

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 October 2010

Joshua Knobe
Affiliation:
Program in Cognitive Science and Department of Philosophy, Yale University, New Haven, CT [email protected]://pantheon.yale.edu/~jk762/

Abstract

It has often been suggested that people's ordinary capacities for understanding the world make use of much the same methods one might find in a formal scientific investigation. A series of recent experimental results offer a challenge to this widely-held view, suggesting that people's moral judgments can actually influence the intuitions they hold both in folk psychology and in causal cognition. The present target article distinguishes two basic approaches to explaining such effects. One approach would be to say that the relevant competencies are entirely non-moral but that some additional factor (conversational pragmatics, performance error, etc.) then interferes and allows people's moral judgments to affect their intuitions. Another approach would be to say that moral considerations truly do figure in workings of the competencies themselves. I argue that the data available now favor the second of these approaches over the first.

Type
Target Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, F. & Steadman, A. (2004a) Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or pragmatic understanding? Analysis 64:173–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. & Steadman, A. (2004b) Intentional actions and moral considerations: Still pragmatic. Analysis 64:268–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. & Steadman, A. (2007) Folk concepts, surveys, and intentional action. In: Intentionality, deliberation, and autonomy: The action-theoretic basis of practical philosophy, ed. Lumer, C., pp. 1733. Ashgate.Google Scholar
Alicke, M. (2000) Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin 126:556–74.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Alicke, M. (2008) Blaming badly. Journal of Cognition and Culture 8:179–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beebe, J. R. & Buckwalter, W. (forthcoming) The epistemic side-effect effect. Mind and Language.Google Scholar
Buckwalter, W. (2010) Gender and epistemic intuition. Unpublished manuscript, City University of New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, R. (2005) The rational imagination: How people create alternatives to reality. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carey, S. & Spelke, E. (1996) Science and core knowledge. Philosophy of Science 63:515–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chapman, L. & Chapman, J. (1967) Genesis of popular but erroneous psychodiagnostic observations. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 72:193204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Churchland, P. (1981) Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 78(2):6790.Google Scholar
Cushman, F. (2010) Judgments of morality, causation and intention: Assessing the connections. Unpublished manuscript, Harvard University.Google Scholar
Cushman, F., Knobe, J. & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008) Moral appraisals affect doing/allowing judgments. Cognition 108:353–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F. & Mele, A. (2008) Intentional action: Two-and-a-half folk concepts? In: Experimental philosophy, ed. Knobe, J. & Nichols, S., pp. 171–88. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damasio, A. R., Tranel, D. & Damasio, H. (1990) Individuals with socio-pathic behavior caused by frontal damage fail to respond autonomically to social stimuli. Behavioural Brain Research 41:8194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Villiers, J., Stainton, R. & Szatmari, P. (2006) Pragmatic abilities in autism spectrum disorder: A case study in philosophy and the empirical. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31:292317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ditto, P., Pizarro, D. & Tannenbaum, D. (2009) Motivated moral reasoning. In: Moral judgment and decision making: The psychology of learning and motivation, ed. Bartels, D. M., Bauman, C. W., Skitka, L. J. & Medin, D. L., pp. 307–38. Elsevier.Google Scholar
Driver, J. (2008a) Attributions of causation and moral responsibility. In: Moral psychology, vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W., pp. 423–40. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Driver, J. (2008b) Kinds of norms and legal causation: Reply to Knobe and Fraser and Deigh. In: Moral psychology, vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W., pp. 459–62. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Feltz, A. & Cokely, E. T. (2007) An anomaly in intentional action ascriptions: More evidence of folk diversity. In: Proceedings of the 29th Annual Cognitive Science Society, ed., McNamara, D. S. & Trafton, J. G., p. 1748. Cognitive Science Society.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1970) A theory of human action. Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (2006) Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, A., Glymour, C., Sobel, D. M., Schulz, L. E., Kushnir, T. & Danks, D. (2004) A theory of causal learning in children: Causal maps and Bayes nets. Psychological Review 111:130.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gopnik, A. & Meltzoff, A. (1997) Words, thoughts and theories. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. & Wellman, H. M. (1992) Why the child's theory of mind really is a theory. Mind and Language 7:145–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Guglielmo, S. & Malle, B. F. (2009) The timing of blame and intentionality: Testing the moral bias hypothesis. Unpublished manuscript, Brown University.Google Scholar
Guglielmo, S. & Malle, B. F. (in press) Can unintended side-effects be intentional? Resolving a controversy over intentionality and morality. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin.Google Scholar
Haidt, J. (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 108:814–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hindriks, F. (2008) Intentional action and the praise-blame asymmetry. Philosophical Quarterly 58:630–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, C. & Knobe, J. (2009) Cause and norm. Journal of Philosophy 106(11):587612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A., Knobe, J. & Bloom, P. (2009) Disgust sensitivity predicts intuitive disapproval of gays. Emotion 9(3):435–39.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahneman, D. & Miller, D. (1986) Norm theory: Comparing reality to its alternatives. Psychological Review 93:136–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelley, H. H. (1967) Attribution theory in social psychology. In: Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, ed. Levine, D., pp. 192238. University of Nebraska Press.Google Scholar
Knobe, J. (2003a) Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63:190–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2003b) Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation. Philosophical Psychology 16:309–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2004a) Folk psychology and folk morality: Response to critics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24(2):270–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2004b) Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis 64:181–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2006) The concept of intentional action: A case study in the uses of folk psychology. Philosophical Studies 130:203–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2007) Reason explanation in folk psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31:90107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (forthcoming) Action tree and moral judgment. Topics in Cognitive Science.Google Scholar
Knobe, J. & Burra, A. (2006) Intention and intentional action: A cross-cultural study. Journal of Culture and Cognition 6:113–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. & Fraser, B. (2008) Causal judgment and moral judgment: Two experiments. In: Moral psychology, vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, W., pp. 441–8. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Knobe, J. & Roedder, E. (2009) The ordinary concept of valuing. Philosophical Issues 19(1):131–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koenigs, M., Young, L., Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., Cushman, F., Hauser, M. & Damasio, A. (2007) Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgements. Nature 446:908–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kunda, Z. (1990) The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin 108(3):480–98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leslie, A. M., Knobe, J. & Cohen, A. (2006a) Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: Theory of mind and moral judgment. Psychological Science 17:421–07.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, E. (2008) The folk concept of intentional action: Philosophical and experimental issues. Mind and Language 23(2):165–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, K. (2009) An experimental approach to the normativity of “natural.” Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the South Carolina Society for Philosophy, Rock Hill, South Carolina, February 27–28, 2009.Google Scholar
McArthur, L. & Post, D. (1977) Figural emphasis and person perception. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13:520–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCann, H. (2005) Intentional action and intending: Recent empirical studies. Philosophical Psychology 18:737–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloy, R. & Byrne, R. (2000) Counterfactual thinking about controllable events. Memory and Cognition 28:1071–78.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mikhail, J. (2007) Universal moral grammar: Theory, evidence, and the future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11:143–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Murphy, G. L. & Medin, D. L. (1985) The roles of theories in conceptual coherence. Psychological Review 92:289316.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
N'gbala, A. & Branscombe, N. R. (1995) Mental simulation and causal attribution: When simulating an event does not affect fault assignment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 31:139–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. (2005) Skill, luck, control, and folk ascriptions of intentional action. Philosophical Psychology 18:343–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. (2006a) Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: Some problems for jury impartiality. Philosophical Explorations 9:203–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. (2006c) On trying to save the Simple View. Mind and Language 21:565–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nanay, B. (2010) Morality of modality? What does the attribution of intentionality depend on? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40:2840.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. & Ulatowski, J. (2007) Intuitions and individual differences: The Knobe effect revisited. Mind and Language 22:346–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nyholm, S. (2009) Moral judgments and happiness. Unpublished manuscript, University of Michigan.Google Scholar
Pettit, D. & Knobe, J. (2009) The pervasive impact of moral judgment. Mind and Language 24:586604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phelan, M. & Sarkissian, H. (2008) The folk strike back; or, why you didn't do it intentionally, though it was bad and you knew it. Philosophical Studies 138(2):291–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, J. & Knobe, J. (2009) Moral judgments and intuitions about freedom. Psychological Inquiry 20:3036.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Premack, D. & Woodruff, G. (1978) Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1:515–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roese, N. (1997) Counterfactual thinking. Psychological Bulletin 121:133–48.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Roxborough, C. & Cumby, J. (2009) Folk psychological concepts: Causation. Philosophical Psychology 22:205–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shepard, J. (2009) The side-effect effect in Knobe's environment case and the Simple View of intentionality. Unpublished manuscript, Georgia State University.Google Scholar
Sloman, S. (2005) Causal models: How people think about the world and its alternatives. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smedslund, J. (1963) The concept of correlation in adults. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology 4:165–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solan, L. & Darley, J. (2001) Causation, contribution, and legal liability: An empirical study. Law and Contemporary Problems 64:265–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Surian, L., Baron-Cohen, S. & van der Lely, H. K. J. (1996) Are children with autism deaf to Gricean maxims? Cognitive Neuropsychiatry 1:5571.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sverdlik, S. (2004) Intentionality and moral judgments in commonsense thought about action. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24:224–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tannenbaum, D., Ditto, P. & Pizarro, D. (2009) Different moral values produce different judgments of intentional action. Unpublished manuscript, University of California, Irvine.Google Scholar
Tetlock, P. E. (2002) Social-functionalist frameworks for judgment and choice: The intuitive politician, theologian, and prosecutor. Psychological Review 109:451–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, J. (2004) Folk intuitions, asymmetry, and intentional side effects. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24:214–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ulatowski, J. (2009) Action under a description. Unpublished manuscript, University of Wyoming.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (2004) Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, J. C. & Bengson, J. (2009) Asymmetries in judgments of responsibility and intentional action. Mind and Language 24(1):2450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, L., Cushman, F., Adolphs, R., Tranel, D. & Hauser, M. (2006) Does emotion mediate the effect of an action's moral status on its intentional status? Neuropsychological evidence. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6:291304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalla, T., Machery, E. & Leboyer, M. (2010) Intentional action and moral judgment in Asperger Syndrome and high-functioning autism. Unpublished manuscript, Institut Jean-Nicod.Google Scholar