Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T18:21:53.040Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Panaetius, Scipio Aemilianus, and the Man of Great Soul

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 September 2023

Jonathan Barlow*
Affiliation:
Trinity College, University of Melbourne, Australia
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In the second half of the second century BC, a single personality became ascendant in the Roman Republic. Scipio Aemilianus assumed the mantle of the first man in Rome from 146 BC until his death in 129 BC. Modern biographers of this leading statesman have drawn different conclusions about the influence of Greek ethics on the life of Scipio, either that he possessed a Hellenistic way of thinking or that he was a traditional Roman aristocrat. Much debate turns on historiography and the question of the usability of sources like Cicero for the history of the second century BC. This article focusses on de Officiis Books 1–2 and the issue of Cicero's debt to the writing of the Stoic philosopher Panaetius of Rhodes, Scipio's friend and tutor. I argue that sufficient evidence exists in the references to Scipio in Off. 1–2 to demonstrate that Panaetius had characterised Scipio as influenced by the Stoic way of living and explicitly as a Roman example of the virtue of greatness of soul. This argument is supported by corroborating evidence from Polybius, Scipio's friend and confidant, who also wrote about him in his Histories.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Australasian Society for Classical Studies

The Stoic philosopher Panaetius of Rhodes lived in Rome from the 140s BC as the houseguest, tutor, and friend of its leading statesman P. Cornelius Scipio Aemilianus (cos. 147, 134 BC). He accompanied Scipio at home and on campaign (domi militiaeque) and was eyewitness to that statesman's life and character.Footnote 1 Although it is reasonable to suggest he influenced Scipio, the degree to which he may have exercised philosophical influence is disputed in scholarship. Münzer summed up his Realencyclopädie entry with the comment that Scipio appears to have achieved a harmonious combination of the good qualities of the Roman national character with those of the Hellenistic way of thinking.Footnote 2 Münzer's summary was developed in detail in early-twentieth-century studies which explored the influence of Stoic ethics on Scipio's life and career, such as that by Kaerst (Reference Kaerst1929). However, Münzer's summary was rejected by Astin, Scipio's modern biographer, who instead portrayed his subject as an intensely ambitious aristocrat using Roman customs and conventions and little touched, if at all, by a Hellenistic spirit. Astin's evaluation of his subject in terms of Realpolitik has been authoritative and is shared by biographers of other prominent Romans such as Drogula, who likewise downplayed Stoic influences in the life of Cato the Younger.Footnote 3 In contrast, I have argued that Scipio claimed the cardinal virtues in public life and aligned utility with moral goodness on military campaign.Footnote 4 This debate has broader implications for the history of the Roman Republic, whether its statesmen were portrayed by contemporaries as embracing Greek philosophical virtues and referenced as models of exemplary leadership in military and civic affairs of state, or not.

Panaetius was an eyewitness to Scipio's life and character and one who wrote about Scipio. Although his works were mostly lost and testimonies credited to him contested, his Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος, ‘Concerning the Appropriate’, persists in altered form to this day as the source for Cicero's de Officiis 1–2. Panaetius taught the cardinal virtues, illustrated his ethical instruction with exemplars of moral praiseworthiness, and referenced Scipio directly and with approval in Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος. Cicero later used his exemplars when composing de Officiis, and the provenance of two of the Scipio references to Panaetius is not disputed in scholarship. This article focusses mainly on Off. 1–2. Based on its internal evidence, as well as corroborating evidence from the historian Polybius, I argue that Panaetius conceived of Scipio as a Roman example of the Stoic way of living and specifically as a man of great soul. I begin with comments about the role of Stoic philosophers as advisors to men of power, before discussing the question of Cicero's debt to Panaetius in composing de Officiis, its references to Scipio Aemilianus, and the external evidence of Polybius.

Stoics as Advisors

The Stoic school had a tradition of sending philosophers to the courts of kings to serve as advisors on how to resolve conflict in the moral conscience, to guide the course of appropriate action, and to provide direction in leading the moral life.Footnote 5 Zeno of Citium, the foundation Stoic, dispatched Persaeus and others to Macedonia to instruct the king and kingdom in virtue (Diog. Laert. 7.6–9). Persaeus appears to have taught the moral responsibility of rulership as a service to others, or in the words of Antigonus II Gonatas, kingship as a ‘glorious servitude’ distinguished by mildness and humanity.Footnote 6 Zeno's pupil, Sphaerus of Borysthenes, went to Sparta and advised Cleomenes III, the revolutionary monarch and social and economic reformer (Plut. Cleom. 2.2, 11.2). Stoics were active in Republican Rome in the second century BC among the intellectuals and men-of-letters who lived in the households of aristocratic families, like the Sempronii Gracchi, Aemilii Paulli, and Cornelii Scipiones, educating their scions in the language and culture of Greece. Blossius of Cumae advised Tiberius Gracchus and influenced the agrarian law of 133 BC and the more radical social movement at Pergamum later that year.Footnote 7

Panaetius of Rhodes exemplified the Stoic tradition of advisor to power. He had adapted the strict sectarianism of the early Stoics to a broader cultural zeitgeist of accessible knowledge and practical ethics. A lover of Plato and of Aristotle, he had relaxed some of Zeno's doctrines (Ind. Stoic. Herc. 61). He rejected the ‘harshness’ (acerbitas) of Stoic doctrines and the density of logic and instead embraced gentler opinions and a clearer style (Cic. Fin. 4.79). He divided virtue into the theoretical and the practical, and had located wisdom in the former, and justice, greatness of soul, and self-control in the latter (Cic. Off. 1.15–17; Diog. Laert. 7.92). Like other Stoics, he advised that a course of action must be undertaken ‘by means of the good and the useful’ (per honestum et utile, Cic. Off. 3.11–12). He spoke Latin and communicated in non-technical language (Cic. Tusc. 4.4, Off. 2.35). In sum, Panaetius taught practical ethics for men making progress to virtue in their real-world conduct and he will have observed gradations in the progress of the proficients he instructed.Footnote 8

Alesse conveniently collects the evidence of the connections between Panaetius and Roman statesmen like Scipio, C. Laelius, Q. Aelius Tubero, and P. Rutilius Rufus under the headings De amicitia Panaeti et Scipionis (frs. 21–38) and De Panaeti discipulis (frs. 39–52); Vimercati assembles a similar collection (frs. A20–37, A38–52).Footnote 9 Panaetius educated Scipio and other members of the Roman elite in the doctrines of the Stoic school and his instruction yielded notable results, making Scipio ‘most gentle’ (lenissimus). His influence is explicit in the testimony of Cicero, who drew on witnesses of an elder generation when contrasting the mildness of Scipio's way of living with the ‘harshness’ (asperitas) of Cato the Younger's brand of Stoicism (Mur. 66, 75). Of particular relevance to Rome, Panaetius is likely to have been one of the philosophers who re-evaluated glory by transforming it from a matter of moral indifference (the traditional Stoic judgement) into ‘true glory’ (vera gloria), a positive good with intrinsic value.Footnote 10 It was in this form that stoic-inspired Romans like Tiberius Gracchus claimed it as a goal of action.Footnote 11 Possibly, Scipio Aemilianus did the same (Cic. Rep. 6.25). However, since much of the evidence is preserved by Cicero one must ask how much of it is a Ciceronian construction.

Panaetius and de Officiis

Ancient history scholarship has developed an antipathy towards source criticism, a variety of the branch of literary scholarship that is source research (Quellenforschung). This is somewhat understandable. Widely practised in the pre-WWII period as a method of identifying, evaluating, and reconstructing the content of lost sources, it has been criticised as insecure and conjectural and, worse, as fabrication. Source criticism is rejected by many scholars who view texts as expressive only of their time and place.Footnote 12 On this later valuation, Cicero is responsible for the content of de Officiis, an original and independent work that is expressive of the moral and political context of late 44 BC, and with little reliable information about second century BC thought. Attacks on Mark Antony and the dead Julius Caesar lend weight to this valuation.

Cicero's literary output was prodigious and, like other ancient authors, he acknowledged that he used and cited earlier sources. Atticus asked him how he could produce so much quality work in such a short period of time. He quipped, in reply, that his philosophical works were transcripts of the original sources of others with his additions (Att. 12.52.3). In other words, he acknowledged the use of sources while making light of his emendations, alterations, and departures from them. Cicero did not plan to include de Officiis in his initial schema of philosophical texts, and therefore it represents a special case with a distinctive provenance to a principal source. He stated explicitly that he was following the philosopher Panaetius of Rhodes in writing Off. 1–2, albeit at his own discretion and judgement and not as a translator (Off. 1.6, 2.60, 3.7); and he was accepted at his word in antiquity when saying that he was using Panaetius as his source (Plin. NH praef. 22; Gell. NA 13.28). Cicero's selection of a treatise from the previous century over recent treatises such as that by Hecato indicates his agreement with its content and his belief in its moral and political resonance with his audience. Nevertheless, scholarship holds different views about his dependence on Panaetius, the degree to which he may have followed him, and the amount of discretion he may have exercised.

Van Straaten (Reference Straaten1962) produced the primary collection of fragments of Panaetius and he attempted to limit inclusion to texts which directly cited the philosopher. However, he realised this criterion was too restrictive in the case of de Officiis, and he included passages which did not cite Panaetius directly but where attribution of principles to the philosopher seemed secure. His methodology came in for criticism. According to Brunt, van Straaten made arbitrary choices about the inclusion of fragments and omitted content from de Officiis which Brunt subsequently sourced to Panaetius. Brunt commented that ‘it would have been more consistent to excerpt only the texts in which Panaetius is named’.Footnote 13 Edelstein and Kidd applied this methodology of collecting fragments directly attested to Posidonius while acknowledging indirect survival of more of their subject's thought;Footnote 14 and yet Theiler, finding this methodology restrictive, offered a more diffusive collection for Posidonius.Footnote 15 In the case of de Officiis, scholars have detected the thought of Panaetius in unattested passages even when their criteria for the selection of passages remains controversial.

Alesse and Vimercati independently produced new editions of Panaetius’ fragments and testimonies, and each has included a number of unattested passages from de Officiis. Alesse argued that Cicero had continuous reference to Panaetius and did not feel the need repeatedly to name him each time he used him and she cited the example of the unattributed inclusion of Stoic οἰκɛίωσις doctrine from Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος.Footnote 16 Vimercati refined his collection of fragments and testimonies into three levels of reliability: (A) certain, (B) plausible, and (C) uncertain attribution.Footnote 17 Alesse and Vimercati each provided commentary and notes justifying their selections, as well as stand-alone monographs on Panaetius and his intellectual milieu.Footnote 18 Alesse and Vimercati are also notable in their disagreement about the publication date of Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος, with the former assigning it to the 140s and 130s BC and the latter to after the tribunate of Tiberius Gracchus.Footnote 19

Pohlenz and Dyck, authors of two specialist studies of de Officiis, also disagreed about the publication date and historical context of Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος. Pohlenz in many respects commanded the field of Stoic studies in the middle of the twentieth century, and he advanced a selective and thematic treatment of Off. 1–2 premised on the detection of Panaetius’ presence throughout. He presented his Panaetius as a moral and political philosopher writing for a Roman audience and taking into account the tribunate of Tiberius Gracchus and issues of property rights and agrarian reform. He dated publication to after the death of Scipio Aemilianus in 129 BC and believed Scipio pursued a political policy of concordia (ὁμόνοια, ‘concord’) in contrast to the demagogues in Rome who endangered it. Published in 1934, his monograph is linked to its times by its title and theme of ‘Führertum’ (‘leadership’), along with its use of contemporary political diction like ‘Volksgenossen’ (‘compatriots’). Conscious perhaps of the nature of National Socialism, Pohlenz felt the need to distance his work from the regime by averring that his subject was political conservatism.Footnote 20 Nevertheless, his work needed updating.

Dyck's commentary is the leading study of de Officiis. He explained Pohlenz's understanding of leadership principle as a concept of the ‘Hohenzollern monarchy’ anachronistically retrojected into Roman history. Dyck believed that Panaetius was not writing primarily for a Roman audience and had published his treatise around or shortly after 139–138 BC, that is before the Gracchan land reform program. According to Dyck, Cicero tailored Panaetius’ moral and political philosophy to Rome, adding the references and allusions to the Gracchi and heightening emphasis on private property.Footnote 21 On the use of moral exempla in de Officiis, Dyck sourced the examples of Greeks to Panaetius and those of Romans to Cicero, but acknowledged this division did not apply in the case of Scipio Aemilianus.Footnote 22 Dyck did not pursue Pohlenz's line of enquiry into Scipio and instead accepted Astin's assessment of him.Footnote 23

Lefèvre has set out in most detail the sceptical case questioning the amount of content of Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος present in de Officiis and arguing in favour of Cicero's thorough reworking of Panaetius. He drew a distinction between the theoretical intentions and philosophical content of Panaetius on the one hand, and the practical intentions and political content of Cicero on the other, casting Panaetius as a theoretician with little interest in politics and the practical life, and de Officiis mostly as an original work by Cicero writing in 44 BC. Lefèvre believed that Cicero redacted his original source through the lens of contemporary politics to the extent that not much of it remained.Footnote 24

Independent of Dyck and Lefèvre, Brunt made the case for Cicero's reliance on Panaetius in a chapter published posthumously but intended as the foundation for a larger study of Panaetius. From a close reading of de Officiis, he argued it was possible to retrieve much of Panaetius’ thinking in Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος and therefore to know the ethics of this major Stoic philosopher. He believed he had advanced argument and evidence sufficient to ‘treat as Panaetian large parts of de officiis’.Footnote 25 Inwood has also recently applied the methodology of van Straaten and Alesse in his collection of Stoic thinkers by including unattested passages from Off. 1–2 on the assurance that Cicero was drawing on Panaetius.Footnote 26 Inwood's collection reaffirms the importance of Panaetius to the development of Stoic thought in the second century BC.

Lefèvre has not, in my view, overturned the collective research of Pohlenz, Dyck, Alesse, Vimercati, Brunt, and Inwood. In effect, he has fallen back on the cliché of Greeks as theorists and Romans as pragmatists, when his subject, Cicero, was a Roman Realpolitiker who was adept at handling Greek concepts. Moreover, Cicero did not conceive of his task in the way Lefèvre argued. Cicero says in Off. 1–2 that he is following and modifying the work of Panaetius and in Off. 3 that he is completing the unfinished identification of ‘the morally good’ (τὸ καλόν/honestum) with ‘the useful’ (τὸ συμφέρον/utile). Cicero publicly claims responsibility for Off. 3 when he states that he was no longer following a single source and instead boasted of his independence (Off. 3.7, 3.33–4), while privately he told Atticus that he had followed Panaetius for the first two books and now needed a new source for the third (Att. 16.11.4). Despite his efforts, Off. 1 and 2 remained of higher quality than Off. 3 on account of the excellence of the single source they followed. Further, if Cicero were mostly responsible for the political content of a moral treatise on Stoic themes composed in late 44 BC, we would expect him to accentuate the example of Cato the Younger, not Scipio who had died in 129 BC. Recently deceased (46 BC) and subject to polemical praise and condemnation, Cato was the obvious choice for him to use as a Roman moral exemplum as in the case of his other philosophical works of the period and his recent eulogy of Cato.Footnote 27

Dyck comments on Panaetius’ interest in politics. Panaetius was familiar with Scipio and Laelius and an observer of political careers, his messaging was clear, and he wrote on politics in an accessible way. His decision to write on the useful as a ‘criterion for judging actions’ indicated his interest in practical matters, like instruction in the correct way for a man to make progress to virtue without conflict with the morally good. ‘Panaetius’ goal is to win over members of the ruling class to the honestum, if not for its own sake, then on the grounds of utilitas …’. To this end, he wrote at length on ‘the useful’ (τὸ συμφέρον/utile) and sought to reconcile the useful with ‘the morally good’ (τὸ καλόν/honestum), thereby determining the correct course of action while avoiding shameful actions on account of the damage they did to the soul.Footnote 28

Greek philosophy classified politics as a branch of ethics and the Stoics agreed with the interdependence of moral and political philosophy.Footnote 29 Panaetius had developed a real-world interest in politics, government, and the state. He had written a (lost) book On Politics which emphasised the practical aspects of governance (Cic. Leg. 3.13–14). That book would have expounded on topics like the duties of magistrates and the administering of proportionate punishment.Footnote 30 Panaetius had discussed politics with his contemporaries Scipio and Polybius (Cic. Rep. 1.34), and he, like Polybius (13.6–8), had responded to social and economic reform in Sparta. The fact that Panaetius was the source for the references to the Spartan agrarian reformers Cleomenes III, Agis IV, and Lysander in de Officiis demonstrated his willingness to enter into political discussion about the precursors of the Gracchan revolution.Footnote 31 Panaetius was interested in history (Ind. Stoic. Herc. 66). He had illustrated Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος with examples of kings and statesmen making moral choices in the active life; he had directly referred to Themistocles, Pericles, Cyrus, Agesilaus, Alexander (Off. 2.16) and, as Lefèvre himself conceded, he had directly referred to Scipio Aemilianus.Footnote 32

Panaetius’ reference to Scipio as a moral exemplum in Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος on at least two occasions indicates his willingness to enter politics and endorse a conservative Roman politician. He did have members of the Roman ruling class in mind as his audience,Footnote 33 aristocrats like P. Rutilius Rufus who certainly were familiar with its content (Cic. Off. 3.10). He may have dedicated Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος to a Roman as his student Hecato had dedicated a treatise to Tubero (Cic. Off. 3.63), and he, Panaetius, had dedicated his de Dolore Patiendo to Tubero (Cic. Fin. 4.23, Tusc. 4.4). His involvement in Gracchan-era politics in opposition to the activist agenda of Blossius of Cumae and in support of Roman conservatives has been often averred.Footnote 34

Panaetius was integral to the creation of the source tradition on Scipio Aemilianus. I have shown elsewhere from the evidence that Cicero did not create the model of Scipio in the 40s BC. Rather, Scipio's status as an exemplum of moral praiseworthiness who laid claim to the cardinal virtues was part of a received tradition.Footnote 35 Although there were many origins for this received tradition, including Polybius (31.23–30) and the reports of other contemporaries,Footnote 36 the model was remarkably consistent, indicating its derivation from second-century-BC eyewitness accounts and sources. As Welch has shown, later authors like Cassius Dio did not create the criteria of four cardinal virtues to assess the moral character of men like Scipio because these criteria of assessment had already become canonical before their time of writing.Footnote 37 Scholars are justified in using the collections of van Straaten, Alesse, and Vimercati as evidence for the second half of the second century BC. Brouwer uses them in tracing Panaetius’ influence among contemporary Roman jurists and politicians, the interaction of philosophy and law, and law and philosophy.Footnote 38

Lefèvre's claim that Cicero was mostly responsible for the content of Off. 1–2 cannot be sustained. It is difficult to see Cicero transforming a philosophical treatise into a political tract when the philosophical treatise was already political. As he undertook the task of rendering Greek terminology into Latin, Cicero was prepared to edit, emend, and abridge his source, deploy his rhetorical skills and add material and examples which post-dated Panaetius. He wrote de Officiis at pace in October-November 44 BC, with Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος in front of him and in agreement with its ideological tenor and its political content. Specialist research has demonstrated how the depth of the psychological and philosophical insight in Off. 1–2 shows the hand of its acknowledged source, Panaetius of Rhodes. Pohlenz, Dyck, Alesse, Vimercati, Lefèvre, and Brunt, despite their differences, are in agreement that Panaetius had written about Scipio Aemilianus in Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος and in the following section we turn to assess the evidence of Scipio in de Officiis.

Scipio Aemilianus in de Officiis

Panaetius had posited an instinctive basis of ethics in Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος. He began discussion of the morally good with the doctrine of ‘appropriation’ or ‘affinity’ (οἰκɛίωσις), the instinct of self-preservation in living creatures that develops in man from a self-regarding impulse into an affinity with fellow men which is the foundation of the virtue of justice and of the society of the human race.Footnote 39 He identified four innate psychological impulses to the morally good – the desire for truth, the social instinct, the drive for independence, and the feeling for order which, refined by supervening reason, developed into the virtues of wisdom, justice, greatness of soul, and self-control – the four divisions of moral goodness (Cic. Off. 1.15–17). He discoursed at length on the useful but left unfinished his promised resolution of the apparent conflict between moral goodness and utility.

The first two books of de Officiis contain seven references to Scipio Aemilianus, six in Off. 1 and one in Off. 2. There are none in Off. 3, the book that Cicero composed without reliance on Panaetius. There is no doubt the references to Scipio at Off. 1.90 and 2.76 came from Panaetius. They appear in van Straaten's collection as fragments 12 and 13, in Alesse as fragments 124 and 26, and in Vimercati as fragments A101 and A29. In the following, I assess the seven references and argue that Cicero presents a philosophical characterisation of Scipio that is consistent with the two references he took directly from Panaetius.

Panaetius had revised the virtue of ‘courage’ (ἀνδρɛία) as ‘greatness of soul’ (μɛγαλοψυχία) which he defined as the drive for independence (Off. 1.13, 1.61–92). He defined courage, via Cicero's reworking of the Greek, as ‘the virtue that fights for fairness’ (pro aequitate).Footnote 40 For Panaetius, the two characteristics of greatness of soul are indifference to human affairs (especially the vicissitudes of fortune) and the undertaking of arduous actions of supreme utility.Footnote 41

There are three references to Scipio within the treatment of greatness of soul, at Off. 1.76, 1.87, and 1.90. The first reference is:

… nec plus Africanus, singularis et vir et imperator, in exscindenda Numantia reipublicae profuit quam eodem tempore P. Nasica privatus cum Ti. Gracchum interemit.

Cic. Off. 1.76

… and further, Africanus [Scipio Aemilianus], a unique personality as a man and as a commander, did not benefit the republic more by destroying Numantia than did Publius Nasica as a private citizen, when, at the same time, he [Nasica] killed Tiberius Gracchus.Footnote 42

Off. 1.76 referred to Scipio abroad and P. Scipio Nasica Serapio (cos. 138 BC) at home, two branches of the Scipiones whose arduous actions served the state in response to external and internal threats. Panaetius (Off. 2.16) had referred to examples of generals in war and statesmen at home who served the state by their exploits. He was probably responsible for the Greek examples of Themistocles, Solon, Pausanius, Lysander, and Lycurgus that preceded the above text while Cicero added the Roman examples of M. Scaurus, C. Marius, Catulus, and Pompey. Greatness of soul is displayed not only by generals in war but also by statesmen in the service of the state and Solon and Lycurgus are illustrious examples of abiding civic achievement over transitory military victory. Finding the theme congenial, Cicero appears to have upgraded Nasica's achievement over Scipio's before relating his own (Off. 1.74–8). Nevertheless, Cicero's reference to Scipio drew attention to Scipio's claim to be a unique personality, a claim he was known to have made in his lifetime (Polyb. 31.25.2–8, 31.29.12).

The context for the second reference is civil administration of the affairs of state, which must be conducted for the benefit of the governed, for the benefit of the whole, and with mutual respect among leading citizens (Off. 1.85–7). The section included a warning from Plato against competition in steering the ship of state, followed by:

Idemque praecipit ut eos adversarios existimemus qui arma contra ferant, non eos qui suo iudicio tueri rempublicam velint: qualis fuit inter P. Africanum et Q. Metellum sine acerbitate dissensio.

Cic. Off. 1.87

[Plato] further advises that we should regard as adversaries those people who take up arms against the state, not those who want to protect the state by following their personal convictions: such an example was the disagreement without bitterness between Publius Africanus and Quintus Metellus.

This example of respect is consistent with the restrained, gentlemanly qualities credited to the historical Scipio by his friend and apologist Polybius (31.26.10, 31.28.11) and with Cicero's assessment at de Amicitia 77, where Scipio continued to act with moderation towards Metellus (cos. 143 BC) after disagreement with him. However, this example is inconsistent with the assessment of them at de Republica 1.31, where their relations in politics were described as hostile.Footnote 43 Therefore, Rep. 1.31 represented an earlier assessment by Cicero, written in 54–51 BC, while Amic. 77 and Off. 1.87 represented modifications made to this assessment in 44 BC as he read about philosophical themes in the life of Scipio. ‘Disagreement without bitterness’ was a sentiment topical in the wake of Scipio's death in 129 BC when the moderation that prevailed among Optimates prompted the reconciliation of Metellus with Scipio's memory, as he ordered his sons to carry the funeral bier of the late statesman.Footnote 44

The context for the third reference advised restraint in success given the variability of fortune, and it cited the imperturbability of Socrates and Laelius and the contrasting moral temperaments of Philip II and Alexander the Great (Off. 1.90–1). Romans aspired to emulate the model of Alexander as victor over three continents and it is possible that Scipio saw himself in this light.Footnote 45 Alexander had been tutored by Aristotle, and Aristotle's (Eth. Nic. 1123a34–1125a35) conception of the man of great soul (μɛγαλόψυχος) appealed to Panaetius, even though as a Stoic he denied moral content to the passion of anger. Panaetius had probably discussed with Scipio the moral failings of Alexander like the repeated outbursts of anger, as opposed to the example of Philip II, Alexander's father.Footnote 46 Panaetius would have advised that, for actions to be righteous, the useful must identify with the morally good, and it cannot serve self-seeking aims or be subject to emotional outbursts. Panaetius quoted Scipio directly and with approval towards the end of his discussion of the virtue of greatness of soul:

Panaetius quidem Africanum auditorem et familiarem suum solitum ait dicere, ut equos propter crebras contentiones proeliorum ferocitate exsultantes domitoribus tradere soleant, ut iis facilioribus possint uti, sic homines secundis rebus effrenatos sibique praefidentes tamquam in gyrum rationis et doctrinae duci oportere, ut perspicerent rerum humanarum imbecillitatem varietatemque fortunae.

Cic. Off. 1.90

According to Panaetius, his pupil and friend Africanus used to say that when frequent skirmishing has made horses fierce and high-spirited, men are accustomed to give them to trainers so that they may have gentler mounts to ride. Similarly, men whom success has made unbridled and overconfident should be led into the training-ring of reason and learning, so that they perceive the frailty of human affairs and the variability of fortune.Footnote 47

Alesse (fr. 124) and Vimercati (fr. A101) are right to place this passage among the psychological testimonies of Panaetius. Alesse commented on the Platonic imagery of the soul and the metaphor of the unruly horse. Training in reason and learning disciplines the emotions just as the charioteer disciplines unruly horses.Footnote 48

Scipio's moral advice served to smooth out the course of life so that it was not subject to intense and inconsistent emotional irruptions. He advocated restraint in success, foreknowledge of the variability of fortune, and a message of indifference to matters of convention. The broader Stoic message is that moral goodness alone matters and the good is manifest in mental independence and rational consistency in character and conduct throughout the course of life. Scipio spoke as a possessor of greatness of soul, the virtue independent of the vicissitudes of worldly affairs.

Panaetius had quoted Scipio Aemilianus as an example of greatness of soul (μɛγαλοψυχία), the virtue that was the third part of τὸ καλόν. Given the inseparability of the virtues (Off. 1.15, 162), Scipio's moral advice also related to the three other parts of the καλόν, to the virtues of wisdom, justice, and self-control. Perspicientia is the quality of sapientia et prudentia, the virtue of wisdom, that is the first of the cardinal virtues (Off. 1.15–16, 1.100, 2.18). The man of greatness of soul undertakes actions on behalf of the common good and in the interests of the social virtue of justice, and not from self-interest. His desire for consistency in character and conduct is a manifestation of his virtue of self-control.

In his Scipio Aemilianus, Astin did not explore the implications of this undisputed contemporary testimony at Off. 1.90 as it did not fit his narrative of Scipio as a Roman aristocrat fired by ambition.Footnote 49 A Roman aristocrat fired by ambition will desire success in increasing intensity and offer advice to that end, not least if he were the first man in Rome from 146 BC onwards. He would not advocate humility in achievement. Instead, Scipio's advice reflected ethical teaching on the need for restraint in the knowledge of the vicissitudes of fortune.Footnote 50

The fourth, fifth, and sixth references to Scipio Aemilianus occur within the treatment of the virtue of the fitting (Off. 1.93–151), at Off. 1.108, 1.116, 1.121. The context for the fourth reference was the introduction to Panaetius’ ‘roles’ (personae) theory, which was the idea that nature had endowed man with four roles in life, first a general role stemming from human rationality and, second, individual roles where unique differences of character were assigned to each individual (Off. 1.107–8), with treatment of the third and fourth roles to follow.Footnote 51 The fitting (Off. 1.110) was present when each individual lived in agreement with the universal laws of nature and with his individual nature. Gaius Laelius and Scipio had appeared at Off. 1.108 as an example of a contrast in the qualities of individual characters, the one lighter and the other more austere, as part of a list of contrasting moral temperaments originally supplied by Panaetius and subsequently edited by Cicero:

… in C. Laelio multa hilaritas, in eius familiari Scipione ambitio maior, vita tristior.

Cic. Off. 1.108

… Gaius Laelius was the most genial of men, but his close friend Scipio nursed greater ambition, and his life was more austere.Footnote 52

Brunt thought it plausible that Panaetius had referred to Laelius, a Roman he had personally educated in Stoic philosophy.Footnote 53 Although Cicero elsewhere attests to Panaetius’ instruction of Scipio and Laelius in Stoic doctrine (Cic. Mur. 66), it is not certain that Panaetius had referred to Laelius here. Nevertheless, the phrase ‘life more austere’ agrees with Panaetius’ conception of Scipio as a person who taught and practised restraint in success (Off. 1.90, 2.76). Ambition to live a ‘life more austere’ suggests a level of moral consistency aligning with a philosophical characterisation of a person influenced by the Stoic way of living. A ‘life more austere’ also aligned with Polybius’ comment about the impulse to virtue that was innate in the young Scipio and displayed in his early life.Footnote 54 Austerity was chosen as the theme appropriate for Scipio's funeral banquet and benches were covered with tatty goatskins and laid out with cheap crockery, more in keeping, we are told, with the death of a philosopher like Diogenes the Cynic than an eminent Roman.Footnote 55

The context for the fifth reference was the development of Panaetius’ roles theory, specifically the addition of the third role which is imposed by chance or circumstance, like inheritance (Off. 1.115–16):

Quorum vero patres aut maiores aliqua gloria praestiterunt, ii student plerumque eodem in genere laudis excellere, ut Q. Mucius P. f. in iure civili, Pauli filius Africanus in re militari. Quidam autem ad eas laudes quas a patribus acceperunt addunt aliquam suam, ut hic idem Africanus eloquentia cumulavit bellicam gloriam, quod idem fecit Timotheus Cononis filius, qui cum belli laude non inferior fuisset quam pater, ad eam laudem doctrinae et ingenii gloriam adiecit.

Cic. Off. 1.116

Those men whose fathers or forefathers have achieved glory in a specific field generally strive to excel in the same field themselves; for example, Quintus Mucius, son of Publius, in civil law, Africanus [Scipio Aemilianus], the son of [L. Aemilius] Paulus, in military affairs. Indeed, some sons add praise of their own to those distinctions inherited from their fathers; Africanus [Scipio Aemilianus] is again an example, he added eloquence to the glory gained in war, and similarly Timotheus, son of Conon, who was not inferior to his father in military renown, added the glory of his learning and intellectual ability to that renown.

Cicero's fifth reference featured Scipio's eloquence, which Cicero praised elsewhere (De or. 1.215; Brut. 82). Stoics were renowned as concise, restrained, and unadorned orators, and they distrusted appeals to the emotions of the audience. However, Panaetius also embraced oratory and probably was among the certain Stoics known to have included eloquence as a part of the virtue of wisdom (Cic. De or. 1.75, 3.65). Panaetius had commented directly on eloquence, a quality of language and a distinctive feature in humans. In a concession to the pragmatism of forensic oratory, he allowed eloquentia in the lawcourts a lower threshold than truth, the level of the plausible (Off. 2.48–51). The example of Scipio, son of Paulus at Off. 1.116, did fit the third role in the personae theory. Scipio had fulfilled what chance of birth and inheritance had bestowed, he had emulated the military renown of his natural father, and then excelled in eloquence. Scipio is compared with Timotheus (c. 444–392 BC), the Athenian general renowned for his learning (Cic. De or. 3.139). The synkrisis is appropriate in several ways. Scipio and Timotheus both practised restraint in victory; and, as Panaetius had accompanied and advised Scipio, so Isocrates accompanied and assisted Timotheus (Ps.-Plut. X. Orat. 837c).

The context for the sixth reference was a continuation of Panaetius’ roles theory and an elaboration on the fourth role which was the choice of career in life (Off. 1.117–21). The passage merely named Scipio as the ‘son of Paulus’ and instead focussed on his adoptive father P. Scipio, augur in 180 BC:

Sed quoniam paulo ante dictum est imitandos esse maiores, primum illud exceptum sit, ne vitia sint imitanda, deinde si natura non feret ut quaedam imitari possint (ut superioris filius Africani, qui hunc Paulo natum adoptavit, propter infirmitatem valetudinis non tam potuit patris similis esse quam ille fuerat sui), si igitur non poterit sive causas defensitare sive populum contionibus tenere sive bella gerere, illa tamen praestare debebit quae erunt in ipsius potestate, iustitiam fidem liberalitatem modestiam temperantiam, quo minus ab eo id quod desit requiratur.

Cic. Off. 1.121

But although I said a little earlier that we should imitate our ancestors, there are some exceptions, first, their faults must not be imitated; second, if our nature does not allow the possibility of imitating certain aspects. For example, [P. Scipio, augur 180 BC] the son of the elder Africanus who adopted [Scipio Aemilianus] the son of Paulus, could not, on account of ill-health, be like his father in the way the latter was like his father. If, therefore, someone is not able to plead cases for the defence or convince the people in public assemblies or wage wars, he will have to show the qualities which are within his power – justice, good faith, generosity, moderation, and self-restraint – to stop those in which he is deficient from being demanded of him.

During his lifetime, ill-health prevented P. Scipio (augur 180 BC) from imitating the actions of his own father but choice still lay within his power as a moral agent and he chose those virtues that lay within his capability – various forms of justice and self-control (iustitia, fides, liberalitas, modestia, and temperantia). This example also fits Panaetius’ roles theory as, although P. Scipio was unable to fulfil the role imposed by chance of birth and inheritance, he still exercised the choice to lead a virtuous life, leaving a version of the Stoic cardinal virtues as his legacy for his children to imitate.

These references to the Scipionic family at Off. 1.116 and 1.121 suggest interest in Scipio's lineage, through both the natural father L. Aemilius Paulus and the adoptive father P. Scipio. Brunt believed Panaetius was interested in and had written about Romans other than Scipio Aemilianus.Footnote 56 Erskine assigned the synkrisis of Scipio and P. Scipio Nasica Serapio at Off. 1.76 to around 129 BC when both had recently died, although this attribution is dependent on Pohlenz's dating of Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος.Footnote 57 Nasica was characterised elsewhere as upholding Stoic principles and being unaffected by the impulse to anger in acting against Tiberius Gracchus (Cic. Tusc. 4.51). In de Officiis, Cicero appears to have contrasted Nasica, and his unaffable conversation, with Xenocrates, the ‘severest of philosophers’ (Off. 1.109). Heumann deleted the phrase ne Xenocratem quidem severissimum philosophorum on the grounds that it was a mediaeval marginal annotation incompatible with the text's argument, and Winterbottom printed it in square brackets.Footnote 58 However, the phrase is compatible with the text's argument about the contrasting moral temperaments in men like Lysander and Callicratidas, Nasica and Xenocrates.

The context for the seventh reference to Scipio Aemilianus was the theme of service to the state and its citizenry, the safeguarding of property rights, and the contrast between ‘abstinence’ (abstinentia) and ‘avarice’ (avaritia) (Off. 2.72–85). Panaetius had supplied examples to illustrate a moral and political contrast between the abstinence of men like Scipio and the avarice of the Spartan reformers Lysander and Agis. Panaetius’ praise of Scipio survives in Cicero's Latin:

Laudat Africanum Panaetius quod fuerit abstinens. [Quidni laudet? Sed in illo alia maiora; laus abstinentiae non hominis est solum sed etiam temporum illorum. … Imitatus patrem Africanus nihilo locupletior Carthagine eversa.]

Cic. Off. 2.76

Panaetius praises Africanus because of his abstinence. [Why should he not praise him? But there were other greater virtues in him; and praise of abstinence belongs not only to that man, but also to his age … Africanus followed his father's example becoming no wealthier for his overthrow of Carthage.]

The text elaborated on Scipio's emulation of his natural father whose only profit from victory at Pydna was glory. Likewise, Scipio had not enriched himself at the fall of Carthage (146 BC), a fact that was well known at the time (Polyb. 18.35.9). The seventh reference is direct evidence of the moral quality Panaetius had found in Scipio. It is likely that the praise of the individual in this passage comes from Panaetius and the generalisation to the times is Cicero's addition, moralising about decline, although imitatus patrem Africanus nihilo locupletior Carthagine eversa might be a derivative of Panaetius’ explanation of why he had praised Scipio.Footnote 59 Panaetius will have agreed with Polybius (31.25.2–8; Diod. Sic. 31.26.6–31.27.1) who recorded that Scipio stood out in contrast to the prevailing ‘incontinence’ (ἀκρασία) of his age. Indeed, he may have used ἀκρασία as part of the contrast between self-control and its opposites (Off. 2.77). Panaetius’ praise of abstinentia related to the limiting influence displayed by the mind in its choice to restrain from acquisitiveness, and hence it was part of σωφροσύνη. The self-control shown here was associated with integrity in public life and moderation in victory, in both domestic and foreign fields.

Cicero alluded to Scipio on several occasions in Off. 1–2. He showed a lot of interest in Carthage and Numantia, the scenes of Scipio's two triumphs.Footnote 60 At the time of writing de Officiis in late 44 BC, the campaigns against these cities were long past and neither city posed a threat. However, the campaigns were topical in second-century-BC Rome. It is possible, but unprovable, that Panaetius had accompanied Scipio on campaign, as Polybius had done in 151, 149, 146, and probably 134–133 BC.Footnote 61 Panaetius had formulated an ethic of imperial power that identified utility with moral goodness and legitimised the waging of war.Footnote 62 In Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος, he had written on war and had drawn a distinction between enemies capable and incapable of ‘seeing reason’ and the harsher treatment that must be afforded to the latter (beluae, in Cicero's Latin).Footnote 63 He had devalued ἀνδρɛία in warfare as physical courage that did not require the mind's assent and could be exhibited by beastly men, and had replaced ἀνδρɛία with μɛγαλοψυχία which did require the power of the intellect. In de Officiis, there are references to Stoic foresight (πρόνοια) within the treatment of greatness of soul that allude to Scipio. Foresight is presented as the quality of the man of great soul in war who plans his moves and does not rush impulsively into battle like a beast (Off. 1.80–1). Focus rests on the power of the mind to anticipate events and plan for them, and never be forced to say, ‘I had not thought of it’ (non putaram). The historical Scipio placed his trust in foresight on campaign in Africa;Footnote 64 and he is reported to have thought it shameful to have to say the words non putaram (Val. Max. 7.2.2). Scipio had displayed foresight at Numantia in his cautious planning and anticipation of enemy moves, as explained by Rutilius Rufus, the Roman Stoic who served in this campaign and authored an autobiographical History (App. Hisp. 87–8). In another allusion to Scipio, Cicero's statement at Off. 2.43 that the Gracchi were not approved of by good men when they were alive and that their murder was justifiable aligns with the judgement publicly expressed by Scipio about the death of Tiberius Gracchus which was the cause of his unpopularity.Footnote 65

In summation, the evidence of de Officiis 1–2 shows Cicero presenting Scipio Aemilianus as transcending the way of living of a traditional Roman aristocrat: Scipio was unique in character and command; he conducted public affairs without bitterness; he was an example of a man of great soul who taught restraint in success and the perception of the variability of fortune; he lived an austere life true to his individual persona; he emulated his natural father in military renown and added excellence in eloquence as dictated by his circumstance; he fulfilled the legacy of his adoptive father in acquiring virtues of moderation and self-control; and he was a model of moral praiseworthiness for his abstinence. This philosophical characterisation of Scipio cannot be Cicero's creation alone, writing in 44 BC. Cicero had Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος in front of him and there is no doubt that Panaetius had referred to Scipio in this work as a Roman example of ‘greatness of soul’ (μɛγαλοψυχία).

οἰκɛίωσις and Scipio Aemilianus

The case for the derivation of a philosophical conception of Scipio from the second century BC is strengthened by corroborating evidence from beyond Cicero. Polybius, like Panaetius, was a friend, companion, and an eyewitness source to the life of Scipio. Later in life and after the death of Scipio in 129 BC, he added a digression to his Histories at 31.23–30 about Scipio's early life and education and about the role he himself played in the character formation of this Roman aristocrat.Footnote 66 In it, the elderly Greek reflected on his internment in Rome between 167–150 BC and the time he spent in the company of the young Scipio, before his departure and, around the same time, the arrival in Rome of his brilliant compatriot Panaetius. Here, as elsewhere, Polybius was anxious to praise the qualities of Scipio and omit the flaws.Footnote 67 He also appeared to have a personal interest in setting the record straight about the early role he played in forming young Scipio's character and his influence on this aristocrat's acquisition of virtue, prior to the advent of Panaetius.

Scipio, Polybius recalled,Footnote 68 was not yet eighteen and was already atypical for a Roman because of his natural impulse (ὁρμή) towards a virtuous life and his intention to excel all other reputations for ‘self-control’ (σωφροσύνη). Rejecting the ‘incontinence’ (ἀκρασία) of his contemporaries, young Scipio set out to control his passions, making his life ‘coherent’ (ὁμολογούμɛνος) and ‘harmonious’ (σύμφωνος). Within five years, according to Polybius, he gained renown for ‘self-control’ (σωφροσύνη) and ‘moderation’ (ɛὐταξία). As he continued on this course of life, he displayed ‘greatness of soul’ (μɛγαλοψυχία) and a ‘good and noble character’ (καλοκαγαθία) while furthering his renown for self-control and bravery. Polybius concluded that the reader now knew Scipio's achievements stemmed from the principles he acquired earlier in life.Footnote 69

Pohlenz drew attention to Polybius’ ethical terminology and specifically his use of ὁμολογούμɛνος – a Stoic word which expressed coherence, coordination, and consistency with λόγος in the course of life – and he noticed its resemblance to Panaetius’ language.Footnote 70 In his digression, Polybius explained how Scipio acquired two of the four cardinal virtues, σωφροσύνη and μɛγαλοψυχία (ἀνδρɛία), with self-control the unifying virtue in the intention to lead and to live a life of self-consistency. He had elsewhere (Polyb. 35.4) provided the same emphasis on these two cardinal virtues when praising Scipio's achievement of ‘self-control’ and ‘bravery’ in the Celtiberian War (152–151 BC). In de Officiis, all of the references to Scipio concern self-control (σωφροσύνη or the related πρέπον) and bravery (μɛγαλοψυχία). Polybius, therefore, provided the same accent on the same two virtues as that found in the references to Scipio in de Officiis.Footnote 71

In addition, Polybius’ summary of the stages of young Scipio's way of life aligns with the pattern of de Officiis. In Polybius (31.25.2–10), Scipio possesses the natural ‘impulse’ (ὁρμή) to the virtuous life, the intention to reject incontinence and to discipline the appetites, leading to a coherent and harmonious disposition in the course of life, and the acquisition of renown for ‘moderation’ and ‘self-control’ (ɛὐταξία and σωφροσύνη). In de Officiis, the natural ‘impulse’ (appetitus; ὁρμή) is directed to virtue under the guidance of reason, which disciplines the impulses and restrains their incontinence (1.11, 1.21, 1.100–3),Footnote 72 leading to self-consistency in the course of life and individual actions (aequabilitas universae vitae, 1.111, 1.119, 1.125), and to the realisation of ‘the fitting’ (πρέπον/σωφροσύνη) (Off. 1.142). Aequabilitas universae vitae is probably Cicero's understanding of ‘living in accordance with nature’ (ὁμολογουμένως τῇ φύσɛι ζῆν), that is living life consistent with concordant reason and being impervious to the vicissitudes of fortune.

Polybius did not claim to have been Scipio's instructor in philosophy and yet he used the language and concepts of Greek philosophy to describe him. Indeed, Polybius used concepts drawn from the Stoic doctrine of ‘appropriation’ (οἰκɛίωσις) and its theory of the moral development of humans in stages from primary impulse to the acquisition of the cardinal virtues and the undertaking of appropriate actions, from ὁρμή to λόγος refining ὁρμή, and a life lived in accord with concordant reason (ὁμολογούμɛνος, συμπονία) and virtue (ἀρɛτή), understood as φρόνησις, δικαιοσύνη, ἀνδρɛία and σωφροσύνη (Diog. Laert. 7.85–93; Cic. Fin. 3.16–26). The historian Polybius presents Scipio's intention to lead the life of self-consistency and restraint, independent of the vicissitudes of fortune, and in agreement with the telos of Stoic philosophy ‘living in accordance with nature’ (ὁμολογουμένως τῇ φύσɛι ζῆν). Panaetius had been Scipio's instructor in Stoic philosophy. When the historian Polybius eulogised young Scipio for his way of living, there is little doubt he had known the detail of the philosopher Panaetius’ conception of Scipio Aemilianus.Footnote 73

Conclusion

The natural disposition to virtue which exists in some men develops out of their self-regarding instinct for self-preservation and avoidance of harm and into their other-regarding choice to preserve justice and the bonds of human society and it is accompanied in the virtuous few by their acquisition of wisdom, justice, greatness of soul, and self-control. Reason allows man to refine his instincts, curb his passions, and lead a coherent and consistent life in thought and action. Panaetius was expert in οἰκɛίωσις doctrine and its account of man's moral development from the natural instincts and towards the end of ‘living in accordance with nature’. He had lowered his sights from the sage to the men making progress to virtue and adapted Stoic philosophy to the zeitgeist of the cultural mainstream and to the ideological imperatives of Roman conservatism. He had referenced examples to illustrate his moral instruction and his two directly attested references to Scipio from Πɛρὶ τοῦ καθήκοντος demonstrate his characterisation of Scipio Aemilianus as a model of exemplary leadership in philosophical terms. His eyewitness testimony is a Greek valuation of a Roman aristocrat. Panaetius had characterised Scipio as living the Stoic way of life, acquiring the cardinal virtues, and had referenced him explicitly as a Roman example of the man of great soul (μɛγαλόψυχος).

Acknowledgements

I thank Dr Kit Morrell, Dr Andrew Turner, and Associate Professor Kathryn Welch for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Footnotes

1 Cic. Tusc. 1.81, Rep. 1.15; Vell. Pat. 1.13.3. For Panaetius, see van Straaten (Reference Straaten1946); Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1949); Alesse (Reference Alesse1994); Vimercati (Reference Vimercati2004); Alesse (Reference Alesse2015).

2 Münzer (Reference Münzer1900: 1462): ‘In [Scipio] erscheint die harmonische Verbindung der Vorzüge des römischen Nationalcharakters mit denen der hellenischen Geistesanlage wirklich erreicht’.

3 Astin (Reference Astin1967); Drogula (Reference Drogula2019), with Morrell (Reference Morrell2021) and Volk (Reference Volk2021). For Stoic influences in Cato's character and career, see Morrell (Reference Morrell2017).

4 Barlow (Reference Barlow2018); (Reference Barlow2022). For a seminal study of Greek ethics and Roman statesmen, see Stone (Reference Stone, Stevenson and Wilson2008).

5 For Stoic conscience, see Sen. Clem. 1.1.1, 1.13.3; Sorabji (Reference Sorabji2015) 25–9; and, for Stoic advice to emperors and kings, see Sen. Clem. 2.5.2 and passim.

6 Ael. VH 2.20; Sen. Clem. 1.8.1; Braund (Reference Braund2009) 246.

7 e.g., Plut. Aem. 6.8–9, Ti. Gracch. 1–2, 8, 17, 20, C. Gracch. 19; Diod. Sic. 31.26.5; Cic. Brut. 77, Amic. 37.

8 Cic. Off. 1.4, 1.17, 1.46, 2.35, 3.15–16; Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1934) 92; Roskam (Reference Roskam2005) 33–45.

10 Cic. Fin. 3.57 (SVF 3, Antipater 55); Newman (Reference Newman and Fitch2008) 318–19.

11 Nicolet (Reference Nicolet1965) 156–7; Erskine (Reference Erskine1990) 160–1. For Stoic influences on Tiberius Gracchus, see Arena (Reference Arena2012) 157–60.

12 See, for example, the discussion in Most (Reference Most, Blair and Goeing2016).

14 Edelstein and Kidd (Reference Edelstein and Kidd1989) xvii–xxi.

15 Theiler (Reference Theiler1982).

16 Alesse (Reference Alesse1997) 9–12.

17 Vimercati (Reference Vimercati2002) 16–22.

19 Alesse (Reference Alesse1997) 160, 171, 235–6; Vimercati (Reference Vimercati2002) 245.

20 Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1934) 51–4, 113–26, 143–5. For a later publication date, see also Philippson (Reference Philippson1929) 338–9; Erskine (Reference Erskine1990) 158–61.

21 Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 21–36, 461–79; Long (Reference Long, Laks and Schofield1995). For an earlier publication date, see also Brunt (Reference Brunt, Brunt, Griffin and Samuels2013) 193, 241–2. Walsh (Reference Walsh2000: 181) remained uncommitted about the publication date.

22 Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 26, 383. Posidonius referenced Romans, including Scipio (Posid. fr. 254 EK).

23 Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 26–7, 233, 274, 289.

24 Lefèvre (Reference Lefèvre2001) 189–216.

26 Inwood (Reference Inwood2022) 565 (listing Off. 1.11–14, 1.15–20, 1.50–9, 1.93–103, 1.105–7, 1.110–15, 1.152, 2.18, 2.86, 2.88).

27 Cato appears once in Off. 1–2, at 1.112 and twice in Off. 3, at 3.66 and 3.88.

28 Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 18, 69, 97, 354–5.

29 Schmekel (Reference Schmekel1892) 356–78, 439–65; Long and Sedley (Reference Long and Sedley1987) Vol. 1, 429–37; Vol. 2, 423–31.

30 Off. 1.88–9, 1.124. For Panaetius on lawcourts, see Off. 2.51 and for Panaetius on public expenditure, see Off. 2.60.

31 For Cleomenes III, see Off. 1.33, with Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 132; Plut. Cleom. 17, Arat. 39. For Agis and Lysander, see Off. 2.79, with Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 462.

32 Lefèvre (Reference Lefèvre2001) 52, 121, 194.

34 See Nicolet (Reference Nicolet1965) 155–6; Hadot (Reference Hadot1970) 161–71, 178–9; Erskine (Reference Erskine1990) 158–61; Behrends (Reference Behrends, Avenarius and Möller2014) 62–4. For Blossius and his milieu, see Arena (Reference Arena2012) 158–65.

35 Barlow (Reference Barlow2018) 113–17; Welch (Reference Welch, Osgood and Baron2019) 101–4.

36 P. Rutilius Rufus (Cic. Rep. 1.13, 1.17, Brut. 85) and Q. Mucius Scaevola (Cic. Amic. 1) told Cicero about Scipio.

37 Welch (Reference Welch, Osgood and Baron2019) 97–8; for Scipio, see Welch (Reference Welch, Osgood and Baron2019) 100–1, citing Dio Cass. frs. 70.4–9. See also Cic. Amic. 69, De or. 2.154, Verr. 2.2.86; Plin. NH 7.100.

38 Brouwer (Reference Brouwer2021).

39 Cic. Off. 1.11–14 (Pan. fr. 98 van Straaten, fr. 55 Alesse, fr. B11 Vimercati; Dyck [1996] 83–6). See also Off. 1.53–54 on degrees of societas, 1.149 on conciliatio; Long and Sedley (Reference Long and Sedley1987) Vol. 1, 346–54; Vol. 2, 343–9. For οἰκɛίωσις, see, for example, Schofield (Reference Schofield, Laks and Schofield1995) 201–5; Vimercati (Reference Vimercati2007); Klein (Reference Klein2016).

40 Off. 1.62; Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 191–2. Atzert (Reference Atzert1963: 137) suggested ἐπιɛίκɛια for aequitas. For discussion of magnanimity in de Officiis, see Gill (Reference Gill and Vasalou2019) 59–68.

41 Off. 1.66; Pan. fr. 106 van Straaten, fr. 71 Alesse, fr. B20 Vimercati.

42 All translations my own unless otherwise indicated.

43 Although anti-Gracchan, Q. Metellus combined with obtrectatores … et invidi Scipionis (‘detractors and enemies of Scipio’) to oppose the granting of emergency powers to Scipio in 129 BC (Cic. Rep. 1.31).

44 Val. Max. 4.1.12; Plin. NH 7.144; Plut. Mor. 202A. For the quality of gentlemanly moderation, see Off. 1.96, 1.98–9, 1.141.

45 Pliny (NH 7.211) remarked that Scipio, rare for a Roman, was clean shaven. Alexander was clean shaven.

46 Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1934) 54. Off. 1.90, 2.53 commended Philip II for his facilitas (ɛὐκολία) and humanitas (φιλανθρωπία). The historical Philip II claimed to possess μɛγαλοψυχία (Polyb. 18.14.14) and ἐπιɛίκɛια and φιλανθρωπία in victory (Polyb. 5.10.1). Scipio claimed similar values. For Scipio's ἐπιɛίκɛια, see Dio Cass. fr. 70.9; for Scipio's φιλανθρωπία, see App. Pun. 133; and for Scipio's humanitas and aequitas, see Cic. Verr. 2.2.86, 2.4.81, De or. 2.154.

47 Translation by Griffin and Atkins (Reference Griffin and Atkins1991).

48 Alesse (Reference Alesse1997) 257–8, citing Pl. Phdr. 246 A–D. Alesse suggests that Panaetius may have drawn on Socratic literature for the metaphor of horse training, such as Xen. Mem. 2.3.7, 2.6.7, 4.1.3. On the other hand, Scipio himself was fond of referencing Xenophon.

49 Astin (Reference Astin1967) 25, 34, 268 (Dicta Scipionis 61), 298, n. 2.

50 Barlow (Reference Barlow2022) 29; cf. Long and Sedley (Reference Long and Sedley1987) Chs. 58, 61.

52 Translation by Walsh (Reference Walsh2000). For the translation of tristis as ‘solemn’ or ‘austere’, see Walsh (Reference Walsh2000) 37 and 147, citing OLD s.v. tristis 4b.

53 Brunt (Reference Brunt, Brunt, Griffin and Samuels2013) 192, n. 26. At Off. 1.108, hilaritas is present in Laelius and absent in Pythagoras and Pericles; at Off. 1.90, Laelius and Socrates shared imperturbability; and at Off. 2.40, wise Laelius overcame fierce Viriathus. For Panaetius’ education of Laelius, see Cic. Fin. 2.24 and Brut. 101; Pomp. Porphyr. Comm. in Horatii epist. 1.13–14; cf. Cic. Amic. 7–9, Off. 3.16.

54 Polyb. 31.25.2, 31.25.8–10, 31.28.10–13; Barlow (Reference Barlow2018) 116–17.

55 Cic. Mur. 75–6; Val. Max. 7.5.1; Sen. Ep. 95.72, 98.13; cf. Xen. Cyr. 8.7.25.

57 Erskine (Reference Erskine1990) 160.

58 Heumannus (Reference Heumannus1712) 35–6; Winterbottom (Reference Winterbottom1994) 45.

59 Cf. the two voices in the evaluation of L. Mummius. At Off. 2.76, Mummius was paired with Scipio and positive comment made about his moral restraint at Corinth in 146 BC, whereas, in editorial voice at Off. 1.35 and 3.46, Cicero adopted a negative tone towards Mummius.

60 For Carthage, see Off. 1.35, 1.38, 1.39, 2.76, 3.47, 3.99, 3.100. For Numantia, see Off. 1.35, 1.38 (Celtiberians), 1.76, 3.109.

61 Vell. Pat. 1.13.3. For the eastern embassy undertaken by Scipio, Panaetius, and a small entourage, see Mattingly (Reference Mattingly1986).

63 Off. 1.34, with Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1934) 31–3; Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 137–8; Brunt (Reference Brunt, Brunt, Griffin and Samuels2013) 204; Barlow (Reference Barlow2022) 32. For the interest shown by the philosopher Antiochus in the Battle of Tigranocerta, see Plut. Luc. 28.7.

64 App. Pun. 104; Polyb. 36.8.5; Dio Cass. fr. 70.8.

65 Cf. Cic. De or. 2.106, Mil. 8; Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 426.

66 Cf. Walbank (Reference Walbank1979) 492–3, 512.

67 Cf. Polyb. 35.4.8–14. For the pro-Scipio nature of the Polybian narratives, see Tweedie (Reference Tweedie and Welch2015).

68 Polyb. 31.24.4, 31.25.2–8; Diod. Sic. 31.26.5. See also Friedländer (Reference Friedländer and Friedländer1969) 323–6; Barlow (Reference Barlow2022) 33.

69 Polyb. 31.25.9, 31.26.9–10, 31.27.16, 31.28.11–13, 31.29.1, 31.29.11–12, 31.30.

70 Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1934) 111; see also Friedländer (Reference Friedländer and Friedländer1969) 325, 397, n. 4 (SVF 3.12, 3.197, 3.262, 3.293); Walbank (Reference Walbank1979) 501–2; Long and Sedley (Reference Long and Sedley1987) Vol. 1, 394–401; Vol. 2, 389–94; Polyb. 31.25.8, 31.28.11; Pan. fr. 109 van Straaten, fr. 54 Alesse, fr. A81 Vimercati.

71 Cf. Mohay (Reference Mohay, Szabo and Vargyas2008) who argues that Polybius’ notion of μɛγαλοψυχία is similar to Panaetius’ notion.

72 Cf. Off. 1.13–14, 1.132, 2.18.

73 Cf. Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 281. For ɛὐταξία as a part of σωφροσύνη in Stoic thought, see Diog. Laert. 7.126 (SVF 3.295); SVF 3.264; Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1934) 81–2; Dyck (Reference Dyck1996) 320. Scipio's favourite book (Cic. Q Fr. 1.1.23, Tusc. 2.62), Xenophon's Cyropaedia (2.1.22, 8.1.33), featured ɛὐταξία.

References

Alesse, F. (1994), Panezio di Rodi e la tradizione stoica. Naples.Google Scholar
Alesse, F. (1997), Panezio di Rodi. Testimonianze. Naples.Google Scholar
Alesse, F. (2015), ‘Panaetius of Rhodes’, Oxford Biographies: Classics. New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arena, T. (2012), Libertas and the Practice of Politics in the Late Roman Republic. Cambridge.Google Scholar
Astin, A. E. (1967), Scipio Aemilianus. Oxford.Google Scholar
Atzert, C. (ed.) (1963), M. Tulli Ciceronis De Officiis. 4th edn. Leipzig.Google Scholar
Barlow, J. (2018), ‘Scipio Aemilianus and Greek Ethics’, CQ 68, 112–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barlow, J. (2022), ‘Scipio Aemilianus and the Morality of Power’, Historia 71, 2750.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Behrends, O. (2014), ‘Tiberius Gracchus und die Juristen seiner Zeit – die römische Jurisprudenz gegenüber der Staatskrise des Jahres 133 v. Chr.’, in Avenarius, M. and Möller, C. (eds.), Okko Behrends: Zur römischen Verfassung. Göttingen, 1798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braund, S. (2009), Seneca: De Clementia. Oxford.Google Scholar
Brouwer, R. (2021), Law and Philosophy in the Late Roman Republic. Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brunt, P. A. (2013), ‘Panaetius in De Officiis’, in Brunt, P. A., Studies in Stoicism, ed. Griffin, M. and Samuels, A.. Oxford, 180242.Google Scholar
Drogula, F. K. (2019), Cato the Younger: Life and Death at the End of the Roman Republic. Oxford.Google Scholar
Dyck, A. R. (1996), A Commentary on Cicero, De Officiis. Ann Arbor.Google Scholar
Edelstein, L. and Kidd, I. G. (eds.) (1989), Posidonius I: The Fragments. 2nd edn. Cambridge.Google Scholar
Erskine, A. (1990), The Hellenistic Stoa: Political Thought and Action. London.Google Scholar
Friedländer, P. (1969), ‘Socrates Enters Rome’, in Friedländer, P., Plato 1: An Introduction. 2nd edn. Princeton.Google Scholar
Gill, C. (1993), ‘Panaetius on the Virtue of Being Yourself’, in Bulloch, A., Gruen, E. S., Long, A. A. and Stewart, A. (eds.), Images and Ideologies: Self-definition in the Hellenistic World. Berkeley, 330–53.Google Scholar
Gill, C. (1994), ‘Peace of Mind and Being Yourself: Panaetius to Plutarch’, ANRW II.36.7, 4599–640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gill, C. (2019), ‘Stoic Magnanimity’, in Vasalou, S. (ed.), The Measure of Greatness: Philosophers on Magnanimity. Oxford, 4971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, M. T. and Atkins, E. M. (eds.) (1991), Cicero: On Duties. Cambridge.Google Scholar
Hadot, I. (1970), ‘Tradition stoïcienne et idées politiques au temps des Gracques’, REL 48, 133–79.Google Scholar
Heumannus, C. A. (1712), Parerga critica. Jena.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. (2022), Later Stoicism 155 BC to AD 200: An Introduction and Collection of Sources in Translation. Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaerst, J. (1929), ‘Scipio Aemilianus, die Stoa und der Prinzipat’, Neue Jahrbücher für Wiss. und Jugendbildung 5, 653–75.Google Scholar
Klein, J. (2016), ‘The Stoic Argument from oikeiōsis’, OSAPh 50, 143200.Google Scholar
Lefèvre, E. (2001), Panaitios’ und Ciceros Pflichtenlehre: Vom philosophischen Traktat zum politischen Lehrbuch. Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (1995), ‘Cicero's Politics in De Officiis’, in Laks, A. and Schofield, M. (eds.), Justice and Generosity: Studies in Hellenistic Social and Political Philosophy. Cambridge, 213–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, A. A. and Sedley, D. N. (1987), The Hellenistic Philosophers. 2 Vols. Cambridge.Google Scholar
Mattingly, H. B. (1986), ‘Scipio Aemilianus’ Eastern Embassy’, CQ 36, 491–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mohay, G. (2008), ‘The Notion of Megalopsychia in Polybius’, Szabo, A. and Vargyas, P. (eds.), Cultus Deorum: Studia Religionum ad Historiam. Vol. II: De Rebus Aetatis Graecorum et Romanorum. In Memoriam István Tóth. Pécs, 888–97.Google Scholar
Morrell, K. (2017), Pompey, Cato, and the Governance of the Roman Empire. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrell, K. (2021), ‘Review of Fred K. Drogula: Cato the Younger, Life and Death at the End of the Roman Republic’, BMCRev.Google Scholar
Most, G. W. (2016), ‘The Rise and Fall of Quellenforschung’, in Blair, A. and Goeing, A-S (eds.), For the Sake of Learning: Essays in Honor of Antony Grafton. Leiden, 933–54.Google Scholar
Münzer, F. (1900), ‘P. Cornelius Scipio Aemilianus Africanus (no. 335)’, RE 7, 1439–62.Google Scholar
Newman, R. J. (2008), ‘In umbra virtutis: Gloria in the Thought of Seneca the Philosopher’, in Fitch, J. G. (ed.), Seneca. Oxford, 316–34.Google Scholar
Nicolet, C. (1965), ‘L'inspiration de Tibérius Gracchus (A propos d'un livre récent)’, REL 67, 142–58.Google Scholar
Philippson, R. (1929), ‘Panaetiana’, RhM 78, 337–60.Google Scholar
Pohlenz, M. (1934), Antikes Führertum: Cicero De Officiis und das Lebensideal des Panaitios. Leipzig/Berlin.Google Scholar
Pohlenz, M. (1949), ‘Panaitios’, RE 18.3, 418–40.Google Scholar
Roskam, G. (2005), On the Path to Virtue: The Stoic Doctrine of Moral Progress. Leuven.Google Scholar
Schmekel, A. (1892), Die Philosophie der mittleren Stoa in ihrem geschichtlichen Zusammenhange. Berlin.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1995), ‘Two Stoic Approaches to Justice’, in Laks, A. and Schofield, M. (eds.), Justice and Generosity: Studies in Hellenistic Social and Political Philosophy. Cambridge, 191212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schofield, M. (2012), ‘The Fourth Virtue’, in Nicgorski, W. (ed.), Cicero's Practical Philosophy. Notre Dame, 4357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorabji, R. (2015), Moral Conscience through the Ages: Fifth Century BCE to the Present. Oxford.Google Scholar
Stone, A. M. (2008), ‘Greek Ethics and Roman Statesmen: De Officiis and the Philippics’, in Stevenson, T. and Wilson, M. (eds.), Cicero's Philippics: History, Rhetoric, Ideology. Auckland, 214–39.Google Scholar
Straaten, M. van (1946), Panétius: sa vie, ses écrits et sa doctrine. Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Straaten, M. van (1962), Panaetii Rhodii fragmenta. 3rd edn. Leiden.Google Scholar
Theiler, W. (1982), Poseidonios: Die Fragmente. 2 Vols. Berlin.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tieleman, T. L. (2007), ‘Panaetius’ Place in the History of Stoicism: With Special Reference to his Moral Psychology’, in Ioppolo, A. M. and Sedley, D. N. (eds.), Pyrrhonists, Patricians, and Platonizers: Hellenistic Philosophy in the Period 155–86 BC. Naples, 104–42.Google Scholar
Tweedie, F. (2015), ‘Appian's Characterisation of Scipio Aemilianus’, in Welch, K. (ed.), Appian's Roman History: Empire and Civil War. Swansea, 169–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vimercati, E. (2002), Panezio: Testimonianze e frammenti. Milan.Google Scholar
Vimercati, E. (2004), Il Mediostoicismo di Panezio. Milan.Google Scholar
Vimercati, E. (2007), ‘Tre studi recenti sull’oikeiosis e sul fondamento della morale Stoica,’ RFN 4, 573608.Google Scholar
Visnjic, J. (2021), The Invention of Duty: Stoicism as Deontology. Leiden/Boston.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Volk, K. (2021), The Roman Republic of Letters: Scholarship, Philosophy, and Politics in the Age of Cicero and Caesar. Princeton.Google Scholar
Walbank, F. W. (1979), A Historical Commentary on Polybius. 3 Vols. Oxford.Google Scholar
Walsh, P. G. (2000), Cicero: On Obligations. Oxford.Google Scholar
Welch, K. (2019), ‘Cassius Dio and the Virtuous Roman’, in Osgood, J. and Baron, C. (eds.), Cassius Dio and the Late Roman Republic. Leiden, 97128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winterbottom, M. (ed.) (1994), M. Tulli Ciceronis: De Officiis. Oxford.Google Scholar