Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T07:22:15.457Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Two Currents in Contemporary English Political Theory*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 September 2013

Thomas P. Peardon
Affiliation:
Barnard College

Extract

There is widespread discontent today with the state of English political theory. This does not seem to have been so a generation ago. In 1915, Ernest Barker certainly revealed uneasiness about some intellectual tendencies of the time, but his overriding belief was that the new psychology and the new awareness of the personality of groups within society would enrich thinking in the long run. Ten years later, Lewis Rockow was distinctly optimistic at the end of his Contemporary English Political Thought. Having surveyed the first quarter of this century, he was impressed by “the richness of the contemporary mind” and the boldness of its political speculation. How different is the self-judgment of our own day. “In the present generation,” declared Professor Catlin in 1952, “England is in a poorer way as a fount of political ideas than she has been for centuries.” There were only a few men—Laski, Barker, Oakeshott, E. H. Carr—whom he would put in a high category, while apart from them he went on to say, “a drear darkness has fallen on British political theory which was so bright.” A little later, and speaking of the world in general rather than of England alone, Professor Cobban lamented “a general tendency to cease thinking about society in terms of political theory.” He could find no original thought since the eighteenth century and concluded that the idea of democracy had become a mere shibboleth—and not even a serviceable one, since all camps used it. He felt that the study of politics had taken a wrong turn, being corrupted by a neglect of the moral element, by an indifference to the practical problems besetting men, and by a deep pessimism about the possibility of resolving the dilemma between “moral man and immoral society.” Eric Voegelin seems at first to strike a more cheerful note when he speaks of “the revival, not to say the outburst, of political philosophy at Oxford in recent years,” but his article is critical of some of its tendencies and even goes so far at one point as to refer to its “distressing state.”

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1955

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Barker, Ernest, Political Thought in England from Herbert Spencer to the Present Day (New York, 1915), pp. 248–50Google Scholar.

2 Rockow, Lewis, Contemporary Political Thought in England (London, 1925), p. 294Google Scholar.

3 Catlin, George, “Contemporary British Political Thought,” this Review, Vol. 46, pp. 641–59, at p. 641 (Sept., 1952)Google Scholar.

4 Cobban, Alfred, “The Decline of Political Theory,” Political Science Quarterly, Vol. 68, pp. 321–37, at p. 322 (Sept., 1953)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Voegelin, Eric, “The Oxford Political Philosophers,” The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 3, pp. 97114 (April, 1953)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Carr, Edward H., The New Society (London, 1951), pp. 118Google Scholar.

7 Cambridge Journal, Vol. 1, p. 766 (Sept., 1948)Google Scholar, review of Smellie, K. B., Why We Read History (London. 1947)Google Scholar.

8 Oakeshott, Michael, “Rationalism in Politics,” Cambridge Journal, Vol. 1, pp. 145–57, at p. 147 (Dec., 1947)Google Scholar.

9 Ibid., p. 146.

10 Ibid., p. 146.

11 Oakeshott, Michael, “The Political Economy of Freedom,” Cambridge Journal, Vol. 2, p. 213 (Jan., 1949)Google Scholar.

12 Oakeshott, Michael, “Rational Conduct,” Cambridge Journal, Vol. 4, pp. 327, at p. 14 (Oct., 1950)Google Scholar.

13 Oakeshott, Michael, Political Education; An Inaugural Lecture Delivered at the London School of Economics and Political Science on March 6, 1951 (Cambridge, 1951), p. 25Google Scholar.

14 “Rationalism in Politics,” p. 153.

15 Cambridge Journal, Vol. 1, p. 326 (Feb., 1948)Google Scholar.

16 Political Education, p. 25.

17 Postan, Michael M., “The Revulsion from Thought,” Cambridge Journal, Vol. 1, pp. 395408 (April, 1948)Google Scholar.

18 Oakeshott, Michael, “Scientific Politics,” Cambridge Journal, Vol. 1, p. 354 (March, 1948)Google Scholar.

19 Political Education, p. 22.

20 Ibid., p. 28.

21 Weldon, T. D., The Vocabulary of Politics (Penguin Books, 1953), p. 97Google Scholar.

22 Ibid., p. 28.

23 Ibid., p. 192.

24 Weldon, T. D., States and Morals (New York, 1947), pp. 67Google Scholar.

Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.