Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T07:02:23.209Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Power of the Multitude: Answering Epistemic Challenges to Democracy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 September 2018

SAMUEL BAGG*
Affiliation:
McGill University
*
Samuel Bagg is a Postdoctoral Fellow with the Research Group on Constitutional Studies and the Department of Political Science at McGill University, 855 Sherbrooke St. West, Montréal, QC, Canada, H3A 2T7 ([email protected]).

Abstract

Recent years have witnessed growing controversy over the “wisdom of the multitude.” As epistemic critics drawing on vast empirical evidence have cast doubt on the political competence of ordinary citizens, epistemic democrats have offered a defense of democracy grounded largely in analogies and formal results. So far, I argue, the critics have been more convincing. Nevertheless, democracy can be defended on instrumental grounds, and this article demonstrates an alternative approach. Instead of implausibly upholding the epistemic reliability of average voters, I observe that competitive elections, universal suffrage, and discretionary state power disable certain potent mechanisms of elite entrenchment. By reserving particular forms of power for the multitude of ordinary citizens, they make democratic states more resistant to dangerous forms of capture than non-democratic alternatives. My approach thus offers a robust defense of electoral democracy, yet cautions against expecting too much from it—motivating a thicker conception of democracy, writ large.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

For valuable feedback and discussion on the themes of this article, I am very grateful to Arash Abizadeh, Aaron Ancell, Pablo Beramendi, Kevin Elliot, Michael Gillespie, Kelly Gordon, Ruth Grant, Jeffrey Green, Ewan Kingston, Jack Knight, Elizabeth Landesberg, Catherine Lu, Victor Muñiz-Fraticelli, Wayne Norman, Will Roberts, Amit Ron, Christa Scholtz, Melissa Schwartzberg, Lucas Swaine, Daniel Weinstock, and Yves Winter, as well as Leigh Jenco and several anonymous reviewers at the APSR.

References

REFERENCES

Acemoglu, Daron, and Robinson, James. 2012. Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty. New York: Crown Business.Google Scholar
Ancell, Aaron. 2017. “Democracy Isn't That Smart (but We Can Make It Smarter): On Landemore's Democratic Reason.” Episteme 14 (2): 161–75.Google Scholar
Achen, Christopher H., and Bartels, Larry M.. 2016. Democracy for Realists: Why Elections Do Not Produce Responsive Government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2007. “The Epistemology of Democracy.” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 3 (1): 822.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2008. “An Epistemic Defense of Democracy: David Estlund's Democratic Authority.” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 5 (1): 129–39.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2010. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 1993. “Democratic Rights at National and Workplace Levels.” In The Idea of Democracy, eds. Copp, David, Hampton, Jean, and Roemer, John. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 118–48.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2004. “Democracy Is Not Intrinsically Just.” In Justice and Democracy: Essays for Brian Barry, eds. Dowding, Keith, Goodin, Robert, and Pateman, Carole. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 4058.Google Scholar
Bagg, Samuel. 2016. “Between Critical and Normative Theory: Predictive Political Theory as a Deweyan Realism.” Political Research Quarterly 69 (2): 233–44.Google Scholar
Bagg, Samuel. 2017. “What Makes a Political Theory Political? A Comment on Waldron.” Political Studies Review. https://doi.org/10.1177/1478929917704815 (December 18, 2017).Google Scholar
Bagg, Samuel. 2018a. “Beyond the Search for the Subject: An Anti-Essentialist Ontology for Liberal Democracy.” European Journal of Political Theory OnlineFirst. https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885118763881 (March 29, 2018).Google Scholar
Bagg, Samuel. 2018b. “Can Deliberation Neutralise Power?European Journal of Political Theory 17 (3): 257–79.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles R. 1989. Political Equality: An Essay in Democratic Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bell, Daniel A. 2015. The China Model: Political Meritocracy and the Limits of Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bohman, James. 2006. “Deliberative Democracy and the Epistemic Benefits of Diversity.” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 3 (3): 175–91.Google Scholar
Brennan, Jason. 2016. Against Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Campbell, Angus, Converse, Philip E., Miller, Warren E., and Stokes, Donald E.. 1960. The American Voter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Caplan, Bryan. 2007. The Myth of the Rational Voter: Why Democracies Choose Bad Policies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 1996. The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Coulthard, Glen Sean. 2014. Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Crouch, Colin. 2004. Post-Democracy. Malden, MA: Polity.Google Scholar
Davis, Angela Y. 2012. The Meaning of Freedom: And Other Difficult Dialogues. San Francisco: City Lights Publishers.Google Scholar
Dietrich, Franz. 2008. “The Premises of Condorcet's Jury Theorem Are Not Simultaneously Justified.” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 5 (1): 5673.Google Scholar
Disch, Lisa. 2011. “Toward a Mobilization Conception of Democratic Representation.” American Political Science Review 105 (1): 100–14.Google Scholar
Dresden, Jennifer Raymond, and Howard, Marc Morjé. 2016. “Authoritarian Backsliding and the Concentration of Political Power.” Democratization 23 (7): 1122–43.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1996. Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
El Amine, Loubna. 2016. “Beyond East and West: Reorienting Political Theory through the Prism of Modernity.” Perspectives on Politics 14 (1): 102–20.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 1994. “Opinion Leaders, Independence, and Condorcet's Jury Theorem.” Theory and Decision 36 (2): 131–62.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Foa, Roberto Stefan, and Mounk, Yascha. 2016. “The Democratic Disconnect.” Journal of Democracy 27 (3): 517.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2009. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fuerstein, Michael. 2008. “Epistemic Democracy and the Social Character of Justification.” Episteme 5 (1): 7493.Google Scholar
Fukuyama, Francis. 2014. Political Order and Political Decay: From the Industrial Revolution to the Globalization of Democracy. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Galston, William. 2010. “Realism in Political Theory.” European Journal of Political Theory 9 (4): 385411.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 1997. “Does Democracy Reveal the Voice of the People? Four Takes on Rousseau.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75 (2): 141–62.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 2011. “On Seeking the Truth (Whatever That Is) through Democracy: Estlund's Case for the Qualified Epistemic Claim.” Ethics 121 (2): 270300.Google Scholar
Gramsci, Antonio. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks, eds. Hoare, Quintin and Smith, Geoffrey Nowell. New York: International Publishers.Google Scholar
Green, Jeffrey Edward. 2009. The Eyes of the People: Democracy in an Age of Spectatorship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Green, Jeffrey Edward. 2016. The Shadow of Unfairness: A Plebeian Theory of Liberal Democracy. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, Christopher G. 2003. “Democracy as a Non–Instrumentally Just Procedure.” Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (1): 111–21.Google Scholar
Grofman, Bernard, and Feld, Scott L.. 1988. “Rousseau's General Will: A Condorcetian Perspective.” The American Political Science Review 82 (2): 567–76.Google Scholar
Guerrero, Alexander A. 2014. “Against Elections: The Lottocratic Alternative.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (2): 135–78.Google Scholar
Hayward, Clarissa Rile. 2013. How Americans Make Race: Stories, Institutions, Spaces. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Healy, Andrew, and Malhotra, Neil. 2013. “Retrospective Voting Reconsidered.” Annual Review of Political Science 16 (1): 285306.Google Scholar
Hong, Lu, and Page, Scott E.. 2004. “Groups of Diverse Problem Solvers Can Outperform Groups of High-Ability Problem Solvers.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 101 (46): 16385–9.Google Scholar
Hualing, Fu. 2015. “Wielding the Sword: President Xi's New Anti-Corruption Campaign.” In Greed, Corruption and the Modern State: Essays in Political Economy, eds. Rose-Ackerman, Susan and Lagunes, Paul. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar Publishing, 134–59.Google Scholar
Hui, Victoria Tin-bor. 2015. “The Protests and Beyond.” Journal of Democracy 26 (2): 111–21.Google Scholar
Hui, Victoria Tin-bor. 2016. “Contribution to Symposium on Bell's China Model.” Perspectives on Politics 14 (1): 150–1.Google Scholar
Humphrey, Mathew. 2007. Ecological Politics and Democratic Theory: The Challenge to the Deliberative Ideal. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ingham, Sean. 2013. “Disagreement and Epistemic Arguments for Democracy.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 12 (2): 136–55.Google Scholar
Issacharoff, Samuel, and Pildes, Richard H.. 1998. “Politics as Markets: Partisan Lockups of the Democratic Process.” Stanford Law Review 50 (3): 643717.Google Scholar
Jenco, Leigh. 2016. “Contribution to Symposium on Bell's China Model.” Perspectives on Politics 14 (1): 152–3.Google Scholar
Kirshner, Alexander S. 2014. A Theory of Militant Democracy: The Ethics of Combatting Political Extremism. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Knight, Jack, and Johnson, James. 2011. The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kolodny, Niko. 2014. “Rule Over None I: What Justifies Democracy?Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (3): 195229.Google Scholar
Landemore, Hélène. 2012. Democratic Reason: Politics, Collective Intelligence, and the Rule of the Many. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Landemore, Hélène, and Elster, Jon, eds. 2012. Collective Wisdom: Principles and Mechanisms. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Levinson, Daryl J., and Pildes, Richard H.. 2006. “Separation of Parties, Not Powers.” Harvard Law Review 119 (8): 2311–86.Google Scholar
Levitsky, Steven, and Way, Lucan A.. 2010. Competitive Authoritarianism: Hybrid Regimes after the Cold War. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Levitsky, Steven, and Ziblatt, Daniel. 2018. How Democracies Die. New York: Crown.Google Scholar
Lindsey, Brink, and Teles, Steven. 2017. The Captured Economy: How the Powerful Enrich Themselves, Slow Down Growth, and Increase Inequality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
List, Christian, and Goodin, Robert E.. 2001. “Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem.” Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (3): 277306.Google Scholar
Lodge, Milton, and Charles, S. Taber. 2013. The Rationalizing Voter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 2013. Studying Human Behavior: How Scientists Investigate Aggression and Sexuality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mantena, Karuna. 2012. “Another Realism: The Politics of Gandhian Nonviolence.” American Political Science Review 106 (02): 455–70.Google Scholar
Marks, Jonathan. 2009. Why I Am Not a Scientist: Anthropology and Modern Knowledge. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
McNamee, Stephen J., and Miller, Robert K.. 2013. The Meritocracy Myth (3rd ed.). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.Google Scholar
Medearis, John. 2015. Why Democracy Is Oppositional. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Medina, José. 2012. The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Misak, Cheryl. 2008. “A Culture of Justification: The Pragmatist's Epistemic Argument for Democracy.” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 5 (1): 94105.Google Scholar
Nathan, Andrew. 2016. “Contribution to Symposium on Bell's China Model.” Perspectives on Politics 14 (1): 154–5.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C., Wallis, John Joseph, and Weingast, Barry R.. 2009. Violence and Social Orders: A Conceptual Framework for Interpreting Recorded Human History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 2008. Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ong, Lynette. 2016. “Contribution to Symposium on Bell's China Model.” Perspectives on Politics 14 (1): 156–7.Google Scholar
Oppenheimer, Danny, and Edwards, Mike. 2012. Democracy Despite Itself: Why a System That Shouldn't Work at All Works So Well. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2013. On the People's Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Phulwani, Vijay. 2016. “The Poor Man's Machiavelli: Saul Alinsky and the Morality of Power.” American Political Science Review 110 (4): 863–75.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam. 1991. Democracy and the Market: Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam. 1999. “Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense.” In Democracy's Value, eds. Shapiro, Ian and Hacker-Cordon, Casiano. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam. 2005. “Democracy as an Equilibrium.” Public Choice 123 (3–4): 253–73.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam. 2010. Democracy and the Limits of Self-Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rahman, K. Sabeel. 2016. Democracy against Domination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schwartzberg, Melissa. 2015. “Epistemic Democracy and Its Challenges.” Annual Review of Political Science 18 (1): 187203.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999. “Democracy as a Universal Value.” Journal of Democracy 10 (3): 3–17.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 2003. The State of Democratic Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 2016. Politics against Domination. Cambridge: Belknap.Google Scholar
Somin, Ilya. 2013. Democracy and Political Ignorance: Why Smaller Government Is Smarter (1st ed.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Somin, Ilya. 2015. The Grasping Hand: “Kelo v. City of New London” and the Limits of Eminent Domain. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Stout, Jeffrey. 2012. Blessed Are the Organized: Grassroots Democracy in America. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. 1987. “Lochner's Legacy.” Columbia Law Review 87 (5): 873919.Google Scholar
Svolik, Milan. n.d. “When Polarization Trumps Civic Virtue: Partisan Conflict and the Subversion of Democracy by Incumbents.” Working Paper, Yale University.Google Scholar
Tan, Kenneth Paul. 2008. “Meritocracy and Elitism in a Global City: Ideological Shifts in Singapore.” International Political Science Review 29 (1): 727.Google Scholar
Thompson, Abigail. 2014. “Does Diversity Trump Ability? An Example of the Misuse of Mathematics in the Social Sciences.” Notices of the American Mathematical Society 61 (9): 1024–30.Google Scholar
Tilly, Charles. 2007. Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Van Hees, Martin. 2007. “The Limits of Epistemic Democracy.” Social Choice and Welfare 28 (4): 649–66.Google Scholar
Viehoff, Daniel. 2014. “Democratic Equality and Political Authority.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (4): 337–75.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1995. “The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics.” Political Theory 23 (4): 563–84.Google Scholar
Wall, Steven. 2007. “Democracy and Equality.” The Philosophical Quarterly 57 (228): 416–38.Google Scholar
Warren, Mark. 2011. “Voting with Your Feet: Exit-Based Empowerment in Democratic Theory.” The American Political Science Review 105 (4): 683701.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 2005. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, ed. Hawthorn, G.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
X, Malcolm. 1964. The Ballot or the Bullet. Speech, Cory Methodist Church in Cleveland, OH. April 3, 1964.Google Scholar
Yuen, Samson. 2014. “Disciplining the Party: Xi Jinping's Anti-Corruption Campaign and Its Limits.” China Perspectives 2014 (2014/3): 41–7.Google Scholar
Zaller, John. 1992. The Nature and Origins of Mass Opinion. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.